Getting Real: Ockham on the Human Contribution to the Nature and Production of Artifacts
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Ockham’s Reductionist Ontology of Artifacts
[W]e should know that when the artisan works to produce artificial things, he does not produce an absolute form that inheres in a natural thing […], with the result that when a house, an image, a statue, a bed, and the like are made, there is no new thing produced in its entirety.
When some contradictories can be verified of the same thing, either one must posit the destruction or production of a thing or local motion. And so, when contradictories of this sort can be successively verified [of the same thing] merely on account of local motion alone, it is not necessary to posit such an absolute thing.
And so, when a house comes to be nothing real is newly produced in its entirety. Rather, a house is said to come to be when its parts are changed only with respect to place and they are spatially ordered in a determinate way.
For this reason, we ought to say that artificial things do not come to be through the production of a new thing. Rather, in order for artificial things to be produced, it is sufficient to spatially move the same thing or it is sufficient to bring diverse natural things closer together in a certain way or [it is sufficient to] separate them spatially.
3. The Human Contribution, Part One: The Efficient Cause of Artifacts
4. The Human Contribution, Part Two: The Final Cause of Artifacts
[…] artifacts have proper functions that they are (intentionally) designed and produced to perform (whether they perform their proper functions or not) […] a proper function is a purpose or use intended by a producer […] Thus, an artifact has its proper function essentially: the nature of an artifact lies in its proper function—what it was designed to do, the purpose for which it was produced.[21] (p. 102)
She thinks that this act of conversion is insufficient to explain what artifacts are and how they come to exist. In the case of houses and statues, Ockham would surely agree. After all, we saw in the previous section that he holds artistic production to be an instance of real change on the side of the object, the natural thing(s) or its parts that are spatially rearranged by the artisan, and this is what accounts for the existence of the artifact. However, this does not happen in the bath case, where there is no real change on the side of the volume of water that our bather decides to use for the sake of cleaning herself. We would be understandably reluctant to admit that this could be an instance of artistic production.[…] is it possible to create a new artifact simply by ‘converting’ a piece of driftwood into a bench? If so, then apparently a process can qualify as an intentional making or producing, even if no physical work is required on the part of the agent responsible […] and the underlying material from which the new artifact is apparently made […] need not undergo any intrinsic change.[23] (p. 218)
5. Ends and Functions
Contrary to Henry, Ockham thinks that the student’s end is transmitted to the science she acquires, so we can say the end of the science is determined by the end of the student. To use the terminology I have adopted here, the purpose of the scientist fixes the function of the science.[…] I claim that the end of scientific knowledge properly speaking is that which, being loved by the student […], moves him to learn and to acquire that scientific knowledge. Therefore, the very same thing is without qualification the final cause of the scientist and scientific knowledge.
6. Conclusions
Funding
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | See [1,2] for introductions to Ockham’s view of artifacts. In [3], Majcherek focuses on “Ockham’s master argument concerning artefacts made by composition” (p. 114), which I discuss in far less detail here. The ontology of artifacts is the subject of Majcherek’s unpublished PhD dissertation in which Ockham figures prominently. Majcherek generously sent me a copy of his dissertation while I was in the process of revising this paper, which I have only been able to look at cursorily. |
2 | For a contemporary account of artifacts that likewise emphasizes their dependency on the intentions of their makers and how relevant this is for their metaphysical status and constitution, see [4]. Thomasson argues that “[…] the mind-dependence of artifacts and artifactual kinds should in no way be taken to interfere with accepting that such entities exist” (p. 54). |
3 | This qualification is important in order to avoid the suggestion that Ockham admits modes in his ontology, since this is far from clear. On the status of modes, especially as opposed to accidents, in medieval and into early modern philosophy, see [5,6] (pp. 244–275). For Ockham in particular, see [7] (esp. pp. 181–182). |
4 | I am indebted to the current research as yet unpublished by Susan Brower-Toland on Ockham, ontological commitment, metaphysical explanation, and what she calls the “difference-making principle”. The distinction between what things exist as opposed to how those things exist is one that she evokes and I owe this formulation to her (but also see [7] (e.g., p. 179). She defends her interpretation in both [8,9]. |
5 | Ref. [10] (II, c. 1, p. 217, ll. 31–37): “[…] est primo sciendum quod quando artifex operatur producendo artificialia, non producit aliquam formam absolutam inhaerentem rei naturali […] ita quod quando fit domus vel idolum vel statua vel lectus et huiusmodi, non est aliqua res de novo secundum se totam producta”. Cf. [11] (I, c. 20, p. 209, ll. 10–11). All translations are my own unless otherwise stated. |
6 | Ref. [11] (I, c. 20, pp. 208–209, ll. 4–5): “[…] forma artificialium est forma accidentalis distincta a materia et sibi per artem adveniens […]”. |
7 | Ref. [11] (I, c. 20, p. 209, ll. 7–9): “[…] est hic nunc breviter disserendum an forma rei artificialis sit secundum se totam distincta a qualibet re naturali”. |
8 | For a short history of the razor with references to some of the main literature, see [13]. |
9 | Ref. [14] (q. 118, p. 716, ll. 8–13): “Ad istam quaestionem [utrum possit sufficienter probari quod artificialia addant aliquid super naturalia], dico breviter quod non. Cuius ratio est quia haec propositio ‘artificialia aliquid addunt super naturalia’ non est per se nota, quia multi dubitant de ea. Nec potest probari ex per se notis, quia in omni ratione probante accipitur aliquod falsum vel dubium multiplex. Nec est nota per experientiam—manifestum est; igitur etc.”. |
10 | But as Susan Brower-Toland has pointed out in private correspondence, we could provide other arguments whose premises include principles that are not self-evident (per se nota) to establish that the claim “artificial things add something over and above natural things” is true. |
11 | Ref. [10] (II, c. 1, p. 226, ll. 340–344): “[…] quando aliqua contradictoria possunt successive circa idem verificari, vel oportet ponere corruptionem vel productionem alicuius rei vel motum localem. Et ideo quando talia contradictoria possunt successive verificari propter solum motum localem, non oportet ponere talem rem absolutam”. |
12 | For a clear analysis and defense of this argument in context, including reactions to it by Walter Burley and Paul of Venice, see [3] (starting at p. 119). |
13 | Ref. [14] (q. 119, p. 720, ll. 33–37): “Quod probatur, quia quando fit domus, quaero: aut illa forma domus est tota in toto subiecto praeexsistente et tota in quaelibet parte, aut est tota in toto et pars in parte. Non primo modo, quia nullum accidens materiale potest esse in toto extenso et in qualibet parte secundum se totum”. In the Summula, Ockham countances a third way that the house form could exist in its subject, namely as existing only in the artificial part (parte artificiati) of the house, [11] (q. 20, p. 209, l. 20). This option does not not appear in either the Expositio or the Quaestiones version of the argument and Ockham does not bother to argue against it the Summula. Perhaps he thought this option begs the question insofar as it suggests that there already is an artificial part of the house, and what could this be other than the artificial form the existence of which is precisely what the argument is supposed to settle? |
14 | Ref. [14] (q. 119, p. 720, ll. 37–40): “Si secundo modo, aut igitur quaelibet pars praefuit in suo subiecto, ita quod una pars illius artificialis praefuit in lignis domus, alia in lapidibus, et sic de aliis partibus domus, aut quaelibet pars de novo est in suo subiecto”. Translation with modification from [3] (p. 121). |
15 | Ref. [14] (q. 119, p. 720, ll. 40–45): “Si detur primum, habetur propositum quod quando domus est de novo nulla res est res nova absoluta quin quaelibet pars eius prius fuerit. Non potest dari secundum, quia tunc quandocumque fieret domus, oporteret quod quilibet lapis et quodlibet lignum ex quibus fit domus haberet in se formam unam absolutam quam prius non habuit. Quod falsum est”. |
16 | Ref. [14] (q. 119, p. 720, ll. 45–51): “Quod falsum est: tum quia iste lapis in nullo mutatur nisi secundum locum, quia possibile est quod non incidatur in aliquo nec etiam aliquo modo mutetur nisi secundum locum; tum quia possibile est quod lapis non mutatus secundum locum concurrat ad constitutionem domus, et tunc non habet novam substantiam, nec novam quantitatem vel qualitatem, nec novam figuram, et per consequens nullum novum absolutum in se recipit”. |
17 | Ref. [10] (II, c. 1, p. 218, ll. 77–80): “Et per consequens quando domus fit, non est aliquid reale secundum se totum de novo productum; sed ideo dicitur domus fieri, quia partes tantum secundum locum transmutantur et modo determinato localiter ordinantur”. |
18 | Ref. [10] (II, c. 1, p. 219, ll. 102–105): “Ideo dicendum est quod non fiunt artificialia per talem productionem novae rei, sed ad producendum artificialia sufficit movere localiter idem vel sufficit diversa naturalia modo certo approximare localiter vel separare aliqua localiter”. |
19 | Ref. [11] (I, c. 19, p. 206, ll. 38–43): “Sed ad artificialibus est aliud [from natural composite substances], quia una pars potest manere distincta ab alia, ita quod partes possunt simul esse in rerum natura quamvis non sint unitae, ideo illud totum non semper et necessario est illae partes exsistentes, sed tunc solum est illae partes exsistentes quando partes sunt debito modo unitae et localiter situatae et convenienter”. For further discussion on the importance of ordering for aggregates in general, including complex artifacts and social groups, see [18]. |
20 | Ref. [11] (I, c. 19, pp. 206–207, ll. 43–49): “Quando autem sunt separatae vel inconvenienter ordinatae secundum locum, tunc totum, puta domus, non est illae partes; et quia hoc est possibile quod illae partes manentes sint quandoque debite ordinatae et situatae et quandoque a se divisae, ideo haec est vera quandoque ‘domus est illae partes’ et quandoque est falsa; tamen quandocumque illae partes sunt debito modo ordinatae secundum locum, tunc domus est illae partes”. |
21 | Ockham accepts exceptions. He distinguishes between arts that work with nature to produce a new form and arts that do not, like building houses, painting images, and carving statues. Arts of the first kind consist in facilitating a natural process by moving natural things into sufficient proximity so that their active and passive causal powers produce some new substantial or accidental form. His examples are medicine and agriculture. See [14] (q. 119, p. 719, ll. 11–14) and [11] (I, c. 20, p. 209, ll. 13–16). On this, see [3] (pp. 111–112). |
22 | Ref. [10] (II, c. I, pp. 213–214, ll. 25–31): “Circa primam partem primo dividit factibilia et exemplificat de uno membro, dicens quod de numero entium quae sunt factibilia, quaedam fiunt ex natura, hoc est naturaliter, alia autem a casu, alia autem propter alias causas. Et exemplificat de illis quae sunt natura. Quia omnia animalia et omnes partes eorum, similiter plantae et corpora simplicia cuiusmodi sunt terra, ignis, aer, et aqua, dicimus esse et fieri natura, hoc est omnia illa sunt naturalia. Intelligendum est quod Philosophus intendit istam divisionem quod quaedam sunt artificialia et quaedam naturalia”. |
23 | Ref. [10] (II, c. 1, p. 214, ll. 35–37): “Secundo sciendum est quod Philosophus per ‘alias causas’ intelligit artem et voluntatem, hoc est actus intelligendi et actum volendi, quia mediantibus istis homo operatur”. It is important to point out that Ockham immediately qualifies his claim to include agents who make things by means of some cognition (per cognitionem), which is meant to extend to non-rational agents like birds building nests. Nests are not naturally producible things but are produced through the sensory cognition and appetitive desires of birds. This being said, Ockham tends to imply that artifacts are produced by human artisans, since he cites their intellectual and volitional acts. The latter act is simply unavailable to non-rational animals who lack the requisite rational soul to be able to perform them. |
24 | For a recent article on Ockham’s conception of craft, see [19]. |
25 | |
26 | Ref. [14] (q. 118, p. 717, ll: 27–31): “Ad primum istorum [objections] dico quod generatio accipitur dupliciter: uno modo pro generatione alicuius rei novae secundum se totam, et ista potest dici generatio simpliciter, si ista res prius non fuit, et talis generatio semper est per adquisitionem alicuius rei novae”. |
27 | Ref. [14] (q. 118, p. 717, ll: 31–34): “Aliter accipitur pro transformatione aliqua reali qua res fit aliqualis qualis prius non fuerat, ita quod propter talem transformationem realem possit formari propositio de novo vera qua denotatur res talis esse, et ista vocatur generatio secundum quid”. |
28 | Ref. [14] (q. 118, p. 717, ll: 34–36): “Et ad talem generationem non requiritur nova res secundum se totam, sed sufficit transmutatio localis aliquorum vel alicuius”. |
29 | Ref. [14] (q. 118, p. 717, ll. 43–48): “Et propter illam transmutationem localem formatur ista propositio de novo vera ‘ista naturalia sunt domus’, hoc est ista naturalia sunt taliter coniuncta localiter. Similiter per talem transmutationem verificatur ista propositio ‘domus est’, quae aequivalet isti ‘istae res naturales sunt taliter coniunctae localiter’; quae nunc est vera et prius non erat vera”. |
30 | Majcherek discusses these three modes briefly but not exclusively in Ockham, and notes that this third mode of artistic production is the process of molding, citing the example of melting down iron to make a sword [3] (p. 114). |
31 | Ref. [14] (q. 118, p. 717, ll. 36–43): “Primo modo loquendo de generatione [unqualified generation], sic artificialia quae fiunt per substractionem, sicut figura concisa, vel per compositionem, sicut domus, vel per transfigurationem, sicut virgo depicta, non generantur, quia in productione talium nulla res nova secundum se producitur. Sed loquendo secundo modo de generatio [qualified generation], sic artificialia generantur, quia ibi nova res non producitur sed tantum novus locus adquiritur, eo quod res sunt in aliquo loco in quo prius non fuerunt”. The same three modes with examples are repeated throughout [14] (q. 119, pp. 719–721) and [10] (II, c. 1, p. 217, ll. 41–49). The two types of generation and the verification of sentences are also discussed in [10] (II, c. 1, p. 220, ll. 130–148). |
32 | Ref. [11] (I, c. 20, p. 210, ll. 40–43): “Contra istam opinionem potest multipliciter argui: primo, quia artificialia distinguuntur a rebus naturalibus; sed si nulla res nova esset, quaelibet res esset naturalis, et ita nulla esset distinctio inter naturalia et artificialia”. Cf. [14] (q. 118, p. 717, ll. 20–22). |
33 | Ref. [14] (q. 122, p. 726, ll. 34–40): “[…] dico quod de virtute sermonis omnes istae propositiones sunt concendendae […] ‘naturalia sunt artificialia’, ‘aes est statua’, ‘lignum est lectus’, et omnes consimiles”. |
34 | |
35 | Ref. [11] (I, c. 20, p. 211, ll. 60–62): “[…] per talem propositionem ‘res artificialis non est res naturalis’, intendit [Aristotle] dicere quod talis res non est naturaliter talis qualis fit per artem”. |
36 | Ref. [11] (I, c. 20, p. 211, ll. 65–74): “Similiter aqua non est naturaliter balneum, sed aqua per artem fit balneum; et tamen hoc non obstante nulla res est balneum vel in balneo nisi res naturalis: in nullo enim differt aqua ista ab alia aqua nisi quia habet calorem vel quia miscetur cum herbis vel quia est in aliquo loco determinato, quae omnia nullam rem aliam dicunt in illa aqua a re naturali. Unde si poneretur aqua in aliquo loco et postea per naturam fieret calida, totum esset naturale et esset balneum, et tamen in nullo distingueretur ab alio quod per artem fit balneum, sicut quaedam dicuntur balnea naturalia et quaedam artificialia”. |
37 | Ref. [11] (I, c. 20, p. 211, ll. 74–78): “Quamvis forte aliquo modo diversificentur, tamen si in nullo diversificarentur nisi quantum ad agens extrinsecum, puta quod unum fit a natura et aliud non fit balenum nisi arte et voluntate concurrente, vere unum diceretur balenum naturale et aliud artificiale, hoc est una aqua fit balenum naturaliter et alia artificialiter”. |
38 | I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for pressing me on my interpretation. In [22] I discuss the role of ends and final causality in connection to human (intentional) action. There, I argue that, in effect, whenever we decide to use some external object (e.g., a volume of water!), we are doing so for the sake of some end that we desire. We choose to deploy our expertise and we decide to use external objects for a purpose, which stands as a reason—a desire—for why we act the way that we do. |
39 | Pasnau’s interest is the ontological status of final causes, not the one that I am making here. See [24] (pp. 98–99). |
40 | |
41 | |
42 | Ref. [28] (Prologue, q. 11, p. 307, ll: 1–5): “[…] dico quod finis scientiae proprie loquendo est illud quod amatum ab addiscente […], movet ipsum ad discendum et ita ad adquirendum scientiam. Et ideo idem est simpliciter finis quae est causa finalis scientis et scientiae […]”. Cf. [11] (II, c. 5, p. 226, ll. 19–21). |
43 | The whole argument reads: [28] (Prologue, q. 11, p. 305, ll: 17–24): “[…] illud a quo res dependet essentialiter, ita quod sine illo res non haberet esse reale, videtur esse causa essentialiter illius rei. Sed a fine scientis dependet ipsa scientia realiter et essentialiter, quia sine illo simpliciter non foret. Sicut ponatur quod aliquis non addisceret scientiam speculativam nisi propter lucrum vel propter aliquid tale: nisi ille tunc hoc intenderet simpliciter nihil foret illa scientia. Igitur illud habet rationem a causae, et nonnisi rationem causae finalis; ergo etc.”. |
44 | Ref. [28] (Prologue, q. 11, pp. 304–305, ll. 21–26): “[…] idem est finis agentis, hoc est intentus ab agente, et actionis suae […], quia omnis finis cuiuscumque actionis est finis intentus. Aut ergo ab isto agente a superiori dirigente illud agens inferius, sicut in naturalibus idem est finis agentium inferiorum et intelligentiae dirigentis. Et a quocumque intendatur, sequitur quod idem sit finis agentis, hoc est intentus ab agente, et actionis suae”. |
45 | On a teleological explanation of human acts, see [22]. |
46 | See [29] (p. 147) on the distinction between intrinsic and derivative final causality in Ockham. |
47 | Ref. [11] (II, c. 6, p. 228, ll. 25–32): “Propter quod videndum est quomodo respectu inanimatorum est causa finalis. De quo videtur mihi esse dicendum quod, secundum principia Aristotelis, si inanimata a nullo cognoscente finem regantur seu moveantur, quod in eis non est causa finalis, quia tunc sunt mere agentia ex necessitate naturae nihil proprie intendentia. Si autem regantur a cognoscente et desiderante, in illis ponenda est causa finalis, quae cause finalis non est proprie intenta nec desiderata ab agente inanimato sed a dirigente vel movente”. |
48 | Ref. [11] (II, c. 6, p. 228, ll. 32–36): “Dicitur tamen proprie causa finalis illius actionis sive operationis, sicut quando aliquis sagittat ad aliquem terminum, dirigens sagittam vel volens aliquem interficere, illa interfectio est vere causa finalis motus sagittae, quae tamen a sagitta proprie non intenditur, sed proprie intenditur a sagittante”. Also see [29] (pp. 145–146) for commentary on this passage. |
49 | My thanks to Claude Panaccio for raising this point. |
50 | For a discussion about the conflict between “original author-intentions” and “user-intentions”, see [23] (pp. 227–230). |
51 |
References
- Zupko, J. “Nothing in Nature is Naturally a Statue”: William of Ockham on Artifacts. Metaphysics 2018, 1, 88–96. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Panaccio, C. Ockham’s Nominalism. A Philosophical Introduction; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2022; in press. [Google Scholar]
- Majcherek, K. Why is a House Nothing More than Stones and Pieces of Wood? Ockham’s Argument and its Critics. Rech. Théol. Philos. Médiév. 2022, 89, 109–144. [Google Scholar]
- Thomasson, A.L. Artifacts and Human Concepts. In Creations of the Mind. Theories of Artifacts and Their Representation; Eric, M., Stephen, L., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2007; pp. 54–73. [Google Scholar]
- Normore, C. Accidents and Modes. In Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy; Robert, P., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2011; Volume 2, pp. 674–685. [Google Scholar]
- Pasnau, R. Metaphysical Themes. 1274–1671; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Adams, M.M. Things versus ‘Hows’, or Ockham on Predication and Ontology. In How Things Are. Studies in Predication and the History of Philosophy and Science; Bogen, J., McGuire, J., Eds.; D. Reidel Publishing Company: Dordrecht, The Netherlands; Boston, MA, USA; Lancaster, UK, 1984; pp. 175–188. [Google Scholar]
- Brower-Toland, S. Deflecting Ockham’s Razor: A Medieval Debate about Truth and Ontological Commitment. Unpublished manuscript.
- Brower-Toland, S. Ockham’s Metaphysical Commitments: The Case of Locomotion. Unpublished manuscript.
- William of Ockham. Expositio in Libros Physicorum Aristotelis. Prologus et Libri I-III. In Opera Philosophica IV; Richter, V., Leibold, G., Eds.; Franciscan Institute: St. Bonaventure, NY, USA, 1985. [Google Scholar]
- William of Ockham. Summula Philosophiae Naturalis. In Opera Philosophica VI; Brown, S., Ed.; Franciscan Institute: St. Bonaventure, NY, USA, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- William of Ockham. Tractatus de Corpore Christi. In Opera Theologica X; Grassi, C., Ed.; Franciscan Institute: St. Bonaventure, NY, USA, 1985. [Google Scholar]
- Jenny, P. Ockham’s Razor. In Encyclopedia of Philosophy of Religion; Goetz, S., Taliaferro, C., Eds.; Wiley-Blackwell: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- William of Ockham. Quaestiones in Libros Physicorum Aristotelis. In Opera Philosophica VI; Brown, S., Ed.; Franciscan Institute: St. Bonaventure, NY, USA, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Keele, R. Formal Ontology in the Fourteenth Century: The Chatton Principle and Ockham’s Razor. Ph.D. Thesis, Indiana University, Bloomington, IN, USA, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Maurer, A. The Philosophy of William of Ockham in Light of Its Principles; PIMS: Toronto, ON, Canada, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- William of Ockham. Quodlibeta Septem. In Opera Theologica IX; Wey, J., Ed.; Franciscan Institute: St. Bonaventure, NY, USA, 1980. [Google Scholar]
- Pelletier, J. Kingdoms and Social Groups: William Ockham on the ontology of social groups. Br. J. Hist. Philos. 2021, 29, 24–44. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pelletier, J. William of Ockham on Craft: Knowing How to Build Houses on the Canadian Shield. In Women’s Perspectives on Ancient and Medieval Philosophy; Chouinard, I., McConaughey, Z., Ramos, A.M., Noël, R., Eds.; Springer Nature Switzerland AG: Cham, Switzerland, 2021; pp. 303–318. [Google Scholar]
- Cameron, M. The Moving Cause of Artefacts: The role of techne in metaphysical explanation. Anc. Philos. Today 2019, 1, 64–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Baker, L.R. The Ontology of Artifacts. Philos. Explor. 2004, 7, 99–111. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pelletier, J. From Psychological to Factual Use: Acting Intentionally in Ockham’s Thought. Rech. Théol. Philos. Médiév. 2022, 89, 77–108. [Google Scholar]
- Koslicki, K. Form, Matter, Substance; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Pasnau, R. Teleology in the Later Middle Ages. In Teleology. A History; McDonough, J.K., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2020; pp. 90–115. [Google Scholar]
- William of Ockham. Quodlibetal Questions; Freddoso, A.J.; Kelley, F.E., Translators; Yale University Press: New Haven, CT, USA, 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Pelletier, J. William Ockham on Metaphysics. The Science of Being and God; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Pelletier, J. William Ockham on the Mental Ontology of Scientific Knowledge. In The Ontology, Psychology and Axiology of Habits (Habitus) in Medieval Philosophy; Faucher, N., Roques, M., Eds.; Springer Nature Switzerland AG: Cham, Switzerland, 2018; pp. 285–297. [Google Scholar]
- William of Ockham. Scriptum in Librum Primum Sententiarum. Ordinatio. Prologus et Distinctio Prima. In Opera Theologica; Gál, G., Brown, S., Eds.; Franciscan Institute: St. Bonaventure, NY, USA, 1967. [Google Scholar]
- Schmid, S. Potentialities in the Late Middle Ages—The Latin Tradition. In Handbook of Potentialities; Engelhard, K., Quante, M., Eds.; Springer Nature Switzerland AG: Cham, Switzerland, 2018; pp. 123–153. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Pelletier, J. Getting Real: Ockham on the Human Contribution to the Nature and Production of Artifacts. Philosophies 2022, 7, 90. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7050090
Pelletier J. Getting Real: Ockham on the Human Contribution to the Nature and Production of Artifacts. Philosophies. 2022; 7(5):90. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7050090
Chicago/Turabian StylePelletier, Jenny. 2022. "Getting Real: Ockham on the Human Contribution to the Nature and Production of Artifacts" Philosophies 7, no. 5: 90. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7050090
APA StylePelletier, J. (2022). Getting Real: Ockham on the Human Contribution to the Nature and Production of Artifacts. Philosophies, 7(5), 90. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7050090