The Ecological Turn in Design: Adopting a Posthumanist Ethics to Inform Value Sensitive Design
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Technological Assessment and Designing for Values
2.1. Value Sensitive Design
2.1.1. Conceptual Investigations
2.1.2. Empirical Investigations
2.1.3. Technical Investigations
3. Bridging a Severing of Praxis
3.1. Posthumanism and Reclaiming Animality
3.1.1. Metamorphosis
3.1.2. Metaphysics
3.1.3. Materialism
Then, God said, “Let us make humankind in our image, according to our likeness; and let them have dominion over the fish of the sea, and over the birds of the air, and over the cattle, and over all the wild animals of the earth, and over every creeping thing that creeps upon the earth.”(Genesis 1:26)
3.1.4. A Companion Ethics
4. Designing Anticipation
5. Designing Technofutures
5.1. Constructing a Hybrid Project
- Explicit
- Public
- Accessible to all interested/relevant stakeholders
- In order to accurately envision co-habitable, symbiotic futures with nonhuman beings, it is necessary to discard moral law theories of morality and adopt an embodied ethics. This ethics provides an anticipatory landscape for coming to a greater understanding and respect for identities and relations with other entities. In turn, this creates a more accurate mapping of the cognitive undertaking within human moral deliberation. It also allows for intersubjectivity between peoples to take place [99,100,101,102,103].
- Hybridisation and a realist ontology adduce the decoupling of humanity from its traditional theological and humanistic centre [56,57]. All being resides on the peripheries, so this is where transformation, hybridisation, and a space of respect and symbioses can flourish. Shared space permits the distribution of agency and an area for mutual co-habitation [72,84,86,104]. A distribution of agency towards an ecological (rather than an individualist) definition of identity is ontologically warranted, going above and beyond the illusory ones still held and passed down as part of the heritage of theology and agricultural-age societies [58,71,84].
- Unlike Latour’s oppressive ANT of immanence, these third spaces acknowledge necessarily contingent connections between all entities. Such spaces further affirm their discrete heterogeneity [56]. Hybridisation is ipso facto a constitution of heterogeneity; as such, it represents the distinct yet enmeshed entities of which it is composed [73,84].
- An imaginative rationality becomes necessary for envisioning the broadest set of possible in order to sanction organic changes taking place as needed. This consists of curating how futures are imagined but without authoritarianism taking hold [105]. Curation should be restricted insofar as the constraints of an embodied ethics.
- Past papers must be understood as symbiotic; they exert asymmetric effects that impact the present and future. The ontic structures upon which past projects are built call into question what actions are undertaken today for the future. They further interrogate the framework within which those actions are undertaken, i.e., how they constrain and promote specific categories of actions.
5.2. Attuning to Representation
Contracting Nonhumans
An act is wrong if its performance under the circumstances would be disallowed by any set of principles for the general regulation of behaviour that no one could reasonably reject as a basis for informed, unforced, general agreement [112](p. 153).
6. Limitations and Future Research
7. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Jasanoff, S.; Kim, S.-H. Dreamscapes of Modernity: Sociotechnical Imaginaries and the Fabrication of Power; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Baxter, G.; Sommerville, I. Socio-technical systems: From design methods to systems engineering. Interact. Comput. 2011, 23, 4–17. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Haraway, D.J. The Companion Species Manifesto: Dogs, People, and Significant Otherness; Prickly Paradigm Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 2003; Volume 1. [Google Scholar]
- Jasanoff, S. Future Imperfect: Science, Technology, and the Imaginations of Modernity. In Sociotechnical Imaginaries and the Fabrication of Power; Chicago University Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 2015; pp. 1–47. [Google Scholar]
- Bauer, J.M.; Herder, P.M. Designing Socio-Technical Systems. In Philosophy of Technology and Engineering Sciences; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2009; pp. 601–630. [Google Scholar]
- More, M. The Philosophy of Transhumanism. In The Transhumanist Reader; Wiley: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 2013; pp. 3–17. [Google Scholar]
- Van Den Hoven, J.; Miller, S.; Pogge, T. (Eds.) Designing in Ethics. In The Design Turn in Applied Ethics; Cambridge University Press (CUP): Cambridge, UK, 2017; pp. 11–31. [Google Scholar]
- Couture, S. Values and Configuration of Users in the Design of Software Source Code. Int. J. Commun. 2017, 11, 21. [Google Scholar]
- Ferguson, E.S.; Petroski, H. Design Paradigms: Case Histories of Error and Judgment in Engineering. Technol. Cult. 1995, 36, 696. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Umbrello, S. The moral psychology of value sensitive design: The methodological issues of moral intuitions for responsible innovation. J. Responsible Innov. 2018, 5, 1–15. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Hoven, J.V.D.; Lokhorst, G.-J.; Van De Poel, I. Engineering and the Problem of Moral Overload. Sci. Eng. Ethic 2011, 18, 143–155. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Friedman, B. Value-sensitive design. Interactions 1996, 3, 16–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Samadi, P.; Grégoire, L.; Morissette, M.; Calon, F.; Tahar, A.H.; Bélanger, N.; Dridi, M.; Bédard, P.J.; Di Paolo, T. Basal ganglia group II metabotropic glutamate receptors specific binding in non-human primate model of L-Dopa-induced dyskinesias. Neuropharmacology 2008, 54, 258–268. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Friedman, B.; Howe, D.; Felten, E. Informed consent in the Mozilla browser: Implementing value-sensitive design. In Proceedings of the 35th Annual Hawaii International Conference on System Sciences, Big Island, HI, USA, 10 January 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Oosterlaken, I. Applying Value Sensitive Design (VSD) to Wind Turbines and Wind Parks: An Exploration. Sci. Eng. Ethic 2015, 21, 359–379. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Woelfer, J.P.; Iverson, A.; Hendry, D.G.; Friedman, B.; Gill, B.T. Improving the safety of homeless young people with mobile phones. In Proceedings of the 2011 Annual Conference on Human Factors in Computing Systems—CHI ’11; Association for Computing Machinery (ACM): New York, NY, USA, 2011; pp. 1707–1716. [Google Scholar]
- Timmermans, J.; Zhao, Y.; Hoven, J.V.D. Ethics and Nanopharmacy: Value Sensitive Design of New Drugs. NanoEthics 2011, 5, 269–283. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Umbrello, S.; De Bellis, A.F. A Value-Sensitive Design Approach to Intelligent Agents. In Artificial Intelligence Safety and Security; Apple Academic Press: Palm Bay, FL, USA, 2018; pp. 395–409. [Google Scholar]
- Umbrello, S. Atomically Precise Manufacturing and Responsible Innovation: A Value Sensitive Design Approach to Explorative Nanophilosophy. SSRN Electron. J. 2018, 10. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Arie, R. The Past and Future of Constructive Technology Assessment. Technol. Forecast. Soc. Chang. 1996, 54, 251. [Google Scholar]
- Zimmer-Merkle, S.; Fleischer, T. Eclectic, random, intuitive? Technology assessment, RRI, and their use of history. J. Responsible Innov. 2017, 4, 217–233. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fisher, E. Entangled futures and responsibilities in technology assessment. J. Responsible Innov. 2017, 4, 83–84. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Decker, M.; Weinberger, N.; Krings, B.-J.; Hirsch, J. Imagined technology futures in demand-oriented technology assessment. J. Responsible Innov. 2017, 4, 177–196. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Collingridge, D. The Social Control of Technology; St. Martins Press: New York, NY, USA, 1980. [Google Scholar]
- Kulve, H.T.; Rip, A. Constructing Productive Engagement: Pre-engagement Tools for Emerging Technologies. Sci. Eng. Ethic 2011, 17, 699–714. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Wender, B.A.; Foley, R.W.; Hottle, T.A.; Sadowski, J.; Prado-Lopez, V.; Eisenberg, D.A.; Laurin, L.; Seager, T.P. Anticipatory life-cycle assessment for responsible research and innovation. J. Responsible Innov. 2014, 1, 200–207. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brey, P.A.E. Anticipatory Ethics for Emerging Technologies. NanoEthics 2012, 6, 1–13. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Friedman, B.; Kahn, P.H., Jr.; Borinng, A. Value Sensitive Design and Information Systems. In The Handbook of Information and Computer Ethics; Himma, K.E., Tavani, H.T., Eds.; John Wiley & Sons, Inc.: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Ruzic, L.; Sanfod, J.A. Universal Design Mobile Interface Guidelines (UDMIG) for an Aging Population. In Perspectives on HCI Research with Teenagers; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2017; pp. 17–37. [Google Scholar]
- Waller, S.; Bradley, M.; Hosking, I.; Clarkson, P.J. Making the case for inclusive design. Appl. Ergon. 2015, 46, 297–303. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Bødker, K.; Kensing, F.; Simonsen, J. Participatory IT Design: Designing for Business and Workplace Realities; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Camara, F.; Calvary, G. Worth-Centered Design in Practice: Lessons from Experience and Research Agenda. In Lecture Notes in Computer Science; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2015; pp. 123–139. [Google Scholar]
- Friedman, B.; Hendry, D.G.; Huldtgren, A.; Jonker, C.; Hoven, J.V.D.; Van Wynsberghe, A. Charting the Next Decade for Value Sensitive Design. Aarhus Ser. Hum. Centered Comput. 2015, 1, 4. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Santoni de Sio, F.; van den Hoven, J. Meaningful Human Control over Autonomous Systems: A Philosophical account. Front. Robot. AI 2018, 5, 15. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Betz, S.; Fritsch, A. A Comparison of Value Sensitive Design and Sustainability Design. In Computer Science Spectrum; Society for Computer Science eV: Bonn, Germany, 2016; pp. 267–274. [Google Scholar]
- Brey, P.; Center, P.D. Philosophy of Technology after the Empirical Turn. Techné Res. Philos. Technol. 2010, 14, 36–48. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Le Dantec, C.A.; Poole, E.S.; Wyche, S.P. Values as lived experience. In Proceedings of the ACM SIGCHI Conference on Human Factors in Computing Systems; Association for Computing Machinery (ACM): New York, NY, USA, 2009; pp. 1141–1150. [Google Scholar]
- Vermaas, P.E.; Hekkert, P.; Manders-Huits, N.; Tromp, N. Design Methods in Design for Values. In Handbook of Ethics, Values, and Technological Design; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2014; pp. 1–19. [Google Scholar]
- Friedman, B. Value-Sensitive Design: A Research Agenda for Information Technology; Contract No SBR-9729633; National Science Foundation: Arlington, VA, USA, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- 4TU. Centre for Ethics and Technology. Available online: https://ethicsandtechnology.eu/about-4tuethics/about/ (accessed on 18 June 2018).
- TUDelft. Design for Values & Responsible Innovation. Available online: http://designforvalues.tudelft.nl/ (accessed on 18 June 2018).
- Nathan, L.P.; Klasnja, P.V.; Friedman, B. Value scenarios. In CHI ’07 Extended Abstracts on Human Factors in Computing Systems—CHI ’07; Association for Computing Machinery: New York, NY, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nathan, L.P.; Friedman, B.; Klasnja, P.; Kane, S.K.; Miller, J.K. Envisioning systemic effects on persons and society throughout interactive system design. In Proceedings of the 7th ACM Conference on Recommender Systems; Association for Computing Machinery (ACM): New York, NY, USA, 2008; pp. 1–10. [Google Scholar]
- Friedman, B.; Kahn, P.H., Jr. Human Values, Ethics, and Design. In The Human-Computer Interaction Handbook; CRC Press: Boca Ratan, FL, USA, 2003; pp. 1177–1201. [Google Scholar]
- Friedman, B.; Hendry, D.G.; Borning, A. A Survey of Value Sensitive Design Methods. Found. Trends Hum. Comput. Interact. 2017, 11, 63–125. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Friedman, B.; Nathan, L.P.; Kane, S.K.; Lin, J. Envisioning Cards; University of Washington Bookstore: Seattle, WA, USA. Available online: https://www.envisioningcards.com/ (accessed on 15 March 2021).
- Freeman, B.; Borning, A. YP and Urban Simulation: Applying an Agile Programming Methodology in a Politically Tempestuous Domain. In Proceedings of the Agile Development Conference, Salt Lake City, UT, USA, 28 June 2003; pp. 2–11. [Google Scholar]
- Waddell, P. UrbanSim: Modeling Urban Development for Land Use, Transportation, and Environmental Planning. J. Am. Plan. Assoc. 2002, 68, 297–314. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- van de Poel, I. Dealing with Moral Dilemmas through Design. In Designing in Ethics; van den Hoven, J., Miller, S., Pogge, T., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2017; pp. 57–77. [Google Scholar]
- Harman, G. Object-Oriented Ontology: A New Theory of Everything; Penguin Random House: New York, NY, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Helmreich, S. Alien Ocean: Anthropological Voyages in Microbial Seas; University of California Press: Oakland, CA, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Ferrando, F. Posthumanism, Transhumanism, Antihumanism, Metahumanism, and New Materialisms: Differences and Relations. Existenz 2013, 8, 26–32. [Google Scholar]
- Fuller, S. Preparing for Life in Humanity 2.0; Springer Science and Business Media LLC.: Berlin, Germany, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Sorgner, S.L. Pedegrees. In Post–And Transhumanism: An Introduction; Ranisch, R., Sorgner, S.L., Eds.; Peter Lang: Frankfurt am Main, Germany, 2014; pp. 29–48. Available online: https://doi.org/10.15496/publikation-738 (accessed on 15 March 2021).
- Caffo, L. Fragile Umanità; Giulio Einaudi editore: Torino, Italy, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Harman, G. Immaterialism: Objects and Social Theory; Polity: Cambridge, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Morton, T. Being Ecological; MIT Press: Boston, MA, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Morton, T. The Ecological Thought; Dykinson: Madrid, Spain, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Caffo, L. L Maiale Non Fa La Rivoluzione: Manifesto Per Un Antispecismo Debole; Sonda: Milano, Italy, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Caffo, L.; Cimatti, F. A Come Animale: Voci per Un Bestiario Dei Sentimenti; Giunti: Firenze, Italy, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Marchesini, R. Tecnosfera: Proiezioni per Un Futuro Posthumano; Castelvechi: Roma, Italy, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Caffo, L. Adesso l’animalità; Graphe.it: Perugia, Italy, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Cottingham, J. ‘A Brute to the Brutes?’: Descartes’ Treatment of Animals. Philosophy 1978, 53, 551–559. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Marchesini, R. Alterity and the Non-Human. Humanimalia 2010, 1, 91–96. [Google Scholar]
- Marchesini, R.; Tonutti, S. Manuale Di Zooantropologia; Meltemi Editore srl: Milan, Italy, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Sax, B. Who Patrols the Human-Animal Divide? Minn. Rev. 2009, 2010, 165–169. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sax, B. Zootropia, kinship, and alterity in the work of roberto marchesini. Angelaki 2016, 21, 7–13. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Caffo, L. Margini Dell’umanità: Animalità e Ontologia Sociale; Mimesis: Milano, Italy, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Bryant, L.; Srnicek, N.; Harman, G. The Speculative Turn: Continental Realism and Materialism; Re.Press: Melbourne, Australia, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Meillassoux, Q. After Finitude: An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency; Brassier, R., Ed.; Bloomsbury Publishing: London, UK, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Morton, T. Dark Ecology: For a Logic of Future Coexistence; Columbia University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Caffo, L.; Marchesini, R. Così Parlò Il Postumano; Novalogos: Anzio-Lavinio, Italy, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Haraway, D.J. A Cyborg Manifesto. In Cultural Theory: An Anthology; Wiley: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 2016; pp. 3–90. [Google Scholar]
- Armelagos, G.J.; Van Gerven, D.P. A Century of Skeletal Biology and Paleopathology: Contrasts, Contradictions, and Conflicts. Am. Anthr. 2003, 105, 53–64. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- De Waal, F.B.; Ferrari, P.F. Towards a bottom-up perspective on animal and human cognition. Trends Cogn. Sci. 2010, 14, 201–207. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Johnson, M. Moral Imagination: Implications of Cognitive Science for Ethics; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Johnson, M.; Lakoff, G. Why cognitive linguistics requires embodied realism. Cogn. Linguist. 2002, 13, 245–263. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Singer, P. On Comparing the Value of Human and Nonhuman Life; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1998; pp. 93–104. [Google Scholar]
- Singer, P. The Expanding Circle: Ethics, Evolution, and Moral Progress; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Deleuze, G. Spinoza: Practical Philosophy; City Lights Books: San Francisco, CA, USA, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- Bostrom, N. A History of Transhumanist Thought. J. Evol. Technol. 2005, 14, 1–25. [Google Scholar]
- Nagel, T. What Is It like to Be a Bat? Philos. Rev. 1974, 83, 435–450. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bogost, I. Alien Phenomenology, or What It’s Like to Be a Thing; University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, MN, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Caffo, L.; Muzzonigro, A. Costruire Futuri: Migrazioni, Città, Immaginazioni—Con un Dialogo Tra Stefano Boeri, Amos Gitai e Adrian Paci; Bompiani/Giunti Editore: Firenze, Italy, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Rosenberger, R.; Verbeek, P.-P. Postphenomenological Investigations: Essays on Human-Technology Relations; Lexington Books: Washington, DC, USA, 2015; pp. 9–41. [Google Scholar]
- Haraway, D.J. Staying with the Trouble: Making Kin in the Chthulucene; Duke University Press: Durham, NC, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Lowenhaupt, T.A. The Mushroom at the End of the World: On the Possibility of Life in Capitalist Ruins; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Haraway, D. Anthropocene, Capitalocene, Plantationocene, Chthulucene: Making Kin. Environ. Humanit. 2015, 6, 159–165. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Randerson, J. Richard Dawkins: Blurring the Human/Animal Boundary. Available online: https://www.theguardian.com/science/blog/2009/jan/02/richard-dawkins-chimpanzee-hybrid (accessed on 23 June 2018).
- Kellner, D. Postmodernism as Social Theory: Some Challenges and Problems. Theory Cult. Soc. 1988, 5, 239–269. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sim, S. The Routledge Companion to Postmodernism; Routledge: Milton Park, UK, 2012; pp. 3–14. [Google Scholar]
- Prado, C.G. A House Divided: Comparing Analytic and Continental Philosophy; Humanity Books: Amherst, MA, USA, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Levy, N. Analytic and Continental Philosophy: Explaining the Differences. Metaphilosophy 2003, 34, 284–304. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jirotka, M.; Grimpe, B.; Stahl, B.; Eden, G.; Hartswood, M. Responsible research and innovation in the digital age. Commun. ACM 2017, 60, 62–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stahl, B.C.; Coeckelbergh, M. Ethics of healthcare robotics: Towards responsible research and innovation. Robot. Auton. Syst. 2016, 86, 152–161. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Grunwald, A. The hermeneutic side of responsible research and innovation. J. Responsible Innov. 2014, 1, 274–291. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Van Der Burg, S. On the hermeneutic need for future anticipation. J. Responsible Innov. 2014, 1, 99–102. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gibbs, R.W., Jr.; Hampe, B. The Embodied and Discourse Views of Metaphor: Why These Are Not so Different and How They Can Be Brought Closer Together. In Metaphor: Embodied Cognition and Discourse; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2017; pp. 319–365. [Google Scholar]
- Narvaez, D. Triune Ethics Meta-Theory and Embodied Moral Development. In Embodied Morality; Springer Science and Business Media LLC.: Berlin, Germany, 2016; pp. 31–46. [Google Scholar]
- Narvaez, D. Embodied Morality: Protectionism, Engagement and Imagination; Palgrave: Cham, Switzerland, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Haraway, D. Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism and the Privilege of Partial Perspective. Fem. Stud. 1988, 14, 575. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Johnson, M. Morality for Humans: Ethical Understanding from the Perspective of Cognitive Science; The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Morton, T. Humankind: Solidarity with Nonhuman People; Verso: London, UK, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Umbrello, S. Imaginative Value Sensitive Design: How Moral Imagination Exceeds Moral Law Theories in Informing Responsible Innovation; University of Edinburgh: Edinburgh, UK, 2018; Available online: https://doi.org/10.13140/RG.2.2.16304.61447 (accessed on 15 March 2021).
- Latour, B. Facing Gaia: Eight Lectures on the New Climatic Regime; Polity: Cambridge, UK, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Winner, L. Do Artifacts Have Politics? Technol. Futur. 2003, 109, 148–164. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gerchick, M. What We Breathe When We Fly. Available online: https://medium.com/science-and-technology/what-we-breathe-when-we-fly-e8eb910d8b48 (accessed on 24 June 2018).
- Beekmans, J. Trend 7: Design for Animals. Available online: https://popupcity.net/trend-7-design-for-animals/ (accessed on 24 June 2018).
- Warnke, U. Bees, Birds and Mankind Destroying Nature by “Electrosmog” Effects of Wireless Communication Technologies; Competence Initiative for the Protection of Humanity, Environment and Democracy: Kempten, Germany, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Umbrello, S.; Lombard, J. Silence of the Idols: Appropriating the Myths of Daedalus and Sisyphus for Posthumanist Discourses. Postmod. Open 2018, 9, 98–121. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Scanlon, T.M. What We Owe to Each Other; Indiana University Press: Bloomington, IN, USA, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Carruthers, P. The Animal Issue: Moral Theory in Practice; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Carruthers, P. Against the Moral Standing of Animals. In Questions of Life and Death: Readings in Practical Ethics; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2011; pp. 274–284. [Google Scholar]
- Talbert, M. Contractualism and Our Duties to Nonhuman Animals. Environ. Ethic 2006, 28, 201–215. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rowlands, M. Animal Rights; Wiley Online Library: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Slaughter, R.A. Welcome to the anthropocene. Futures 2012, 44, 119–126. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Latour, B. We Have Never Been Modern; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1993. [Google Scholar]
1 | For this reason, the VSD method is taken up as the comparative approach in criticising value-investigations in the design turn. Of course, there are other more commonly practiced applied design methods (such as Human Centered Design or HCD) that can be used as a locus to bridge the goals of this work with a larger community of current design practices. HCD or Design thinking is implicitly anthropocentric and very widespread today. Within the design community, designers have proposed adding a fourth (albeit incremental) dimension to HCD’s Desirable, Feasible, Viable triage: Responsible. ‘Responsible’ is meant to be a catch-all dimension that would demand for design to consider its impacts whether unintended or not, such as pollution, killing of animals, climate change, etc. Some have suggested a Bio-centric Design (BCD to replace HCD). |
2 | The ‘4TU’ represents four technology-focused universities in mutual collaboration with one another. They are Delft University of Technology, Eindhoven University of Technology, University of Twente, and Wageningen University. |
3 | This is only one of a set of values that is context-specific to ‘care’, as broadly construed within the medical domain. |
4 | In [10] author discusses the applicability of intersubjectivity (a primarily continentally-derived notion) towards DfV approaches. However, this is the exception and not the rule. |
5 | Haraway [3] provides a good way to envision this togetherness in terms of various nature-cultures between humans and dogs. Togetherness would be based on finding common respect for difference rather than anthropocentrically anthropomorphising behaviour and projecting anthropic consciousness to nonhuman beings as a way to relate. |
6 | Such a philosophical move is based on questionable logic and borders on committing the genetic fallacy. Still, the theological and purely coincidental observations of pre-moderns can be criticised on their own grounds, which I contend are similarly false. |
7 | Like Heidegger’s claim of Dasein being particularly human, and mainly German at that. Making Dasein a feature of all lifeforms would begin on a more egalitarian ontological footing. |
8 | Sustainability discourse has been quite egregious given its association with renewable energies. Counter-literature has discussed how discourse on sustainability is directed at merely sustaining currently destructive practices. These practices may consequentially lead to the continued and unmitigated use of environmentally devastating forms of energy and fuel development. |
9 | These moral law theories should be distinguished from other moral traditions like virtue ethics, which have deep and ancient roots. |
10 | This is notably different from the deontological ethics prescribed Kant, as it is not so oppressively universal or absolutist. Instead, it is deeply contingent on context. |
11 | Objects should not be confused with things being ‘objectified’; an object can be any entity, event, etc. including nonhuman animals. |
12 | The term refers to the always-already posthumans of philosophical posthumanism, and not to the other interpretations of posthumans such as that envisioned in transhumanism. |
13 | More literal conceptions of hybridisation have retarded the progress of philosophical posthumanism recounted herein. This is primarily caused by the transhumanist (i.e., ultra-humanist) domain in which the concept of hybridisation has arisen. The will towards progress and human betterment has infected the discourse. To this end, a more metaphorical definition of hybridisation has greater utility in understanding human-nonhuman relations and being-with other forms of life. |
14 | The latter is a reference to the necessary superiority of the human rational mind, as argued by theology and Enlightenment philosophy. This contrasts with the notion of the mind as a product of evolutionary contingency, as argued by Darwin. |
15 | Imagine the state mandates the euthanasia of all pets/animals within the polis. The companionship that exists intersubjectively between species, particularly human-nonhuman, could foreseeably result in a similar destabilisation of society. |
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2021 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Umbrello, S. The Ecological Turn in Design: Adopting a Posthumanist Ethics to Inform Value Sensitive Design. Philosophies 2021, 6, 29. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies6020029
Umbrello S. The Ecological Turn in Design: Adopting a Posthumanist Ethics to Inform Value Sensitive Design. Philosophies. 2021; 6(2):29. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies6020029
Chicago/Turabian StyleUmbrello, Steven. 2021. "The Ecological Turn in Design: Adopting a Posthumanist Ethics to Inform Value Sensitive Design" Philosophies 6, no. 2: 29. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies6020029
APA StyleUmbrello, S. (2021). The Ecological Turn in Design: Adopting a Posthumanist Ethics to Inform Value Sensitive Design. Philosophies, 6(2), 29. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies6020029