Cosmic Conundrums, Common Origins, and Omnivorous Constraints
Abstract
1. Introduction
2. Revisiting COIs: Janssen’s Account
“If it were the case that X, then that would explain observations/phenomena a, b, c, …” → “It is, in fact, the case that X” ([1], p. 464).
(CAUSAL EXPLANATION) COIs, at least provisionally, posit some causal structure or mechanism as their central explanantia. COI stories provide causal explanations: they explain by exhibiting how the phenomena fit into a larger causal nexus. Typically, and for “the most interesting cases” ([1], p. 467) COI stories postulate common causes.
(SUPREME EXPLANATORY POWER) The explanatory power of COIs is so formidable that it counts as compelling evidence. In fact, “the main COIs examined in (Janssen’s) paper have provided some of the strongest evidence ever produced by science on how to cut nature at the joints” ([1], p. 465).
(WEAK REALISM) COIs “provide exceptionally strong warrant for the conclusion that the phenomena they tie together are due to the same structure or mechanism” (ibid.; also p. 512), circumscribing “phenomena kinds” ([1], p. 465), i.e., natural groupings.
COIs do not warrant, however, realist commitments to any specific details of their explanatorily operant structure/mechanism, nor to the “ontological status of theoretical entities” ([1], p. 468) more generally.
(COMMITMENT) COIs exact a twofold commitment towards them.3 The first is a corollary of (WEAK REALISM): they establish firm grounds (sometimes even “beyond the shadow of a doubt” [1], pp. 492, 512) for believing a COI story’s distinctive causal structure or mechanism to correspond to something real. In addition to that, COIs also commit us to prospective “forward-engagement” ([1], p. 476) as gripping “promissory (notes)” (ibid.) for further work on them: they instil rationally warranted trust in their implementation into future research as “important constraints” ([1], p. 465), and in their fruitful further elaboration.
3. Analysis: Re-Examining COIs, and the Case for COI*s
3.1. Causal Explanations vs. Accounting for Constraints
- -
- concrete material common causes (as one would intuitively and conventionally classify them), such as the Chicxulub asteroid impact ([1], p. 469, fn. 23), or Dark Matter and Energy (see below, Section 5.1 and Section 5.2));
- -
- -
- lawlike claims/generalisations under which phenomena are subsumed as instantiations, as in the case of Copernican, Keplerian or Newtonian celestial mechanics (op.cit., p. 471), or Einstein’s light quantum hypothesis14 (cf. op.cit., p. 512, fn. 67); or
- -
- more abstract, mathematical principles, such as the Pauli Principle (as a symmetry postulate for many-particle quantum systems) or Einstein’s Relativity Principle.
“If it were the case that X, then that would account for the constraints a, b, c, ….” → adopt X.
3.2. COI*s as Guides to Warranted Pursuit
- -
- internal consistency: absence of logical contradictions;
- -
- explanatory power, with its dimensions of scope (or unifying power), and fit22;
- -
- coherence in the narrow sense: the ability to form a harmonious whole (non-adhocness) links to other areas (minimally: consistency);
- -
- programmatic character: “methodological and heuristic means to tackle [existing] problems in […] further development” ([11], p. 3123).
- -
- (mathematical or ontological) simplicity and parsimony
- -
- ease of testability
- -
- conservatism and familiarity,
- -
- a powerful heuristic that sketches fruitful paths of further inquiry, and equips the researcher with versatile toolbox for tackling problems, sophisticate and extending an idea to other areas (cf. [87], p. 48).
4. COI*s as Inferences to Pursuit-Worthy Ideas
(CONSTRAINT OMNIVORY) Whereas COIs start from empirical phenomena as explananda in a COI story, we propose to include also “more theoretical” facts: COI*s start from scientific constraints more generally. Whereas the common origins of empirical phenomena are the target explananda of Janssen’s COIs, our COI*s are “constraint-omnivorous”: they account for a plethora of constraints at once.
(EXPLANATORY PLURALISM) Whereas Janssen originally portrays COIs as purveying causal information—their common origins as common causes or mechanisms—we drop this restriction to causal explanations: also non-causal types of explanations are permissible. In fact, we allow for a broader array of ways in which an omnivorous COI*’s constraints can be accounted for (such as accommodation, or coherent integration).
(TANTALISING EXPLANATORY POWER) The explanatory power of COI*s is impressive, in an epistemically non-trivial/non-arbitrary sense. Yet, it would be hasty to declare it, at least on its own, compelling evidence.
The extent to which explanation and confirmation/evidence are intertwined is a separate matter; they plausibly are, though this is inessential here.
(HOPEFUL REALISM) COI*s fall short of the evidential-epistemic standards that realists typically presuppose: their explanantia are epistemically evidentially (still) too insecure. Nonetheless, COI* are not entirely devoid of epistemic merits: meeting a credibility threshold, they qualify as reasonable working hypotheses that we may countenance.
(PURSUIT) Whereas Janssen deems COI reasoning legitimate also in the context of acceptance (i.e., as conferring evidential-epistemic reasons for belief), we restrict the reach of COIs and COI*s to the context of pursuit: they only warrant inference to promising working hypotheses which deserve imposition as constraints and/or further scrutiny, elaboration, and testing—an incentive to further work with them.
Contra Janssen, this does not commit us to divesting COI/COI* stories of evidential-epistemic significance (nor explanatory power more generally). In particular, the theories constructed through COI* reasoning may account for the empirical phenomena or constraints in an evidentially epistemically relevant manner.
(PURSUIT-WORTHINESS) Assuming no overriding shortcomings in other regards, COIs and COIs* underwrite warranted inferences to pursuit-worthy ideas on two major models of pursuit-worthiness.
The coherentist account conceives of pursuit-worthiness as the plausible prospect of evidence/epistemic justification in the sense of a coherentist epistemology. Then, the characteristic coherence with constraints that COI*s promise grounds their inference to pursuit-worthy ideas. The virtue-economic account conceives of pursuit-worthiness as a favourable balance between cognitive costs and benefits, a favourable score in terms of theory virtues. Again, the characteristic coherence with constraints tends to secure this for COI*s.
5. Cosmic Common Origins and COI*s
5.1. Dark Matter
5.1.1. The Dark Matter Problems
5.1.2. Dark Matter and COI*s
5.2. Dark Energy
5.2.1. The Chequered History of the Cosmological Constant
5.2.2. Dark Energy and COI*s
5.3. Inflation
5.3.1. Enigmas of the Big Bang
5.3.2. Inflation and COI*s
Author Contributions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
Abbreviations
COI | Common Origins Inference |
COI* | Constraint-Omnivorous Inference |
IBE | Inference to the Best Explanation |
1. | |
2. | Regrettably, to the best of our knowledge, neither the authors participating in that debate over the methods of the historical sciences, nor Janssen engage with each other’s work. |
3. | Interestingly, we find this double-commitment also in Kuhn [11] (as well as in van Fraassen [12], p. 210, and elaborated in his [13]). It is also prevalent in many scientists’ philosophical musings on science (e.g., [14], as well as Turner, whom Janssen cites). As one of our main corrections of Janssen’s account, Section 3.2 will argue that, first and foremost, the prospective dimension of this commitment, the one related to promise and trust-worthy potential, is what COIs licence. |
4. | Our critique will primarily draw on philosophical arguments. An anonymous reviewer alerted us to a complementary argument from more historiographical arguments: should we construe Janssen’s own COI exemplars as historically situated within the context of pursuit or that of justification? At least for some cases (e.g., Copernicanism until the early 1700s, or the first decade of Special Relativity), the former seems a very plausible case. This is would undoubtedly be grist to our mills. Regrettably, space limitations forbid doing justice to such a historical re-assessment. We hope that readers of this Special Issue will take up the challenge! |
5. | Note in particular one of the challenges to Salmon’s conception: its inherent physicalism (as Salmon [15], p. 204 frankly admits): its applicability to disciplines other than physics seems doubtful (especially to Janssen’s ([1], fn. 23; p. 460, fn. 5) example of COI reasoning in recent art history). This clearly contravenes the cross-disciplinary pervasiveness of COIs that Janssen otherwise stresses. |
6. | |
7. | Analogously to how identity theorists seek to explain away and reduce mental states to physical states (see, e.g., [23], Ch. 8). |
8. | It would even be hasty to parade the Copernican and Keplerian cases of celestial mechanics as clear-cut examples for causal explanations. Neither Copernicus nor Kepler obviously stated their COI reason in causal terms; arguably that would involve gravity as a key explanans. Even if we allow for the later description in terms of Newtonian gravity, the appropriateness of causal terminology is not straightforward (owing to the action-at-a-distance nature of Newtonian Gravity, [15], pp. 209, 242)—the linchpin of, e.g., Russell’s and others’ anti-causalism (as cited by Salmon, op.cit., p. 136, see [18], Ch. 2 for a broader historical review of anti-causal sentiments amongst 19th and early 20th century physicists). The general-relativistic perspective on gravity as a causal explanans is even more controversial (e.g., [26,27]). |
9. | Salmon ([15], p. 238) is lucid about the requisite ontological status for causal explanantia: “(c)onsider, for example, the causal interactions involved in Brownian motion. According to Einstein’s theoretical account of this phenomenon, the microscopic particle undergoes many collisions with the molecules of the fluid in which it is suspended. If there are no such things as molecules, then we have a radically inaccurate account of the mechanism. […] For the ontic approach, any causal mechanism that is invoked for explanatory purposes must be taken to be real. If we are not prepared to assert its existence, we cannot attribute explanatory force either to that mechanism or to any theory that involves it. […] The tooth fairy does not explain anything”. |
10. | Effective ontic structural realism, as outlined by [29], seems to be especially close to what Janssen has in mind. |
11. | |
12. | Permissiveness and liberalism as far as apriori/philosophical constraints on explanations are concerned seem prudent not only vis-à-vis Janssen’s primacy of scientific practice (to which we are largely sympathetic, see also [36]), but also vis-à-vis the proliferation of models of explanation and forms of explanatory reasoning (including non-causal explanations), flourishing in the philosophy of science literature. |
13. | This liberalism dovetails Janssen’s comment elsewhere ([1], p. 458, fn. 2): he seems to recognise the context-sensitivity of what counts as an explanation. Following van Fraassen ([12], Ch. 5.2.8), he characterises explanations as answers to a ‘why’-question in a given context of inquiry. This liberalism is also congenial to our subsequent extension of explanations to coherence relations. |
14. | In the introduction of one of his annus mirabilis papers, Einstein ([37], p. 368) writes: “(i)t seems to me that the observations associated with blackbody radiation, fluorescence, the production of cathode rays by ultraviolet light, and other related phenomena connected with the emission or transformation of light are more readily understood if one assumes that the energy of light is discontinuously distributed in space”. |
15. | The term is modelled after Currie’s [10,46,47] notion of “methodological omnivory”, the practice of historical scientists (paleobiologists, archaeologists, etc.) to “(utilise) multiple and disparate methods to generate evidence streams” by “opportunistically exploiting what resources are available” ([46], p. 198) or “(squeezing) all the empirical juice they can from whatever sources are available” ([10], p. 297). |
16. | |
17. | The quasi-inductive argument for COIs shares key difficulties with those of Laudan’s “normative naturalism” (as discussed by [53], sect. 11). |
18. | |
19. | Such exegetical issues aside, Janssen explicitly ([1], p. 471) considers it a natural follow-up question to what extent COIs “yield normative prescriptions for current scientific practice—or even criteria for funding decisions”. |
20. | It goes without saying that, like all non-deductive inferences, even rational applications of IBE involve inductive risk. No non-deductive inference rule has a guarantee of truth ([56], p. 232). |
21. | In recent presentations of his work, Janssen himself has adopted this view (cf., e.g., [65], p. 3266, fn. 3). |
22. | Note that no particular account of explanation is stipulated ([11], p. 3126). “Explanation” should here be construed broadly. It ought to include also the form of conceptual integration, usually labelled “accommodation” (e.g., [38,69,78]). We side with Janssen: caution and non-presumptuousness counsel maximal permissiveness, especially vis-à-vis scientific practice. |
23. | An example of a COI that does not count as pursuit-worthy because it purchases some gain in explanatory-unificatory coherence by sacrificing substantial coherence in other areas (in this case: the factual and theoretical background knowledge of relativistic physics and cosmology) is MOND, an alternative to the Dark Matter hypothesis (Section 5.2). See [80] for a detailed analysis. Another example from cosmology is the Steady State model of the universe in the aftermath of the 1964 discovery of the Cosmic Microwave Background radiation (see, e.g., [81], for details): any claims to empirical adequacy would be purchased by significant ad-hocness liabilities in a coherentist sense ([5], Ch. 5). A similar case (op.cit., p. 142), of special interest—last but not least since Janssen himself discusses it ([1], p. 497; [19])—is Lorentz’s ether contraction hypothesis. |
24. | |
25. | Right at the end of his paper, Janssen ([1], p. 514) seems to backtrack on his earlier (SUPREME EXPLANATORY POWER): COIs are “(risky propositions) at the frontiers of science. […] All one can ask for is the presence of safeguards against garden paths.” We whole-heartedly concur with this characterisation, a paraphrase of (HOPEFUL REALISM). |
26. | |
27. | In Dark Matter research, candidates such as WIMPs and axions have long received privileged attention. WIMPs have been extensively investigated because they arise naturally in extensions of the Standard Model, such as supersymmetry, and because of the so-called “WIMP miracle”: their thermal freeze-out from the early universe plasma generically produces a relic density remarkably close to the observed Dark Matter density. Similarly, axions have received attention due to their ability to solve what is known as the strong CP problem: one of the mysteries of the current standard model of particle physics as the standard model symmetries allow CP violation. However, no violation has been observed to-date. Axions can kill two birds with one stone, both offering a promising Dark Matter candidate and dynamically resolving the strong CP problem by cancelling the CP violating term. Despite extensive searches, attempts to detect these Dark Matter candidates have all met with failure, driving a sense of “crisis” in some circles and led physicists to pursue alternatives the particle dark matter paradigm such as scalar field proposals, primordial black holes, or even modified gravity [105]. Despite such powerful constraints tying together empirical clues in cosmology and theoretical puzzles from particle physics, the COI does not guarantee success. It still may, as direct detection experiments proceed to this day, but the lack of success so far merely highlights that COIs are best understood in the context of pursuit. |
28. | We would be remiss to not mention one of the most exciting very recent developments: the latest data combining measurements from the CMB, supernovae, and baryonic acoustic oscillations displays a notable preference for dynamical explanation of Dark Energy phenomenology over the cosmological constant [119]. While these results are still preliminary and must await further data and analysis before any strong conclusions can be drawn, much of the analysis in this paper regarding COI* reasoning in the context of the Dark Energy problem would still hold. For example, the most straightforward candidate for dynamical Dark Energy would be a so-called thawing scalar field known as quintessence. Such quintessence models (see, e.g., [120] approximate a cosmological constant at early times when the field is frozen, but then begin to evolve only at recent times. These models would preserve GR, while still offering a similar COI* story regarding constraints surrounding the growth of cosmic structure, the missing energy component in the CMB to obtain a flat universe, and luminosity distance measurements for supernovae, etc. |
29. | As in the case of Dark Matter (Section 5.1.2), (HOPEFUL REALISM) with its reticence about any strong ontological commitments seems appropriate for Dark Energy. In this spirit, for instance, Turner ([121], p. 1261) flags the provisional makeshift nature of the cosmological standard model, with its Dark Energy and Matter ingredients: “at best incomplete and at worst a phenomenological construct that accommodates the data” (see also, e.g., [40] for a sustained plea for “healthy scepticism”, especially in light of various tensions and anomalies). (HOPEFUL REALISM) also seems a judicious stance vis-à-vis the underdetermination of theories accounting for Dark Energy phenomenology [66,122,123]. |
30. | This stabilisation and mutual consistency are mirrored in another common name for the CDM model: “the concordance model”. |
31. | Advocates of the virtue-economic account of pursuit-worthiness will add that as compared to generalisations/extensions of, or distinct alternatives to, General Relativity (see, e.g., [101], esp. Ch. 5) General Relativity with a non-vanishing is the mathematically simplest option (see [66] for details). The mathematical complexities of those alternatives tend to be formidable; their application even to standard tests of General Relativity in the solar system poses knotty challenges. The cognitive costs of pursuing General Relativity with a non-zero cosmological constant pale by comparison to those of pursuing most alternatives. That said, a non-zero cosmological constant creates more complexity (or, depending on one’s viewpoint: structural richness) than standard General Relativity with (see, e.g., [124]). |
32. | More recently, “(i)nflation became detached from the initial [GUTs] for several reasons. First, there are several independent ways to generate an effective period of inflation, that all utilise different speculative physics at high energies. Inflation was therefore thought to be a more general feature of high-energy physics, and not explicitly dependent on grand unification. Second, there is mounting evidence that grand unified theories are not true of our world, so a theory of inflation tied to grand unified theory is unlikely to be successful” [133]. |
33. | Here, one should mention “the modern version of the horizon problem” ([141], p. 139): not only near-uniformity, but also the more fine-grained structure “beneath”: measured correlations between parts of the CMB that, according to the HBB-model, ought to be causally separated. Inflation accounts for these correlations, too (op.cit., Ch.4. 2.4). How staggering inflation’s ability to account for these correlations—arguably a novel prediction—is evocatively recounted by Guth ([142], p. 9): “(w)hen my colleagues and I were trying to calculate the spectrum of density perturbations from inflation in 1982, I never believed for a moment that it would be measured in my lifetime. Perhaps the few lowest moments would be measured, but certainly not enough to determine a spectrum. But I was wrong. The fluctuations in the CMB have now been measured to exquisite detail, and even better measurements are in the offing.” |
34. | Here, we will not join the recent fray over the evidential status of inflation (i.e., how it fares within the context of acceptance); see, however, [139,143,144,145,146], [83], sect. 3 for philosophical commentaries. We emphasise that despite inflation’s impressive explanatory power, a few novel predictions, and coherence with well-motivated ideas in high-energy theory, it remains a speculative idea. Integrating the inflaton into particle physics will be a daunting challenge for going forward (see also [147]). Recent CMB data have disfavoured many of the simplest realisations of inflation. This necessitates a move towards more complicated models with more parameters and fine-tuning. This has led a minority of cosmologists to question the inflation paradigm and explore alternatives (see [143] for critical remarks and [139] for a rebuttal). Inflation remains by far the most popular and promising framework with which to model the early universe. These concerns highlight that the common origin inferences that make inflation so tantalising are best understood in the context of pursuit—with no guarantee of ultimate success—rather than acceptance or confirmation. |
35. | Despite regarding it as “the most important idea in cosmology since the big bang itself”, Turner ([121], p. 9), for instance, qualifies its status: “inflation is not yet a well-formulated, complete theory, and there is no standard model of inflation. At best, we have a rudimentary description of inflation.” |
36. | Even staunch champions of inflation are most naturally understood as making a claim about pursuit, rather than acceptance. According to Guth et al. ([139], p. 118), for instance, inflation “provides a self-consistent framework with which we may explain several empirical features of our observed universe to very good precision, while continuing to pursue long-standing questions about the dynamics and evolution of our universe at energy scales that have, to date, eluded direct observation”. |
37. | |
38. |
References
- Janssen, M. COI Stories: Explanation and Evidence in the History of Science. Perspect. Sci. 2002, 10, 457–522. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McAllister, J.W. Using History as Evidence in Philosophy of Science: A Methodological Critique. J. Philos. Hist. 2018, 12, 239–258. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dimitrakos, T. Confrontation and Its Problems: Can the History of Science Provide Evidence for the Philosophy of Science? J. Philos. Hist. 2020, 15, 182–213. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Barseghyan, H. The Laws of Scientific Change; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Switzerland, 2015; ISBN 978-3-319-17595-9. [Google Scholar]
- Schindler, S. Theoretical Virtues in Science: Uncovering Reality Through Theory, 1st ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2018; ISBN 978-1-108-38135-2. [Google Scholar]
- Kuhn, T.S. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1996; ISBN 978-0-226-45808-3. [Google Scholar]
- Cleland, C.E. Common Cause Explanation and the Search for a Smoking Gun. In Rethinking the Fabric of Geology; Geological Society of America: Boulder, CO, USA, 2013; ISBN 978-0-8137-2502-4. [Google Scholar]
- Cleland, C.E. Prediction and Explanation in Historical Natural Science. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2011, 62, 551–582. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tucker, A. Our Knowledge of the Past: A Philosophy of Historiography, 1st ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2004; ISBN 978-0-521-83415-5. [Google Scholar]
- Currie, A. Rock, Bone, and Ruin: An Optimist’s Guide to the Historical Sciences; The MIT Press: Cambridge, UK, 2018; ISBN 978-0-262-34415-9. [Google Scholar]
- Šešelja, D.; Straßer, C. Kuhn and the Question of Pursuit Worthiness. Topoi 2013, 32, 9–19. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Van Fraassen, B.C. The Scientific Image; Clarendon library of logic and philosophy; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1980; ISBN 978-0-19-824427-1. [Google Scholar]
- Van Fraassen, B.C. Belief and the Will. J. Philos. 1984, 81, 235. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Peebles, P.J.E. The Physicists Philosophy of Physics. arXiv 2024, arXiv:2401.16506. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Salmon, W.C. Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1984; ISBN 978-0-691-22148-9. [Google Scholar]
- Salmon, W.C. Scientific Explanation: Three Basic Conceptions. PSA Proc. Bienn. Meet. Philos. Sci. Assoc. 1984, 1984, 293–305. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kitcher, P. Explanatory Unification and the Causal Structure of the World. Minn. Stud. Philos. Sci. 1989, 13, 410–505. [Google Scholar]
- Hüttemann, A. Ursachen; De Gruyter: Berlin, Germany, 2018; ISBN 978-3-11-059482-9. [Google Scholar]
- Janssen, M. Reconsidering a Scientific Revolution: The Case of Einstein versus Lorentz. Phys. Perspect. PIP 2002, 4, 421–446. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Janssen, M. Drawing the Line between Kinematics and Dynamics in Special Relativity. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. Part B Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 2009, 40, 26–52. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dorato, M.; Felline, L. Structural Explanations in Minkowski Spacetime: Which Account of Models? In Space, Time, and Spacetime; Petkov, V., Ed.; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2010; pp. 193–207. ISBN 978-3-642-13537-8. [Google Scholar]
- Explanation Beyond Causation: Philosophical Perspectives on Non-Causal Explanations, 1st ed.; Reutlinger, A., Saatsi, J., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018; ISBN 978-0-19-877794-6. [Google Scholar]
- Beckermann, A. Analytische Einführung in Die Philosophie des Geistes; De Gruyter Studienbuch; 3., aktualisierte und erweiterte Auflage; De Gruyter: Berlin, Germany, 2008; ISBN 978-3-11-020993-8. [Google Scholar]
- Weatherall, J.O. On (Some) Explanations in Physics. Philos. Sci. 2011, 78, 421–447. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sober, E. Equilibrium Explanation. Philos. Stud. 1983, 43, 201–210. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Curiel, E. The Constraints General Relativity Places on Physicalist Accounts of Causality. Theor. Rev. Teoría Hist. Fundam. Cienc. 2000, 15, 33–58. [Google Scholar]
- Vassallo, A. Dependence Relations in General Relativity. Eur. J. Philos. Sci. 2020, 10, 2. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ladyman, J. Structural Realism. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Zalta, E.N., Nodelman, U., Eds.; Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2023. [Google Scholar]
- Ladyman, J.; Lorenzetti, L. Effective Ontic Structural Realism. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2023, 729061. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ladyman, J.; Ross, D.; With John Collier, A.D.S. Every Thing Must Go; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2007; ISBN 978-0-19-927619-6. [Google Scholar]
- Bartelborth, T. Erklären; De Gruyter: Berlin, Germany, 2007; ISBN 978-3-11-019433-3. [Google Scholar]
- Woodward, J. Making Things Happen: A Theory of Causal Explanation, 1st ed.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2004; ISBN 978-0-19-515527-3. [Google Scholar]
- Scheibe, E. Die Philosophie Der Physiker; Beck’sche reihe; C.H. Beck: Munich, Germany, 2007; ISBN 978-3-406-54788-1. [Google Scholar]
- Norton, J. Causation as Folk Science. Philos. Impr. 2003, 3, 1–22. [Google Scholar]
- Norton, J.D. Is There an Independent Principle of Causality in Physics. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2009, 60, 475–486. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ben-Menahem, Y. Causation in Science; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2018; ISBN 978-0-691-17493-8. [Google Scholar]
- Einstein, A. Über Einen Die Erzeugung Und Verwandlung Des Lichtes Betreffenden Heuristischen Gesichtspunkt. Ann. Phys. 1905, 322, 132–148. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Barnes, E.C. Prediction versus Accommodation. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Zalta, E.N., Nodelman, U., Eds.; Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2022. [Google Scholar]
- Ruphy, S. La Classification Des Étoiles: Un Nouvel Allié Pour Le Pluralisme Taxinomique. In La Philosophie de la Physique.; Syllepse: Geneva, Switzerland, 2010; pp. 274–294. [Google Scholar]
- Scott, D. The Standard Model of Cosmology: A Skeptic’s Guide; IOS Press: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2018. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ellis, G. The Standard Cosmological Model: Achievements and Issues. Found. Phys. 2018, 48, 1226–1245. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Elgin, C.Z. Considered Judgment; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1996; ISBN 978-0-691-02879-8. [Google Scholar]
- Elgin, C.Z. True Enough; The MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2017; ISBN 978-0-262-34138-7. [Google Scholar]
- Dellsén, F. Beyond Explanation: Understanding as Dependency Modelling. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2020, 71, 1261–1286. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Duerr, P.M.; Dellsén, F. Progress and Modern Cosmology. Eur. J. Philos. Sci. (Forthcom.), 2025. [Google Scholar]
- Currie, A. Marsupial Lions and Methodological Omnivory: Function, Success and Reconstruction in Paleobiology. Biol. Philos. 2015, 30, 187–209. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Currie, A. Hot-Blooded Gluttons: Dependency, Coherence, and Method in the Historical Sciences. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2017, 68, 929–952. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Elgin, C. Weaving the Web of Belief. In Contemporary Debates in Epistemology (Forthcoming); Steup, M., Ed.; Blackwell: Malden, MA, USA.
- Nyrup, R. Of Water Drops and Atomic Nuclei: Analogies and Pursuit Worthiness in Science. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2020, 71, 881–903. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Furlan, S.; Gaudenzi, R. The Earth Vibrates with Analogies: The Dirac Sea and the Geology of the Vacuum. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 2022, 93, 163–174. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Van Fraassen, B.C. Laws and Symmetry, 1st ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1989; ISBN 978-0-19-824860-6. [Google Scholar]
- Cabrera, F. Inference to the Best Explanation—An Overview. In Handbook of Abductive Cognition; Magnani, L., Ed.; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2022; pp. 1–37. [Google Scholar]
- Nola, R.; Sankey, H. A Selective Survey of Theories of Scientific Method. In After Popper, Kuhn and Feyerabend: Recent Issues in Theories of Scientific Method; Nola, R., Sankey, H., Eds.; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2000; pp. 1–65. ISBN 978-94-011-3935-9. [Google Scholar]
- Nanay, B. Rational Reconstruction Reconsidered. Monist 2010, 93, 598–617. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nanay, B. Internal History versus External History. Philosophy 2017, 92, 207–230. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ben-Menahem, Y. The Inference to the Best Explanation. Erkenntnis 1990, 33, 319–344. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Norton, J.D. The Material Theory of Induction; BSPS Open Ser; University of Calgary Press: Calgary, Canada, 2021; ISBN 978-1-77385-255-3. [Google Scholar]
- Currie, A. Scientific Knowledge and the Deep Past: History Matters, 1st ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2019; ISBN 978-1-108-58249-0. [Google Scholar]
- McKaughan, D.J. From Ugly Duckling to Swan: C. S. Peirce, Abduction, and the Pursuit of Scientific Theories. Trans. Charles Peirce Soc. 2008, 44, 446–468. [Google Scholar]
- Nyrup, R. How Explanatory Reasoning Justifies Pursuit: A Peircean View of IBE. Philos. Sci. 2015, 82, 749–760. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Laudan, L. Progress and Its Problems: Towards a Theory of Scientific Growth; 1st paperback print; University of California Press: Berkeley, CA, USA, 1978; ISBN 978-0-520-03721-2. [Google Scholar]
- Laudan, L. Beyond Positivism and Relativism: Theory, Method and Evidence; Westview Press: Oxford, UK, 1996; ISBN 978-0-8133-2469-2. [Google Scholar]
- Barseghyan, H.; Shaw, J. How Can a Taxonomy of Stances Help Clarify Classical Debates on Scientific Change? Philosophies 2017, 2, 24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kao, M. Unification and the Quantum Hypothesis in 1900–1913. Philos. Sci. 2015, 82, 1200–1210. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kao, M. Unification beyond Justification: A Strategy for Theory Development. Synthese 2019, 196, 3263–3278. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wolf, W.J.; Duerr, P.M. Promising Stabs in the Dark: Theory Virtues and Pursuit-Worthiness in the Dark Energy Problem. Synthese 2024, 204, 155. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Castellani, E.; Dardashti, R.; Dawid, R. Unification and Surprise: On the Confirmatory Reach of Unification, Preprint. 2025. Available online: https://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/24651/ (accessed on 18 August 2025).
- Crupi, V. Confirmation. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Zalta, E.N., Nodelman, U., Eds.; Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Dellsén, F. An Epistemic Advantage of Accommodation over Prediction. Philos. Impr. 2025, 25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kuhn, T.S. Objectivity, Value Judgment, and Theory Choice. In The Essential Tension—Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change; The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1977; pp. 320–339. [Google Scholar]
- McMullin, E. Values in Science. PSA Proc. Bienn. Meet. Philos. Sci. Assoc. 1982, 1982, 3–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McMullin, E. Epistemic Virtues and Theory Appraisal. In Realism in the Sciences; Horsten, L., Douven, I., Eds.; Louvain Philosophical Studies; Leuven University Press: Leuven, Belgium, 1996; pp. 13–34. ISBN 978-90-6186-763-0. [Google Scholar]
- Douglas, H. The Value of Cognitive Values. Philos. Sci. 2013, 80, 796–806. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Carrier, M. Values and Objectivity in Science: Value-Ladenness, Pluralism and the Epistemic Attitude. Sci. Educ. 2013, 22, 2547–2568. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Keas, M.N. Systematizing the Theoretical Virtues. Synthese 2018, 195, 2761–2793. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Šešelja, D.; Weber, E. Rationality and Irrationality in the History of Continental Drift: Was the Hypothesis of Continental Drift Worthy of Pursuit? Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. Part A 2012, 43, 147–159. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- BonJour, L. The Structure of Empirical Knowledge; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1985. [Google Scholar]
- Douglas, H.; Magnus, P.D. State of the Field: Why Novel Prediction Matters. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. Part A 2013, 44, 580–589. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Seselja, D.; Kosolosky, L.; Strasser, C. The Rationality of Scientific Reasoning in the Context of Pursuit: Drawing Appropriate Distinctions. Philosophica 2012, 86. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Duerr, P.M.; Wolf, W.J. Methodological Reflections on the MOND/Dark Matter Debate. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 2023, 101, 1–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kragh, H.S. Steady-State Theory and the Cosmological Controversy. In The Oxford Handbook of the History of Modern Cosmology; Kragh, H., Longair, M., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2019; pp. 162–205. ISBN 978-0-19-881766-6. [Google Scholar]
- Duerr, P.M.; Fischer, E. Rationally Warranted Promise: The Virtue-Economic Account of Pursuit-Worthiness. Synthese 2025, 206, 68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wolf, W.J.; Duerr, P.M. The Virtues of Pursuit-Worthy Speculation: The Promises of Cosmic Inflation. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2023, 728263. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fischer, E. No-Lose Theorems and the Pursuitworthiness of Experiments, Preprint. 2024. Available online: https://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/23856/1/NLT.pdf (accessed on 18 August 2025).
- Baumberger, C.; Beisbart, C.; Brun, G. What Is Understanding? An Overview of Recent Debates in Epistemology and Philosophy of Science. In Explaining Understanding; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 2016; ISBN 978-1-315-68611-0. [Google Scholar]
- De Regt, H.W. Can Scientific Understanding Be Reduced to Knowledge? In Scientific Understanding and Representation; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 2022; ISBN 978-1-003-20290-5. [Google Scholar]
- Lakatos, I. The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes: Philosophical Papers, 1st ed.; Worrall, J., Currie, G., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1978; ISBN 978-0-521-21644-9. [Google Scholar]
- Worrall, J. Pragmatic Factors in Theory-Acceptance. In A Companion to the Philosophy of Science; Newton-Smith, W., Ed.; Blackwell: Oxford, UK, 2000; pp. 349–357. [Google Scholar]
- De Swart, J.G.; Bertone, G.; Van Dongen, J. How Dark Matter Came to Matter. Nat. Astron. 2017, 1, 0059. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Longair, M.S.; Smeenk, C. Inflation, Dark Matter, and Dark Energy. In The Oxford Handbook of the History of Modern Cosmology; Kragh, H., Longair, M.S., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2019; pp. 424–464. ISBN 978-0-19-881766-6. [Google Scholar]
- Eisenstaedt, J. The Low Water Mark of General Relativity, 1925–1955. In Einstein and the History of General Relativity; Howard, D., Stachel, J., Eds.; Birkhäuser: Basel, Switzerland, 1989; pp. 277–292. [Google Scholar]
- Longair, M.S. Relativistic Astrophysics and Cosmology. In The Oxford Handbook of the History of Modern Cosmology; Kragh, H., Longair, M.S., Eds.; Oxford handbooks; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2019; ISBN 978-0-19-881766-6. [Google Scholar]
- Longair, M.S. The Cosmic Microwave Background: From Discovery to Precision Cosmology. In The Oxford Handbook of the History of Modern Cosmology; Kragh, H., Longair, M.S., Eds.; Oxford handbooks; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2019; ISBN 978-0-19-881766-6. [Google Scholar]
- De Swart, J. Closing in on the Cosmos: Cosmology’s Rebirth and the Rise of the Dark Matter Problem. arXiv 2019, arXiv:1903.05281. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ostriker, J.P.; Peebles, P.J.E.; Yahil, A. The Size and Mass of Galaxies, and the Mass of the Universe. Astrophys. J. 1974, 193, L1. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Turner, M.S.; KICP/UChicago; Foundation, T.K. Understanding BBN: The Physics and Its History. arXiv 2021, arXiv:2111.14254. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bertone, G.; Hooper, D. History of Dark Matter. Rev. Mod. Phys. 2018, 90, 045002. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Partridge, R.B. The Cosmic Microwave Background: From Discovery to Precision Cosmology. In The Oxford Handbook of the History of Modern Cosmology; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2019. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Martens, N.C.M. Dark Matter Realism. Found. Phys. 2022, 52, 16. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Allzén, S. Modest Scientific Realism and Belief in Astronomical Entities. 2022. Available online: https://www.diva-portal.org/smash/record.jsf?dswid=6853&pid=diva2%3A1686091 (accessed on 18 August 2025).
- Will, C.M. Theory and Experiment in Gravitational Physics, 2nd ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2018; ISBN 978-1-316-33861-2. [Google Scholar]
- Ishak, M. Testing General Relativity in Cosmology. Living Rev. Relativ. 2019, 22, 1. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Quine, W.V.O. Philosophy of Logic; Prentice-Hall: Englewood Cliffs, NJ, USA, 1970. [Google Scholar]
- Smith, G.E. Closing the Loop: Testing Newtonian Gravity, Then and Now. In Newton and Empiricism; Biener, Z., Schliesser, E., Eds.; Oxford University Press USA—OSO: New York, NY, USA, 2014; pp. 262–352. ISBN 978-0-19-933709-5. [Google Scholar]
- Bertone, G.; Tait, T.M.P. A New Era in the Search for Dark Matter. Nature 2018, 562, 51–56. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Weinberg, S. Gravitation and Cosmology: Principles and Applications of the General Theory of Relativity; Wiley: New York, NY, USA, 1972; ISBN 978-0-471-92567-5. [Google Scholar]
- Smeenk, C. Einstein’s Role in the Creation of Relativistic Cosmology. In The Cambridge Companion to Einstein; Janssen, M., Lehner, C., Eds.; Cambridge Companions to Philosophy; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2014; pp. 228–269. ISBN 978-0-521-82834-5. [Google Scholar]
- O’Raifeartaigh, C.; O’Keeffe, M.; Nahm, W.; Mitton, S. Einstein’s 1917 Static Model of the Universe: A Centennial Review. Eur. Phys. J. H 2017, 42, 431–474. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- O’Raifeartaigh, C.; O’Keeffe, M.; Mitton, S. Historical and Philosophical Reflections on the Einstein-de Sitter Model. Eur. Phys. J. H 2021, 46, 4. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- O’Raifeartaigh, C.; O’Keeffe, M.; Nahm, W.; Mitton, S. One Hundred Years of the Cosmological Constant: From “Superfluous Stunt” to Dark Energy. Eur. Phys. J. H 2018, 43, 73–117. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kragh, H. Cosmology and Controversy: The Historical Development of Two Theories of the Universe; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1996; ISBN 978-0-691-22771-9. [Google Scholar]
- Eddington, A.S. On the Instability of Einstein’s Spherical World. Mon. Not. R. Astron. Soc. 1930, 90, 668–678. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Eddington, A. The Expanding Universe. Nature 1933, 131, 637–638. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Luminet, J.-P. Editorial Note to: Georges Lemaître, A Homogeneous Universe of Constant Mass and Increasing Radius Accounting for the Radial Velocity of Extra-Galactic Nebulae. Gen. Relativ. Gravit. 2013, 45, 1619–1633. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lemaître, A.G. Contributions to a British Association Discussion on the Evolution of the Universe. Nature 1931, 128, 704–706. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Earman, J. Lambda: The Constant That Refuses to Die. Arch. Hist. Exact Sci. 2001, 55, 189–220. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Calder, L.; Lahav, O. Dark Energy: How the Paradigm Shifted. Phys. World 2010, 23, 32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lahav, O. Dark Energy: Is It ‘Just’ Einstein’s Cosmological Constant Λ? Contemp. Phys. 2020, 61, 132–145. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- DESI Collaboration; Abdul-Karim, M.; Aguilar, J.; Ahlen, S.; Alam, S.; Allen, L.; Prieto, C.A.; Alves, O.; Anand, A.; Andrade, U.; et al. DESI DR2 Results II: Measurements of Baryon Acoustic Oscillations and Cosmological Constraints. arXiv 2025, arXiv:2503.14738. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chiba, T. Slow-Roll Thawing Quintessence. Phys. Rev. D 2009, 79, 083517. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Turner, M.S. $$\Lambda $$CDM: Much More Than We Expected, but Now Less Than What We Want. Found. Phys. 2018, 48, 1261–1278. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wolf, W.J.; Read, J. Navigating Permanent Underdetermination in Dark Energy and Inflationary Cosmology. arXiv 2025, arXiv:2501.13521. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ferreira, P.G.; Wolf, W.J.; Read, J. The Spectre of Underdetermination in Modern Cosmology. arXiv 2025, arXiv:2501.06095. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Belot, G. Accelerating Expansion: Philosophy and Physics with a Positive Cosmological Constant; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2023; ISBN 978-0-19-286646-2. [Google Scholar]
- Peebles, P.J.E. Tests of Cosmological Models Constrained by Inflation. Astrophys. J. 1984, 284, 439. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rugh, S.E.; Zinkernagel, H. The Quantum Vacuum and the Cosmological Constant Problem. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. Part B Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 2002, 33, 663–705. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kragh, H. Conceptions of Cosmos: From Myths to the Accelerating Universe: A History of Cosmology; 1. publ. in paperback; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013; ISBN 978-0-19-966514-3. [Google Scholar]
- Nussbaumer, H.; Bieri, L. Discovering the Expanding Universe; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2009; ISBN 978-0-521-51484-2. [Google Scholar]
- Peebles, P.J.E.; Yu, J.T. Primeval Adiabatic Perturbation in an Expanding Universe. Astrophys. J. 1970, 162, 815. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Misner, C.W. The Isotropy of the Universe. Astrophys. J. 1968, 151, 431. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dicke, R.H.; Peebles, P.J.E. The Big Bang Cosmology—Enigmas and Nostrums; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1979; pp. 504–517. [Google Scholar]
- Dicke, R.H. Gravitation and the Universe; American philosophical society: Memoirs of the american philosophical society; American Philosophical Society: Philadelphia, PA, USA, 1970; ISBN 978-0-87169-078-4. [Google Scholar]
- Koberinski, A. How Cosmic Inflation Came to Be a Paradigm Without a Theory. Available online: https://iai.tv/articles/cosmic-inflation-the-paradigm-without-a-theory-auid-3028 (accessed on 18 August 2025).
- Blau, S.K.; Guth, A.H. Inflationary Cosmology. In Three Hundred Years of Gravitation; Harvard University: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1987; pp. 524–603. [Google Scholar]
- Guth, A.H. Inflationary Universe: A Possible Solution to the Horizon and Flatness Problems. Phys. Rev. D 1981, 23, 347–356. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Starobinsky, A.A. A New Type of Isotropic Cosmological Models without Singularity. Phys. Lett. B 1980, 91, 99–102. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Smeenk, C. Inflation and the Origins of Structure. In Beyond Einstein; Rowe, D.E., Sauer, T., Walter, S.A., Eds.; Einstein Studies; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2018; Volume 14, pp. 205–241. ISBN 978-1-4939-7706-2. [Google Scholar]
- Planck Collaboration; Akrami, Y.; Arroja, F.; Ashdown, M.; Aumont, J.; Baccigalupi, C.; Ballardini, M.; Banday, A.J.; Barreiro, R.B.; Bartolo, N.; et al. Planck 2018 Results: X. Constraints on Inflation. Astron. Astrophys. 2020, 641, A10. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Guth, A.H.; Kaiser, D.I.; Nomura, Y. Inflationary Paradigm after Planck 2013. Phys. Lett. B 2014, 733, 112–119. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Smeenk, C. False Vacuum: Early Universe Cosmology and the Development of Inflation. In The Universe of General Relativity; Kox, A.J., Eisenstaedt, J., Eds.; Birkhäuser Boston: Boston, MA, USA, 2005; pp. 223–257. ISBN 978-0-8176-4380-5. [Google Scholar]
- Baumann, D. Cosmology; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2022; ISBN 978-1-108-93709-2. [Google Scholar]
- Guth, A.H. Inflation. In Measuring and Modeling the Universe; Freedman, W.L., Ed.; Carnegie Observatories Astrophysics Series; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2004; Volume 2, ISBN 978-0-521-75576-4. [Google Scholar]
- Ijjas, A.; Steinhardt, P.J.; Loeb, A. Inflationary Paradigm in Trouble after Planck2013. Phys. Lett. B 2013, 723, 261–266. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ijjas, A.; Steinhardt, P.J.; Loeb, A. Inflationary Schism. Phys. Lett. B 2014, 736, 142–146. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wolf, W.J. Cosmological Inflation and Meta-Empirical Theory Assessment. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 2024, 103, 146–158. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Dawid, R.; McCoy, C. Testability and Viability: Is Inflationary Cosmology “Scientific”? Eur. J. Philos. Sci. 2023, 13, 51. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Koberinski, A.; Smeenk, C. Establishing a Theory of Inflationary Cosmology. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2024, 733886. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Martin, J.; Ringeval, C.; Vennin, V. Encyclopædia Inflationaris. Phys. Dark Universe 2014, 5–6, 75–235. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Smeenk, C. Testing Inflation. In The Philosophy of Cosmology; Chamcham, K., Silk, J., Barrow, J.D., Saunders, S., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2017; pp. 206–227. ISBN 978-1-107-14539-9. [Google Scholar]
- Peebles, P.J.E. Principles of Physical Cosmology, 1st ed.; Princeton Series in Physics Series; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1993; ISBN 978-0-691-20981-4. [Google Scholar]
- Guth, A.H. The Inflationary Universe: The Quest for a New Theory of Cosmic Origins; Helix Books; 1. printing; Addison-Wesley: Reading, MA, USA, 1997; ISBN 978-0-201-14942-5. [Google Scholar]
- Guth, A.H.; Steinhardt, P.J. The Inflationary Universe. Sci. Am. 1984, 250, 116–129. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Maudlin, T. The Metaphysics Within Physics; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2009; ISBN 978-0-19-957537-4. [Google Scholar]
- Wolf, W.J.; Thébault, K.P.Y. Explanatory Depth in Primordial Cosmology: A Comparative Study of Inflationary and Bouncing Paradigms. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2023, 725096. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Abazajian, K.N.; Adshead, P.; Ahmed, Z.; Allen, S.W.; Alonso, D.; Arnold, K.S.; Baccigalupi, C.; Bartlett, J.G.; Battaglia, N.; Benson, B.A.; et al. CMB-S4 Science Book, First Edition. arXiv 2016, arXiv:1610.02743. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brandenberger, R.H.; Martin, J. Trans-Planckian Issues for Inflationary Cosmology. Class. Quantum Gravity 2013, 30, 113001. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Martin, J.; Brandenberger, R.H. Trans-Planckian Problem of Inflationary Cosmology. Phys. Rev. D 2001, 63, 123501. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Martin, J.; Brandenberger, R. Dependence of the Spectra of Fluctuations in Inflationary Cosmology on Trans-Planckian Physics. Phys. Rev. D 2003, 68, 063513. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cicoli, M.; Conlon, J.P.; Maharana, A.; Parameswaran, S.; Quevedo, F.; Zavala, I. String Cosmology: From the Early Universe to Today. Phys. Rep. 2024, 1059, 1–155. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Duerr, P.M.; Wolf, W.J. Cosmic Conundrums, Common Origins, and Omnivorous Constraints. Philosophies 2025, 10, 101. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10050101
Duerr PM, Wolf WJ. Cosmic Conundrums, Common Origins, and Omnivorous Constraints. Philosophies. 2025; 10(5):101. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10050101
Chicago/Turabian StyleDuerr, Patrick M., and William J. Wolf. 2025. "Cosmic Conundrums, Common Origins, and Omnivorous Constraints" Philosophies 10, no. 5: 101. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10050101
APA StyleDuerr, P. M., & Wolf, W. J. (2025). Cosmic Conundrums, Common Origins, and Omnivorous Constraints. Philosophies, 10(5), 101. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10050101