Caring for Whom? Racial Practices of Care and Liberal Constructivism
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Living Counterfactually
3. The Trail
3.1. Episode 1. Epistemic Leaning and Interspecies Status Hierarchies
3.2. Episode 2. Equations of Space
3.3. Episode 3. We Don’t Like Your Fence!
4. Entitlements Are Relational
5. Resetting Intuitions in Liberal Theories of Distributive Justice
Funding
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Gilligan, C. In a Different Voice; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1982. [Google Scholar]
- Noddings, N. Caring: A Feminine Approach to Ethics and Moral Education; University of California Press: Berkeley, CA, USA; Los Angeles, CA, USA, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Ruddick, S. Maternal Thinking. Fem. Stud. 1980, 6, 342–367. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ruddick, S. Maternal Thinking; Beacon Press: Boston, MA, USA, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Bartky, S. Femininity and Domination: Studies in the Phenomenology of Oppression; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Tronto, J. Moral Boundaries; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Kittay, E. Love’s Labor; Routledge: New York, MY, USA, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Held, V. The Ethics of Care; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Engster, D. The Heart of Justice; Oxford University Press: New York, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Gouws, A. Toward a Feminist Ethics of Ubuntu: Bridging Rights and Ubuntu. In Care Ethics and Political Theory; Engster, D., Hamington, M., Eds.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Bhandary, A.; Baehr, A.R. Introduction. In Caring for Liberalism; Bhandary, A., Baehr, A., Eds.; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2021; pp. 1–21. [Google Scholar]
- Bhandary, A. Freedom to Care; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Okin, S. Justice, Gender, and the Family; Basic Books: New York, NY, USA, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Baehr, A. (Ed.) Varieties of Feminist Liberalism; Rowman and Littlefield: Lanham, MD, USA, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Mill, J.S. On Liberty. In On Liberty and Other Writings; Stefan, C., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1989; pp. 1–116. [Google Scholar]
- Rawls, J. Justice as Fairness. Philos. Rev. 1958, 67, 164–194. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lloyd, S.A. Varieties of Feminist Liberalism; Baehr, A.R., Ed.; Rowman and Littlefield Publishers: Lanham, MD, USA, 2014; pp. 63–84. [Google Scholar]
- Bhandary, A. Liberal Dependency Care. J. Philos. Res. 2016, 41, 43–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mills, C.W. Black Rights/White Wrongs; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Bhandary, A. The theory of liberal dependency care: A reply to my critics. In Critical Review of Social and Political Philosophy; Mullin, A., Ed.; Routledge: London, UK, 2021. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lorde, A. Sister Outsider; Ten Speed Press: Berkeley, CA, USA, 1984; Random House: New York, NY, USA, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Hooks, B. Racism and Feminism: The issue of accountability, In Ain’t I a Woman: Black Women and Feminism, 2nd ed.; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2015; pp. 119–158. [Google Scholar]
- Lugones, M. Pilgrimages/Peregrinajes; Rowman and Littlefield: Lanham, MD, USA, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Spivak, G.C. ‘Can the Subaltern Speak?: Revised Edition, from the ‘History’ Chapter of Critique of Postcolonial Reason. In Can the Subaltern Speak?: Reflections on the History of an Idea; Rosalind, C.M., Ed.; Columbia University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2010; pp. 21–78. [Google Scholar]
- Narayan, U. Dislocating Cultures; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Khader, S. Decolonizing Feminism; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Welch, S. Existential Eroticism; Lexington Books: Washington, DC, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Bhandary, A. The Arrow of Care Map: Abstract Care in Ideal Theory. Fem. Philos. Q. 2017, 4. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Bhandary, A. Interpersonal reciprocity. In Caring for Liberalism; Bhandary, A., Baehr, A., Eds.; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2021; pp. 145–167. [Google Scholar]
- Bhandary, A. Arranged Marriage: Could it Contribute to Justice? J. Political Philos. 2018, 26, 193–215. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brake, E. Minimizing Marriage; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Metz, T. Untying the Knot: Marriage, the State, and the Case for their Divorce; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Collins, P.H. Black Feminist Thought: Knowledge, Consciousness and the Politics of Empowerment, 2nd ed.; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Muhs, G.G.; Niemann, Y.F.; González, C.G.; Harris, A.P. (Eds.) Presumed Incompetent: The Intersections of Race and Class for Women in Academia; University Press of Colorado: Boulder, CO, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Sheth, F. Toward a Political Philosophy of Race; SUNY Press: Albany, NY, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Yguico, E. Unpublished Conference Paper. In Proceedings of the Pacific APA Meeting, Symposium on Gina Schouten’s “Liberalism, Neutrality, and the Gendered Division of Labor”, Online, 5–10 April 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Sheth, F.A. Unruly Women: Race, Neocolonialism, and the Hijab; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2022. [Google Scholar]
- Palkowitsch, P.; Bostelmann, S.; Lengsfeld, P. Safety and tolerability of iopromide intravascular use: A pooled analysis of three non-interventional studies in 132,012 patients. Acta Radiol. 2014, 55, 707–714. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Crenshaw, K. Mapping the Margins: Intersectionality, Identity Politics, and Violence Against Women of Color. Stanf. Law Rev. 1991, 43, 1241–1299. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gibson, J.J. The Theory of Affordances. In An Ecological Approach to Visual Perception; Houghton-Mifflin: Boston, MA, USA, 1979. [Google Scholar]
- Schapiro, T. Compliance, Complicity, and the Nature of Nonideal Conditions. J. Philos. 2003, 100, 329–335. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Laden, A. Reasoning: A Social Picture; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Kukla, R. Performative Force, Convention, and Discursive Injustice. Hypatia 2014, 29, 440–457. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mills, C.W. Blackness Visible; Cornell University Press: Ithaca, NY, USA, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Bhandary, A. “Being at Home”, White Racisim, and Minority Health. In Applying Nonideal Theory to Bioethics; Victor, E., Palgrave, Guidry-Grimes, L., Eds.; Springer Nature: Cham, Switzerland, 2021; pp. 217–234. [Google Scholar]
- Brison, S.J. ‘We Must Find Words or Burn’: Speaking Out Against Disciplinary Silencing. Fem. Philos. Q. 2017, 3, 1–10. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- On, B.-A.B. The Subject of Violence: Arendtean Exercises in Understanding; Rowman and Littlefield Publishers: Oxford, UK, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Chin, E. My Life with Things; Duke University Press: Durham, NC, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- O’Neill, O. Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant’s Practical Philosophy; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Fricker, M. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Dotson, K. Tracking Epistemic Violence, Tracking Practices of Silencing. Hypatia 2011, 26, 236–257. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Medina, J. The Epistemology of Resistance; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Pohlhaus, G., Jr. Varieties of Epistemic Injustice. In The Routledge Handbook of Epistemic Injustice; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2017; pp. 13–26. [Google Scholar]
- Allen, A.L. Why Privacy Isn’t Everything; Rowman and Littlefield: Lanham, MD, USA, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Card, C. The Atrocity Paradigm: A Theory of Evil; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Sullivan, S. Revealing Whiteness: The Unconscious Habits of Racial Privilege; Indiana University Press: Bloomington, India, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Greyser, N. On Sympathetic Grounds: Race, Gender, and Affective Geographies in Nineteenth-Century North America; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Bhandary, A. Being at Home: Liberal Autonomy in an Unjust World; Department of Philosophy, College of Liberal Arts and Sciences, University of Iowa: Iowa City, IA, USA, 2022; in progress. [Google Scholar]
- Meyers, D.T. Psychocorporeal Selfhood, Practical Intelligence, and Adaptive Autonomy. In Autonomy and the Self; Michael, K., Nadja, J., Eds.; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Laden, A. The Justice of Justification. In Habermas and Rawls; Finlayson, J.G., Freyenhagen, F., Eds.; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Taylor, C. Sources of the Self; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Fraser, N. Talking about needs: Interpretive contests as political conflicts in welfare-state societies. Ethics 1989, 99, 291–313. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stark, C.A. Hypothetical Consent and Justification. J. Philos. 2000, 97, 313–334. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gruen, L. Ethics and Animals: An Introduction; Cambridge, University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Jaggar, A. Thinking about Justice in the Unjust Meantime. Fem. Philos. Q. 2019, 5, 9. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Meyers, D.T. Self, Society, and Personal Choice. Part I. Personal Autonomy and Related Concepts; Columbia University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1989. [Google Scholar]
1 | “Epistemic leaning” is Sandra Bartky’s term [5]. |
2 | The way I am defining “care theory” is also implicit in Daniel Engster’s work (see [9] and private correspondence). |
3 | For liberals theorizing about care, see all contributors) [11]. For a liberal theory of justice that incorporates care, see [12]. Because questions about care have overlapped with debates about women’s labor and socialization, the liberal tradition of evaluating care has been shaped by Susan Okin’s feminist liberalism [13]. For an overview of feminist liberalism, see also [14]. |
4 | |
5 | |
6 | See [6], (p. 11, Figure A) for the initial depiction of the arrow of care map. |
7 | For a range of liberal approaches to care, see [11]. |
8 | There are forms of racialized care that are not defined by whiteness in Asian and Arab countries. In Europe, as well, less advantaged white groups care for the white groups in power. In Asian and Arab countries, for instance, social hierarchies locate care in servant classes. Therefore, a global form of addressing whiteness would not remedy all caregiving invisibility. |
9 | |
10 | Eva Yguico [36] argues that eliminating the gendered division of labor may have harmful effects on, for example, relatives who submit remittances to family members in the Philippines. |
11 | Of course, there will be many exceptions, based on part on the fact that many families are interracial. My recommendations apply to the overall global distribution of care and its systems, and not to legitimate relations of care. Families are the paradigm case for legitimate care relations. |
12 | The experience for racially ambiguous mixed race cis women may be most relevant here. On Muslim women, see Sheth [37]. |
13 | I use “burn” here in a phenomenological sense to describe the sensation as reported anecdotally. The sensation is described medically as “warmth/feeling hot” [38] (Palkowitsch et al., 2014, Table 6). |
14 | See Crenshaw (1991) [39] for the way these inequalities manifest in the law, and also for the concept of intersectionality. |
15 | An “affordance”, in Gibson’s sense (1979) [40], is what the environment makes available to person X. See also Schapiro 2003 [41] (cited in [42] (p. 106, n 2). The minority person’s agency is thwarted when an “act” is not completed, because uptake does not occur, and the intended meaning does not ensue. |
16 | Compare [43] on the ways background social norms impede particular expressions of agency for disadvantaged persons. In this case, I prefer the language of “uptake” to Kukla’s contextual analysis of background social norms. This is my account here centers questions about who it is who endorses and hears claims. This approach deliberately makes individuals the salient objects of analysis, and it is complementary to the analysis of caregiving injustice I make possible with the “arrow of care map” [28]. |
17 | See Tronto and Fisher for the original account of care as attentiveness and responsiveness (p. 127, [6]). |
18 | Here I follow Charles Mills to define whiteness relationally in a status hierarchy that demands deference from non-whites (p. 71, [44]). |
19 | See [45] for the argument that microaggressions cause stress, and the consequence of this stress is harm akin to violence against the body. |
20 | By epistemic leaning, here, I mean that the person who epistemically leans considers the world from the perspective and priorities of the other. |
21 | Susan Brison has argued forcefully for the relevance of personal narrative to the validity of the philosopher’s claims [46]. (Bat-Ami Bar On calls the use of personal narrative a kind of “public autobiography” (p. 3, [47]). Anthropologists call a similar approach “auto-ethnography” (For a good example, see Chin [48]). |
22 | |
23 | These encounters have the significance I attribute to them because they are located among many other similar interactions, constituting a pattern. They can be understood, therefore, only through a form of pattern-recognition, one more readily accessible to others who also experience racism. |
24 | |
25 | Perhaps this was a case of being rendered a “subperson”, the category Charles Mills defines as characteristic of blackness (p. 6, [44]). Or perhaps I was being placed in a nonperson category. I will not take a position here on this question, because what is important for the present analysis is that these people were far more concerned with their dog than they were with me, and my claim to freedom had less uptake than their dog’s claims to freedom of movement. |
26 | As is the case with pattern recognition and instances of microaggressions, whether any one event is an instance of racism will be indeterminate. However, by evaluating the effects of multiple events on the target of the actions, we can see the accumulation of racist and intersectional microaggressions. It thereby paints a picture of the terrain an individual traverses in a particular social form. |
27 | See Claudia Card’s [55] groundbreaking work on evil for the argument that people who have suffered as victims can also perpetrate evil. |
28 | I do not want this episode to be read as if the man was the reasonable adjudicator in a fight among women. Indeed, triangulation to men when they have de facto or de jure power is an anti-feminist dynamic in a patriarchal society. The details about the man are relevant to this example because he was the other witness to the exchanges. |
29 | |
30 | There are ample examples of white ontological expansiveness resulting in an unjustified demand for a justification. To list just one, consider neighbors who used our driveway for several years for their bed and breakfast clients, both they and their customers looked surprised and alarmed when we asked them to stop, or to move their car so that we could rush to work. They simply replied that the previous owner of our house (who had been largely bedridden), had allowed them use of the driveway. |
31 | In fact, initially hoping for reasonableness, I explained to this woman that, although she knows her dogs, and may have a high degree of confidence that they will not bite other people, other people who do not know those dogs do not know that they won’t bite them. However, her hostile gaze quickly made evident that the attempt was futile. |
32 | In the interactions described above, where it seemed that these women simply could not consider me, it seems that what is acceptable has to be indexed to someone with very different affordances than these women. This line of inquiry then points to the need to index affordances to the reasonable individual, where reasonableness is not only a set of beliefs, but it is also corporeal. I take up this question in [58]. On psychocorporeal agency and affordances, see [59]. See [60] on the Habermas-Rawls dispute about acceptance versus acceptability. On my view, if the clause is “acceptable to her”, then the woman’s “strong horizons” [61] are invoked. |
33 | |
34 | My view here is in the same family as Charles Taylor’s account of horizons of significance. On my view, though, these horizons occur within a particular social form, and salient social stratification creates regularities in our experiences of moral salience and significance. |
35 | Cf. Mills, who claims that the liberal idea of reasonableness is based on the perspective of the western white person, who have “traditionally thought of nonwhite assets as a common white resource to be legitimately exploited” (p. 47, [19]). |
36 | For further elaboration on this concept, see my monograph in progress, Being at Home: Liberal Autonomy in an Unjust World. |
37 | |
38 | Here I use “persons” in a way that is inclusive of the view that dogs are persons or members of families (for a species-inclusive view of who counts as a moral patient, see (p. 75, [64]). |
39 | See [12] for the comprehensive account. |
40 | For an alternative account, see [65]. |
41 | For the original account of autonomy skills, see Meyers [66] and many other works. For a role for autonomy skills in a liberal care theory of justice, see [12]. The critical awareness of norms engendered by these skills overlaps with Medina’s epistemic virtue of metalucidity [52]. For discussion, see [20]. |
42 | For the first stage, see [12]. |
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Bhandary, A.L. Caring for Whom? Racial Practices of Care and Liberal Constructivism. Philosophies 2022, 7, 78. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7040078
Bhandary AL. Caring for Whom? Racial Practices of Care and Liberal Constructivism. Philosophies. 2022; 7(4):78. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7040078
Chicago/Turabian StyleBhandary, Asha Leena. 2022. "Caring for Whom? Racial Practices of Care and Liberal Constructivism" Philosophies 7, no. 4: 78. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7040078
APA StyleBhandary, A. L. (2022). Caring for Whom? Racial Practices of Care and Liberal Constructivism. Philosophies, 7(4), 78. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7040078