Hegel’s Souls: Aristotle, Kant, and the Climax of Life
Abstract
1. Introduction
One reason for treating of Aristotle in detail rests in the fact that no philosopher has had so much wrong done him by the thoughtless traditions which have been received respecting his philosophy, and which are still the order of the day, although for centuries he was the instructor of all philosophers. For to him views are ascribed diametrically opposite to his philosophy. And while Plato is much read, the treasures contained in Aristotle have for centuries, and until quite modern times, been as good as unknown, and the falsest prejudices reign respecting him [3] (p. 118)1.
Aristotle’s books on the soul, along with his essays on particular aspects and states of the soul, are for this reason [for their speculative approach on the issue—AK] still the most admirable, even the sole, work of speculative interest on this topic. The essential aim of a philosophy of Spirit can only be to introduce again into the knowledge of spirit, and so also to disclose once more the sense of those Aristotelian books [6] (pp. 4–5, § 378; translation adjusted).
Aristotle’s conception of nature is, however, nobler than that of today, for with him the principal point is the determination of end as the inward determinateness of natural things. Thus, he comprehended nature as life, i.e., as that which has its end within itself, is unity with itself, which does not pass into another, but, through this principle of activity, determines changes in conformity with its own content, and in this way, maintains itself therein. In this doctrine, Aristotle has before his eyes the inward immanent end, to which he considers necessity an external condition [3] (p. 157)10.
2. Aristotle’s Soul, Kant’s Organism
In Aristotle’s teaching on this subject, we must not expect to find so-called metaphysics of the soul. For metaphysical handling such as this really presupposes the soul as a thing, and asks, for example, what sort of a thing it is, whether it is simple, and so on. Aristotle did not busy his concrete, speculative mind with abstract questions such as these, but, as already remarked, he deals rather with the manner of the soul’s activity [.] [3] (pp. 180–181)15.
Today philosophy rarely speaks of soul but, rather, of Spirit. This because Spirit is different than the soul, which [the soul—AK] is, so to say, the middle element between corporeity and Spirit, the bond between the two. The Spirit as soul is immersed in the corporeity [4] (vol. 23.1, p. 187; my translation).
Actuality (entelechy) is an activity (energeia), but [an activity that—AK] is determined in and for itself. This actuality is [according to Aristotle—AK] the essential being [the being that an entity is meant to be—AK] and the being of the soul. It is the substance according to the Concept, or the Concept itself, the form is the substance. If a physical body, an axe, had as its substance to be an axe, which [the axe—AK] is its external form [the form that the substance is—AK], then this [the physical body—AK] would be a soul. If such a body ceased to be an axe, then only the name would remain. But the soul has the principle of order and of movement in itself […] In this way the form is the essence of the soul itself. The eye is, then, the seeing and the eyeball; and in this way it is [the eye—AK] soul and body. The soul is the actuality, the entelechy; the [materiality of the—AK] body [is—AK] only the potentiality [4] (vol. 30.1, p. 108; my translation)30.
[According to Aristotle—AK] [t]he natural [that is, organic—AK] element is a product, it emerges and is equally the subsequent as the antecedent. The product is at the beginning. This is the production of things living. In the case of the mechanical [and of the—AK] chemical element, the product is something other. The self-production is the activity (ενεργεια) [Greek in the original text—AK] [,] the self-preserving [element—AK]. The fundamental determination of [organic—AK] Nature is, therefore: to be an activity according to a purpose, that is no outer purposiveness [4] (vol. 30.2, p. 607; my translation)33.
Further, objective purposiveness, as a principle of the possibility of the things of nature, is so far from being necessarily connected with the concept of the latter that it is rather precisely that to which one refers above all in order to prove the contingency of it (of nature) and of its form. For if one adduces, e.g., the structure of a bird, the hollowness of its bones, the placement of its wings for movement and of its tail for steering, etc., one says that given the mere nexus effectivus in nature, without the help of a special kind of causality, namely that of ends (nexus finalis), this is all in the highest degree contingent: i.e., that nature, considered as a mere mechanism, could have formed itself in a thousand different ways without hitting precisely upon the unity in accordance with such a rule, and that it is therefore only outside the concept of nature, not within it, that one could have even the least ground a priori for hoping to find such a principle [38], (pp. 233–234, § 61) [5: 360].
End is an ideal determination which is already existent beforehand; so that, in the process of realization which must fit in with what exists determinately beforehand; nothing new is developed. The realization is equally a return-into-self. The accomplished End has the same content as that which is already present in the agent; the living creature, therefore, with all its activities does not add anything to it. As the organization [of life] is its own End, so too it is its own Means, it is nothing merely there. The viscera, the organs generally, are perpetually posited as ideal, for they are active against each other: and just as each, as centre, produces itself at the expense of all the others, so it exists only through the process; in other words, that which, as sublated, is reduced to Means is itself End, is itself product. As that which develops the Concept, the animal organism is the Idea manifesting only the differences of the Concept; and thus each moment of the Concept contains the others, is itself system and totality. These totalities, as determinate, produce in their transition the whole which each system is in itself, as a One, as subject [12] (pp. 356–357, § 352, oral addition; translation adjusted)48.
The basic determination of the living being seized on by Aristotle, that it must be conceived as acting purposively, has in modem times been almost forgotten till Kant, in his own way, revived this concept in his doctrine of inner teleology, in which the living being is to be treated as its own end (Selbstzweck). The difficulty here comes mainly from representing the teleological relationship as external, and from the prevalent opinion that an end exists only in consciousness [12] (pp. 388–389, § 361, Remark)49.
The concept is realized as the soul in a body; the soul is the immediate, self-referring universality of the body’s externality just as much as it is the body’s particularization, so that the body expresses no other differences than the determination of the concept, and finally it is the individuality as infinite negativity—the dialectic of the body’s objectivity, [the factors of which are] outside one another, an objectivity that is led back into subjectivity from the semblance of self-sufficient subsistence, so that all members are reciprocally momentary means as much as momentary purposes, while life, inasmuch as it is the inceptive particularization, results in itself as the negative unity that is for itself and, in the dialectic of corporeity (Leiblichkeit), joins itself together only with itself [45] (p. 287, § 216; translation adjusted)50.
As to what concerns more nearly the relation of the three souls, as they may be termed (though they are incorrectly thus distinguished), Aristotle says of them, with perfect truth, that we need to look for no one soul in which all these are found, and which in a definite and simple form is conformable with any one of them. This is a profound observation, by means of which truly speculative thought marks itself out from the thought which is merely logical and formal [3] (p. 185).
In the same way the soul must not be sought for as an abstraction, for in the animate being the nutritive and the sensitive soul are included in the intelligent, but only as its object or its potentiality; similarly, the nutritive soul, which constitutes the nature of plants, is also present in the sensitive soul, but likewise only as being implicit in it, or as the universal. Or the lower soul inheres only in the higher, as a predicate in a subject: and this mere ideal is not to be ranked very high, as is indeed the case in formal thought; that which is for itself is, on the contrary, the never-ceasing return into itself, to which actuality belongs [3] (p. 185).
3. Between Soulless and Ensouled Beings: The Non-Emergence of Life
It has been an inept conception of ancient and also recent Philosophy of Nature to regard the progression and transition of one natural form and sphere into a higher as an outwardly-actual production which, however, to be made clearer, is relegated to the obscurity of the past. It is precisely externality, which is characteristic of Nature, that, is, differences are allowed to fall apart and to appear as indifferent to each other: the dialectical Concept which leads forward the stages, is the inner side of them. A thinking consideration must reject such nebulous, at bottom, sensuous, ideas, as in particular the so-called origination, for example of plants and animals from water, and then the origination of the more highly developed animal organisms from the lower, and so on [12] (p. 20, § 249; translation adjusted)56.
[T] his transition, as Hegel conceives it, is a logical one that hinges on conceptual inner necessity, not a natural one in which chemical processes actually give rise to living organisms at specific points in time […] Hegel holds neither the vitalistic view that organic life ‘emerges’ from an essentially lifeless matter by means of the sudden appearance of a natural productive power of generation (Lebenskraft), nor the hylozoic view that nature in its temporal existence is everywhere really alive in all its parts [53] (p. 203).
The chemical process is, in fact, in general terms, Life; for the individual body in its immediacy is not only produced by the process but also destroyed by it, so that the Concept no longer remains at the stage of inner necessity but is made manifest. But on account of the immediacy of the corporealities entering into chemical process, the Concept is everywhere infected with division. As a result, its moments appear as external conditions, and what is dissociated falls apart into mutually indifferent products, the fire and activation (Begeistung) are extinguished in the neutral body and not spontaneously rekindled in it. The beginning and end of the process are separate and distinct; this constitutes its finitude which keeps it far from Life and distinguishes it there from [12] (p. 269, § 335; translation adjusted)60.
The living body is always on the point of passing over into the chemical process: oxygen, hydrogen, salt, are always about to appear, but are always again sublated; and only at death or in disease is the chemical process able to prevail. The living creature is always exposed to danger, always bears within itself an other, but can endure this contradiction which the inorganic cannot [12] (p. 274, § 337, oral addition).
It [the organism—AK] acts, and reacts against, the most diverse powers (Potenzen); in each reaction it is differently determined, but equally also remains a single unity with itself. This implicit determinateness of a kind now also exists; it enters into relationship with an other, but also breaks off this involvement, and is not neutralized in it: it preserves itself, on the contrary, in the process which, none the less, is determined by it and its other. The infinite form as the soul (Seele) of individuality is still materialized in shape, and so reduced to a unity which is not an infinitely free form within itself, but is in its existence a quiescently enduring being [12] (p. 271, § 336, oral addition)61.
4. The Plant and Its Soul
The plant is still not veritable subjectivity because the subject, in distinguishing itself from itself and making itself into its own object, cannot trust itself to the truly articulated differences; but it is the return out of these differences which first constitutes true self-preservation. The plant therefore does not advance beyond a formal distinguishing of itself from itself, and it can remain only in formal communion with itself. It unfolds its parts; but since these its members are essentially the whole subject, there is no further differentiation of the plant: leaves, root, stem, are themselves only individuals. Since the real differences (das Reale) which the plant produces in order to preserve itself are completely similar to itself, it does not develop true members. Each plant is therefore only an infinite number of subjects; and the togetherness whereby it appears as one subject is only superficial. The plant is thus impotent to hold its members in its power, for these, as self-subsistent, escape from it; and the innocence of the plant is the same impotence of self-relation to inorganic being in which the plant’s members become, at the same time, other individuals [12] (p. 276, § 337; translation adjusted)71.
Animal life is therefore the Concept which displays itself in space and time. Each member has within itself the entire soul (Seele), is not self-subsistent but exists only as bound up with the whole. Feeling, the finding of self in self, is the highest achievement and occurs here for the first time; it is to remain one with self in determinateness, in determinateness to be freely at home with oneself. The plant does not find itself within itself because its members are self-subsistent individuals over against it [12] (p. 277, § 337, oral addition; translation adjusted)72.
In the plant, which is only the first, immediate stage of subjective vitality, the objective organism and its subjectivity are still immediately identical. Consequently the process whereby the plant differentiates itself into distinct parts and sustains itself, is one in which it comes forth from itself and falls apart into a number of individuals, the whole plant being rather the basis (Boden) for these individuals than a subjective unity of members; the part—bud, branch, and so on, is also the whole plant. A further consequence is that the difference of the organic parts is only a superficial metamorphosis and one part can easily assume the function of the other [12] (p. 303, § 343; translation adjusted)73.
Like every living organism, the nature of a plant is particularized; but whereas in the animal the particularity is at the same time a particularity in contrast with which the subjectivity as soul (Seele) is also a universal, in the plant the particularity is quite immediately identical with the plant’s vitality in general. It does not exist as a state distinct from the plant’s inner life; on the contrary, the quality of the plant completely pervades its general vegetative nature, instead of being distinct from it as in the animal [12] (p. 304, § 343, oral addition and pp. 305–306, § 344).
Now because, as we have said, the subjective One of the plant is fused with its very quality and particularization, and consequently the negative selfhood (Selbstischkeit) of the plant is not yet self-related, therefore this self, too, does not yet exist as a purely non-sensuous being, the name of which is simply soul (Seele), but is still sensuous; no longer, it is true, as a material plurality, yet still as a sensuous unity of material parts. Now the sensuous element which remains for the unity is space. Since the plant thus cannot entirely destroy the element of sense, it is not yet pure time within itself; for this reason, the plant is in a specific place which it cannot get rid of, although it unfolds itself within it [12] (pp. 306–307, § 344, oral addition).
5. Between Ensouled and Conscious Beings: The Animal and Its Soul
That the disease becomes for the self: i.e., there is established in the self and in opposition to it as universal [that is, as purposive unity—AK], a determinateness which makes its own self into a fixed self; in other words, the self of the organism becomes a fixed existence, a specific part of the whole[12] (p. 433, § 372, oral addition, p. 440, § 374) and [4] (vol. 25.1, p. 315)82.
The animal, in overcoming and riddling itself of particular inadequacies, does not put an end to the general inadequacy which is inherent in it, namely that its Idea is only the immediate Idea that, as animal, it stands within Nature, and its subjectivity is only implicitly the Concept but is not for its own self the Concept. The inner universality [that is, the soul—AK] therefore remains opposed to the natural singularity of the living being as the negative power from which the animal suffers violence and perishes, because natural existence (Dasein) as such does not itself contain this universality and is not therefore the reality which corresponds to it [12] (vol. 440, § 374; translation adjusted)84.
6. From Ensouled to Conscious Beings: The Human and Her Soul
[T]he spirit is essentially consciousness, with a content that has become an object. As a feeling, it is the non-objectified content itself […] and only the lowest level of consciousness, indeed, in that form of the soul that we have in common with animals. Only thinking makes the soul (with which animals are also endowed) a spirit, and philosophy is only a consciousness of that content, the spirit and its truth, in the shape and manner of its essential character that distinguishes it [the spirit] from the animal […] [45] (p. 16; translation adjusted).
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | See also [4] (vol. 30.1, pp. 339–340). |
2 | The translation opts for the translation of the German term Geist as ‘Mind’ and not as ‘Spirit’. In what follows, I will be adjusting the translation by using the term ‘Spirit’ instead. |
3 | |
4 | See, for example, Kant’s classical argument for the existence of the soul as postulate of practical reason [11] (pp. 238–239) [5:122–124]. |
5 | |
6 | See also [4] (vol. 30.3, p. 1106) and [15] (26) [De Anima II 3, 415a 16–22] and De generatione animalium, II 3, 736a 35-b 9. Michael Wollf notices that Hegel’s choice of the term “soul” since 1817 goes back to Plato’s Timaeus. There (Timaeus 30b) Plato depicts the soul as the “band” between mind and body. See [16] (p. 32). I assume that Aristotle adopted the use of term for the same reason. See [16] (36). |
7 | In his Lectures on the History of Philosophy Hegel refers explicitly to this—immanently and not retrospectively—developmental account of the different actualizations of the soul-principle, projecting it back on Aristotle. See [4] (vol. 25.1, p. 221), [4] (vol. 30.1, p. 109), and [4] (vol. 30.3, p. 1107). There, Hegel repeats his admiration of Aristotle and his theory of human soul, mind, and spirit, that remains “the best” that has been written on the topic until Hegel’s time. |
8 | On this, crucial, point see [17] (726–727) and [18] (pp. xii–xiii and pp. 1–29). This paper can be read as an exemplification of what Stone calls Hegel’s “strong a priorism”. For an authoritative account of the way that the strong apriorism of Hegel’s philosophy of nature relates to empirical nature, see [19] (183–185). In his fine reconstruction, Houlgate nevertheless does not address the problem that, strictly speaking, the sole subject of the Hegel’s philosophy of nature is the a priori ‘deduction’ of nature and not finite Spirit’s endeavor to match a priori concepts and empirical phenomena as well. |
9 | Dahlstrom is right to connect Hegel’s, Aristotle-inspired, concept of the self, which, as it will be showed, is synonymous with the concept of the soul, with reflective structures that are not characterized by consciousness. See also [8] (p. 38). |
10 | In another lecture on the philosophy of nature, Hegel will add “Aristotle recognized the inner purposiveness of nature. His thoughts on the issue are the greatest.” [4] (vol. 24.1, p. 516; my translation). |
11 | |
12 | For a summary of the aporias emerging from the mind–body dualism, see [26] (pp. 10–17). |
13 | In the passage, Hegel explicitly refers to Descartes as the initiator of Modern European rational psychology, according to which body and soul are conceived as independent elements that coexist in a manner that is, due to their fundamental independence, inconceivable. See also [4] (vol. 25.1, p. 7). |
14 | Hegel delineates in detail the reasons why he critically refers to the object of rational psychology as a “thing” in [4] (vol. 23.1, pp. 187–188). |
15 | As we will see, this does not exclude the possibility that there are souls which are also thinking souls. See Hegel’s reference to Aristotle’s De Anima, II 2, 3, where, according to Hegel, Aristotle “further states that the soul is to be determined in three ways, namely as nutrient or vegetable, as sensitive, and as intelligent, corresponding with plant life, animal life and human life.” [3] (p. 184). |
16 | Hegel defines matter in general as that, “which offers resistance, is for itself, excludes, [and] is individuation through and through.” [4] (vo. 24.2, p. 777); my translation. |
17 | See, for example, again Kant’s argument for the immortality of the soul, based exactly on the premise of the fundamental independence between phenomenal bodies and noumenal souls, in his Critique of Practical Reason [11] (pp. 238–239). |
18 | Hegel proposes a three-fold division between human soul, consciousness and Spirit, but the further, very important distinction between consciousness and Spirit is not relevant for the purposes of this paper. For a Hegel-inspired, systematic account of the differences between mere consciousness and the different sorts of intelligence, see [27]. |
19 | The overall structure of Hegel’s Philosophy of Subjective Spirit unmistakably attests this. See [25,28] (p. 5) and [20] (p. 180). Willem DeVries assumes that Hegel adopts the term ‘soul’ “because of his predecessors’ predilection for treating soul as a thing.” Hegel’s predecessors on the matter are not, though, the ones that Devries thinks, while the use of the term ‘soul’ is adopted by Hegel for the opposite reasons from those that DeVries proposes. Hegel reintroduces the Aristotelian concept of soul because it polemically marks the very opposite of a “thinglike”-approach to the matter [22] (p. 25). |
20 | Hegel, drawing the example from De Anima II 412b 18–24, exemplifies his interchangeable use of the terms by saying that if the eye was an independent living being, then its final cause, seeing, would be its soul. See [4] (vol. 30.3, p. 1106) and [15] (p. 22). See also [4] (vol. 30.4, p. 1478 and p. 1480) and [29] (pp. 164–165). For the emergence of Aristotle’s mature differentiation between dynamis, entelechy, and energeia, see Stephen Menn’s outstanding [30]. As we will see in what follows, it is Kant’s theory of inner purposiveness that leads Hegel to reserve his references to Aristotle’s concept of entelechy only for living beings and not, as Aristotle does, for artefacts as well. As Menn shows, entelechy means “‘having one’s τέλος within one’”. While, however, the parts of the artefacts have as their telos the artefact itself or its use, they can be replaced or exist on their own. This is the reason why Hegel thinks that the parts of the artefacts or the artefacts as such do not have their τέλος within themselves. See [30] (p. 101, footnote). |
21 | In what follows, I will not be making the distinction between the waking and sleeping soul, a distinction very important for both Aristotle and Hegel. I will be using the term soul as synonymous to ‘waking soul’. |
22 | That the soul is the actively organizing principle of the body in Aristotle is not unanimously accepted. It has been contested on good grounds by Robert Heinaman [31] (pp. 88–90). |
23 | |
24 | For the reasons that lead Aristotle to use energeia in the different senses of actuality and of activity, see [30] (p. 75 and pp. 87–95). |
25 | |
26 | Hegel defines the soul as the activity of form that has body, the parts of which are not indifferent to the activity that the forming soul is. See [4] (24.2, p. 777). |
27 | For the logical structure of life as syllogism, see [33]. |
28 | See also Stephen Menn’s reformulation of Aristotle’s general definition of the soul, which, I take, is Hegel’s interpretation of Aristotle’s general understanding of the soul, as “‘bodies having life’” [32] (p. 107). |
29 | |
30 | |
31 | Of course, as we will see later, natural organisms are meant to reproduce and, thus, produce new natural products. But this function is internal and not external to them. Christian Spahn questions Hegel’s positioning of external purposiveness and/or teleology before life because he understands the chapter on teleology as the first appearance of the unifying ‘reconciliation’ between (human) subjectivity and external objectivity, which ought to appear only at the end of the Logic. This leads Spahn to, among other things, the highly debatable position, according to which the logical prefiguration of organic life is to be found in the chapter on teleology and not in the following one on life. Hegel, though, investigates in the chapter on teleology the logical structure of artefacts as such and not the relation between the artefact and the creator of the artefact, which, as Spahn knows, can be both animal or human, as the chapter “The Constructive Instinct” from his philosophy of nature unmistakably attests [35] (pp. 167 ff. and pp. 262–263). |
32 | It is noteworthy that while Hegel develops a theory of mechanical objects as means for living and/or intelligent beings, he does not develop his theory of civil society, notwithstanding a theory of living and/or intelligent being as means for other living and/or intelligent beings. |
33 | See also [4] (vol. 30.3, pp. 1095–1096). This active self-referentiality of a final cause is characterized by Hegel as the “fundamental feature” of the whole Aristotelian philosophy [4] (vol. 30.3, pp. 1095–1096). In another lecture and in more idealistic terms, Hegel will claim that Aristotle’s concept of self-referential, purposive causality is the prefiguration of the idea of the identity between subject and object, that is, of the main idea behind Hegel’s own philosophy [4] (vol. 30.4, p. 1476). |
34 | For Hegel’s distinction between the logical structure of inner and outer purposiveness, see the chapters on “Teleology” and “Life”, respectively [36] (pp. 735–774). |
35 | |
36 | Nevertheless, Kant presumably reserves this definition not only for living beings but also for inorganic bodies such as crystal formations [39] (p. 20, § VI) [20: 217]. I am indebted to Cinzia Ferrini for this insight. |
37 | Hegel explicitly acknowledges his appreciation for Kant’s substantial contribution in understanding the structure of organism in [4] (vol. 23.1, p. 399). |
38 | |
39 | Hegel’s fusion of Aristotle’s and Kant’s approaches to organic structures leads here to one important difference between his and Aristotle’s use of the term “organic”. For Hegel, organic means a natural body, the members of which can simultaneously be seen as means and ends, depending on the perspective [4] (vol. 24,1, p. 133). For Aristotle, “organic” in this context means to have the function of an instrument, whether this be a part of the body or the whole body, without any reference to the members of the body as ends. An organic body is, for Aristotle, unqualifiedly the instrument of a soul [32] (pp. 108–111). Hegel, on the contrary, would never describe the living body of vegetative and of animal organisms as an instrument for the respective soul, since the soul is the activity of the purposive self-preservation of the body and not an activity aiming at something outside the body. (And even when he describes the body as an instrument of the soul at the end of the “Anthropology”, he does this to highlight the transitory status of the human soul, which is about to transform into a disposition for consciousness.) [12] (p. 356, § 352). Hegel thinks that the body parts are instruments of the self-preservation of the whole body also for their own sake, that is, for their own self-preservation and well-being, while, as noted above, he reserves entelechy only for natural organisms and not for the case of artefacts that realize their potential by means of an external agent and/or an instrument. Hegel understands this externality as a case of external, and not internal, entelechy, that is of an entelechy that does not have its activating energeia in itself. See, again, [32] (pp. 105, 125 and 137–139). |
40 | Nicolás Garciía Mills [42] (p. 14) suggests that Hegel supports a “historical approach” in the process of the identification of the function that a member of the organism embodies. To my knowledge, this suggestion finds no textual verification and, more importantly, it overlooks Hegel’s Kant-inspired claim regarding the immanent conceptual standard of the complementary functionality of the members of every living being as such—and not as diachronically comparable individuation of a species. |
41 | See also [22] (pp. 7–8). |
42 | Kant speaks of “astonishment” and of “admiration” [38] (p. 238, § 62) [5: 365]. |
43 | That is, “only in relation to our cognitive faculties, hence in relation to the subjective conditions for thinking it, without undertaking to decide anything about the object.” [38] (p. 266, § 74) [5: 396]. |
44 | Yet, this is a profoundly limited analogy, since the living being has no author at all. As Kant strikingly admits, “Strictly speaking, the organization of nature is therefore not analogous with any causality that we know.” [38] (p. 246, § 65) [5: 374]. |
45 | As Daniel O. Dahlstrom rightly remarks, Hegel’s mature appropriation of Kant’s concept of internal purposiveness takes place in the light of the profound influence of Aristotle [43] (pp. 173–175). |
46 | Cinzia Ferrini shows in detail how Hegel’s effort to reintroduce inner purposiveness of nature as something objectively existing finds its counterpart in the realm of empirical sciences in Georges Cuvier’s ideas, highly praised by Hegel himself [33] (pp. 25–27). For the divergences on this point between Aristotle and Kant, see [44] (p. 239). |
47 | See also [4] (vol. 24.1, p. 527). |
48 | See also [12] (p. 377, § 356). |
49 | See also [12] (pp. 407–409, § 365, oral addition). |
50 | In the oral addition to the main text, we find a direct identification of concept of life with the concept of the soul: the concept of life is the soul, that has as its reality the body [46] (p. 292, § 218, oral addition). See also [4] (vol. 23.1, 140) and [4] (vol. 23.3, p. 953). On this point, my interpretation differs from Michael Wolff’s [16] (p. 38). Wolff proposes the term ‘soul’ is used by Hegel as an abbreviation for the existing Spirit, which emerges out of nature. My interpretation proposes that the term ‘soul’ refers to the actualization-process of the concept of inner purposiveness, i.e., of life, but that the soul is not characterized by consciousness or spirit. The distinctive feature of the latter are the properties of, first, consciouses, and then of Spirit, not of soul. |
51 | Aristotle’s general definition of the soul is to be found in De Anima II 4, 415b 8: “The soul is the cause or principle of the living body”, [15] (p. 27); translation adjusted. See also De anima, II 1, 412b 3–6. |
52 | Aristotle also offers a generic definition of the soul, despite the various embodiments of the soul that definitionally depend on the nutritive soul, as pointed out by Stephen Menn [32] (pp. 106 and 121). Hegel, following Aristotle, states the following: “The universal type which forms the basis, cannot, of course, as such exist; but the universal, because it exists, exists in a particular form (Particularität). Similarly, perfect beauty in art must always be individualized. It is only in spirit that the universal, as ideal (Ideal) or Idea, exists as universal [12] (p. 419, § 370, oral addition). |
53 | The unified concept of intrinsic entelechy is treated in Hegel’s Science of Logic under the name of “Life” [36] (pp. 761–774). |
54 | |
55 | Edgar Maraguat seems to adopt this approach, even if his otherwise detailed interpretation of the relevant parts of the Logic somehow blurs the important difference between the Logic and the Philosophy of Nature. See, for example, [41] (pp. 138 ff.) This blurring becomes more evident when Maraguat compares his account of inner teleology in the Logic with Michael Wolff’s account of Hegel’s solution of the mind–body ‘problem’ in the Philosophy of Spirit [41] (pp. 171 ff). |
56 | See also the oral addition to the paragraph. |
57 | See also [22] (pp. 9 and 201), [49] (pp. 163–165), [19] (pp. 185–192) and [50] (pp. 19–20). It is true that the realm of the chemical phenomena, like every realm, hints not only negatively at the next, more logically adequate realm but also positively: Cinzia Ferrini highlights, for instance, how plants show an analogy of blood circulation in animal organisms with the sap that, by means of the cellular tissues and the spiral vessels of the wood, is transported and moves once it is assimilate [33] (p. 41). |
58 | James Kreines is right, hence, to stress the fact that Hegel, pace Kant, “does not hold that living beings can be explained in two different ways; they can only be explained in teleological terms.” [51] (p. 366). |
59 | In this, I concur with Christian Spahn’s account of life in Hegel, which places self-preservation at the core of Hegel’s theory of organisms [52]. |
60 | For a succinct reconstruction of this transition, see [33] (pp. 9–11). |
61 | See also [12] (p. 270, § 335). |
62 | In his Philosophy of Nature, Hegel not only develops his theory of vegetable, animal, and human life only in respect of the inner structure of the respective organic structure that they embody. He equally develops several accounts regarding the organism’s relation to its environment and the organism’s reproductive mechanisms. In what follows, I will only focus on the internal structure of the respective organic paradigms, which aims at their self-preservation, that is, on what Hegel, following Aristotle, calls ‘the soul’. |
63 | See also [12] (p. 276, § 337, oral addition). |
64 | For an apt reconstruction of these processes in Hegel, see [13] (pp. 106–119). |
65 | |
66 | Thus, I beg to differ with Michal Wolff’s claim that Hegel does not understand plants as souls [16] (pp. 33 ff.). My claim is that plants according to Hegel are a realization of the concept of the soul, albeit a fundamentally inadequate one. Klaus Brinkmann [14] (p. 142) follows a somehow undecided line of interpretation. Brinkmann writes that “this third part of the Philosophy of Nature (Organic Physics—AK) can be viewed as the progressive working out of the full-fledged concept of an organism and of organic life.” |
67 | See also [49] (pp. 165–166). |
68 | See Hegel’s related remarks in the subchapter “Judgment of Reflection” [36] (p. 643–657). |
69 | |
70 | This specific principle of hierarchization is most probably taken from Goethe’s Morphology. See [55] (pp. x–xi). “The more imperfect a creature is, the more do the parts resemble each other, and the more are they like the whole. The more perfect the creature is, the more dissimilar its parts become. In the first case, the whole is more or less like the parts; in the second, the whole is dissimilar to the parts. The more the parts resemble each other, the less they are subordinated to each other. Subordination of the parts betokens a more perfect creature.” [12] (p. 304, § 343). The reference and the passage from Goethe was added to Hegel’s main text by his pupil and editor of his works and lectures, Karl Ludwig Michelet. On Goethe’s Morphology, see [21] (pp. 33–40). |
71 | See also [12] (pp. 314–315, § 345). Here, Hegel describes the self-subsistence of the parts as “the impotence of the plant”. |
72 | |
73 | See also the oral addition to the main text (p. 315 § 345). |
74 | The seeming differentiation of the parts of the plant because of their ability to turn into other parts is an idea also taken by Hegel from Goethe. See [12] (p. 315 § 345). |
75 | Hegel refers to the intrinsic relation between “selfhood”, that is, soul, “self-movement” and “self-differentiation” in [12] (p. 385, § 359, Remark). |
76 | |
77 | While Christian Spahn rightly stresses the function of the categories of the Logic as prefigurations of the realms described in the Realphilosophie, he nevertheless understands this correspondence in a highly questionable way. Spahn namely claims that the chapters of the Logic that are relevant for understanding Hegel’s account of organisms are those on the ‘Concept’, on ‘Teleology’ and, finally, on ‘Life’ even if, Spahn claims, the latter “does not offer on a logical level many new insights” [35] (pp. 119–120 and 135–136). Yet, it is the very concept of ‘Life’ alone that prefigures living entities and not the much less developed concept of external purposiveness and/or teleology that prefigures logically artefacts or the concept of the ‘Concept’, which, as such, finds its correspondence in the chapter on “Universal Will” in the Philosophy of Right. |
78 | Here, Hegel develops his account of the five senses of developed organisms. |
79 | Nicolás García Mills [56] (pp. 243–248) rightly argues that, for Hegel, animal organisms are not inadequate in the sense that (some of their) individual realizations are “defective”. He, nevertheless, goes on to claim that the inadequacy of all natural organisms resides in the fact that, while their genus is not sexually differentiated, its individual realizations are. Hence, García Mills argues, the inadequacy arises because the individual realizations of the genus “cannot satisfy the description that articulates the content of their genus.” Aside the fact that Hegel explicitly holds that the sexual differentiation is a progress relative to the previous stage of vegetative life, García Mills’ line of argumentation cannot accommodate the fact that Hegel, both in the Logic and in the Philosophy of Nature, aspires to exhibit conclusively that the concept of genus as such hints at its sexually differentiated individualization, thus rendering vegetative life more inadequate than animal life in the light of the concept of life developed in the Logic. The sexually differentiated individualizations of the realm of animal life are, hence, not inadequate but, on the contrary, fully adequate qua necessary, just as the “spurious infinite progress” of the genus-reproduction, that García Mills describes is. It is also adequate in the sense that its inadequacy hints at a further, less inadequate realm, the realm of (Subjective) Spirit. My suggestion, namely, is that the general inadequacy of all preceding natural realms, and more specifically the realms of plant and animal life before human life and intelligence, is not an inadequacy resulting from the (sexed) individuations of these realms but an inadequacy hinting beyond these realms, i.e., at the further, more adequate realms of human soul and, more accurately, of Spirit: the genus of animal organisms perishes and emerges in its individual realizations, whereas rational thinking neither perishes nor emerges but remains the same through the individual rational agents that actualize it. García Mills agrees in this but maintains that human consciousness emerges as the overcoming of sexual differentiation, while I propose that human consciousness emerges as the overcoming of corporeity as such: the perishable, not the sexed, hints at the unperishable. On Hegel’s understanding of inadequacy in the light of his theory of truth, see [57]. |
80 | Hermann Drüe [58] (p. 191) misses this point and highlights locomotion as the sign of the human soul’s independence from its corporeity. This sort of independence is, though, not specific human but already present in the animal life. |
81 | For Aristotle’s account of ὑλικὸς and ποιητικὸς νοῦς, which correspond to what here Hegel denominated as “material” and “universal element”, respectively, see [15] (pp. 51–54) [De Anima III 4–5]. |
82 | Hegel argues that the death of the animal organism out of natural reasons is explained by the fact that the self-preserving activity of the organism has become a “habit”, since the body parts, through time, have become completely adjusted to their active unity, thus offering no resistance to it. But for Hegel, a (unifying) activity that does not have something to unite and/or meet opposition ceases to be an activity. The process of self-preservation, in other words, stops being a process. That is why the chapter on the death of the individual animal organism is tellingly entitled “The Self-induced Destruction of the Individual” [12] (pp. 441–445, § 375, and the oral addition), [4] (vol. 24.1, p. 180) and [4] (vol. 24.3, p. 1610). According to Hegel, the same reason applies for the phenomenon of aging [4] (vol. 25.1, pp. 50–51, § 317). |
83 | Not immaterial in a Kantian sense, as something totally independent from the material body, but rather as an element, that is embodied in the body as a whole and, thus, pertaining to no specific part [4] (vol. 24.1), pp. 510, 751–752), [4] (vol. 24.2, pp. 778, 949), [4] (vol. 24.3, pp. 1190, 1451, 1515–1516) and [4] (vol. 25.1, p. 13). |
84 | In the oral addition, Hegel describes the death of the organism as that “which is abandoned by self”, meaning by the soul qua immaterial, purposive unity. |
85 | In §§ 410–412 of the Philosophy of Mind [6], the soul is presented as the omnipresent element that exerts a formative action within corporeality but is unable to sublate completely the difference between soul and body. There is, namely, an irreducible purely organic aspect of the body which resists the molding power of the soul and constitutes the limit to the soul’s formative action. This movement marks the emergence of consciousness. I am thankful to Cinzia Ferrini for this remark. |
86 | This discipline, which Hegel calls “psychical physiology”, would amount to a “system of the embodiment of the spiritual element.” [28] (vol.2, pp. 163–164, § 401). See also [4] (vol. 25.1, p. 296). Here actually lies the corporeal superiority of the human organism over the animal organism, since the latter lacks this “system of embodiment”, by means of which consciousness and, later, spirit emerge. |
87 | For the difference between consciousness and self-consciousness see [59] (p. 73). |
88 | Therefore, it is fundamentally misleading to interpret Hegel’s account of the soul as some sort of “transcendental-ideal condition of the possible unity of a given manifold of mental phenomena”, as Reiner Wiehl suggests [60] (p. 445). This because the soul is not a possible and, thus, external unity imposed on mutually external phenomena but rather the necessarily actualized activity of their unifying hierarchization and alignment. |
89 | |
90 | Richard Dien Winfield summarizes the path from vegetative life to human consciousness in the following way: “[R]ational animals bring the development of life to its consummating complexity, adding rational intelligence to the sentience, desire, and motility that brute animals add to the nutrition, growth, and reproductive function of plants.” [13] (p. 80). |
91 | On this point my interpretation is not aligned with the one that Allegra de Laurentiis proposes. De Laurentiis namely argues that “I only become a self- conscious “I” when this second nature is no longer just habit but the object of my will.” [21] (p. 188). It seems to me that de Laurentiis’ suggestion entails the following petitio principii: de Laurentiis suggests that consciousness emerges when “being human” stops being an achievement of preconscious habit and becomes am achievement of the “object of my will”, which, I take, according to de Laurentiis, is a conscious will. In this way though, the explanation of the emergence of consciousness uses consciousness to explain its emergence. |
92 | See also Richard Dien Winfield’s fine reconstruction of this crucial transition in [26] (p. 139–141). |
93 | To put it differently, the fully actualized soul becomes the disposition, on the basis of which consciousness necessarily emerges. My interpretation on this point differs from the one Michael Wolff’s. Wolff claims that the animal and human soul remain in a specific sense “not [fully- AK] actual [unwirklich]”. Wolff is referring to the passage in § 412 PN that causes difficulties to his interpretation. There, Hegel namely explicitly declares that “the ‘I’ hast lost the meaning of being a soul, of the immediacy of Spirit” [translation adjusted]. Wolff suggests that Hegel’s statement should be read as paradoxical regarding its articulation, but not regarding its subject matter. Yet, the fully actualized or the actual soul is not a materially bound organizing principle anymore, but something wholly immaterial, i.e., consciousness and, hence, no soul. This becomes evident from a further passage in the same paragraph that Wolff does not comment, where Hegel describes the ‘I’ as that, which “excludes from itself the natural totality of its determinations”, something that the soul, as the active entelechy of the body, cannot do. See [28] (vol. 2, p. 425, § 412) and [16] (pp. 132–133). |
94 | Hegel is namely building on Aristotle’s twofold function of the soul, as “internal principle of organic nature” and as “the ground of thinking mind”, as Allegra de Laurentiis rightfully stresses in her interpretation of Aristotle [44] (p. 231). In this, sense, de Laurentiis goes on, the human soul is both, “a formal and a material principle.” [44] (p. 236). See also [22] (p. 45) and [25], 13–15. |
95 | This, of course, does not mean that consciousness is independent from the body in the light of its further existence. The emergence of consciousness is necessarily bound to the full actualization of the soul’s control over the body. Thus, when the individual body perishes, the individual consciousness and intellect perish as well. This is the reason why Hegel dismisses the question about the immortality of the soul: it makes no sense to ask it, since the soul and, further, the consciousness and the mind are grounded on a specific achievement of the soul over the body and its functions. In his Lectures on Subjective Spirit from Hegel explicitly says that “the moment of immediacy [that is, the moment of corporeity—AK] does not disappear but is posited as indifferent.” [63] (p. 162). On this point see also [64] (pp. 164–165). |
96 | This provides also a further reason for understanding retrospectively Hegel’s decision to place “Life” in the final part of the “Idea” —and not at the end of “Objectivity”—in the Logic: the ultimate determination of life is not to be self-referring but to function as the other-referring disposition for immaterial states-of-affairs, which are logically prefigured in the “Idea of Cognition” and in the “Absolute Idea”. Christian Spahn misses this point and argues that Hegel ought to have placed the chapter on life at the end of “Objectivity” [35] (p. 278). |
References
- Plato. Platons Werke; (translation of Plato’s dialogues by Schleiermacher); Realschulbuchhandlung: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 1804–1828. [Google Scholar]
- Forster, M.N. The History of Philosophy. In The Cambridge History of Philosophy in the Nineteenth Century (1790–1870); Wood, A.W., Hahn, S.S., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2012; pp. 866–904. ISBN 978-05-1197-525-7. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G.W.F. Lectures on the History of Philosophy. Haldane, E.S.; Simson, F.H., Translators; Kegan Paul, Trench, Trübner & Co.: London, UK, 1894; Volume II. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G.W.F. Gesammelte Werke. edited by the Academy of Sciences of North Rhein-Westphalia, in cooperation with the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft; Meiner: Hamburg, Germany, 1968ff. [Google Scholar]
- Düsing, K. Hegel und die Geschichte der Philosophie; Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft: Darmstadt, Germany, 1984; ISBN 978-35-3407-959-9. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G.W.F. Philosophy of Mind; Wallace, W.; Miller, A.V., Translators; revised with introduction and commentary by Inwood, M.J.; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 2007; ISBN 978-01-9875-014-7. [Google Scholar]
- Ferrini, C. Tra etica e filosofia della natura: Il significato della metafisica aristotelica per il problema delle grandezze del sistema solare nel primo Hegel. In Hegel e Aristotele; Movia, G., Ed.; Edizioni AV: Cagliari, Italy, 1997; pp. 173–191. [Google Scholar]
- Beiser, F.C. Hegel; Routledge: New York, NY, USA; London, UK, 2005; ISBN 978-04-1531-208-0. [Google Scholar]
- Ninos, G. Hegel’s Theory of Finite Cognition and Marx’s Critique of Political Economy. Hegel-Bulletin. 2024, pp. 1–26. Available online: https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/hegel-bulletin/article/hegels-theory-of-finite-cognition-and-marxs-critique-of-political-economy/E9C98F0AECA06239C0AAE8793584E66E (accessed on 2 August 2025). [CrossRef]
- Kern, W., SJ. Eine Übersetzung zu De Anima III, 4-5. Hegel-Studien 1961, 1, 49–88. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, I. Critique of Practical Reason. In Practical Philosophy; Gregor, M.J., Ed.; Gregor, M.J., Translator; with a general introduction by Allen Wood; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1996; pp. 133–271. ISBN 978-05-2165-408-1. References followed by reference to the Akademie Ausgabe. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G.W.F. Philosophy of Nature; Miller, A.V., Translator; with an introduction by Findlay, J.N.; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1970 2004; ISBN 978-01-9927-267-9. [Google Scholar]
- Winfield, R.D. Universal Biology After Aristotle, Kant and Hegel: The Philosopher’s Guide to Life in the Universe; Palgrave Macmillan: London, UK, 2018; ISBN 978-33-1975-358-4. [Google Scholar]
- Brinkmann, K. Hegel on the Animal Organism. Laval Théologique et Philosophique 1996, 52, 135–153. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Aristotle. On the Soul. In The Complete Works of Aristotle. The Revised Oxford Translation; Barnes, J., Ed.; Smith, J.A., Translator; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1984; Volume 1, ISBN 978-06-9101-650-4. Page references are followed by the reference to Immanuel Bekker’s standard edition of the Greek text of Aristotle of 1831. [Google Scholar]
- Wolff, M. Das Körper-Seele-Problem: Kommentar zu Hegel, Enzyklopädie (1830), § 389; Klostermann: Frankfurt am Main, Germany, 1992; ISBN 978-34-6502-509-2. [Google Scholar]
- Stone, A. Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature: Overcoming the Division between Matter and Thought. Dialogue 2000, 39, 725–744. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stone, A. Petrified Intelligence. Nature in Hegel’s Philosophy; State University of New York Press: Albany, NY, USA, 2005; ISBN 978-07-9146-294-2. [Google Scholar]
- Houlgate, S. Logic and Physics in Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature. In Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature: A Critical Guide; Bykova, M.F., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2024; pp. 176–196. ISBN 978-10-0902-316-0. [Google Scholar]
- Dangel, T. Hegel und die Geistmetaphysik des Aristoteles; De Gruyter: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany; Boston, MA, USA, 2013; ISBN 978-31-1031-371-0. [Google Scholar]
- de Laurentiis, A. Hegel’s “Anthropology”. Life, Psyche and Second Nature; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 2021; ISBN 978-08-1014-376-0. [Google Scholar]
- DeVries, W.A. Hegel’s Theory of Mental Activity; Cornell University Press: Ithaca, NY, USA; London, UK, 1988; ISBN 978-08-0142-133-4. [Google Scholar]
- Peperzak, A. Selbsterkenntnis des Absoluten: Grundlinien der Hegelschen Theorie des Geistes; frommann-holzboog: Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt, Germany, 1987; ISBN 978-37-7280-911-8. [Google Scholar]
- Dahlstrom, D.O. The Self before Self-Consciousness: Hegel’s Developmental Account. Hegel Bulletin 2013, 34, 135–158. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brinkmann, K. The Natural and the Supernatural in Human Nature: Hegel on the Soul. In Philosophies of Nature: The Human Dimension (= Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Nature 195); Cohen, R.S., Tauber, A.I., Eds.; Kluwer Academic Publishers: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1998; pp. 3–18. ISBN 978-07-9234-579-4. [Google Scholar]
- Winfield, R.D. The Living Mind: From Psyche to Consciousness; Rowman & Littlefield: Lanham, MD, USA, 2011; ISBN 978-14-4221-155-1. [Google Scholar]
- Winfield, R.D. The Intelligent Mind: On the Genesis and Constitution of Discursive Thought; Palgrave Macmillan: London, UK, 2015; ISBN 978-11-3754-932-7. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G.W.F. Philosophy of Subjective Spirit; Petry, M.J., Translator; Reidel Publishing: Dordrecht, The Netherlands; Boston, MA, USA, 1978; Volumes 1–3, ISBN (volume 1): 978-9027707154, ISBN (volume 2): 978-90-2770-716-1, ISBN (volume 3): 978-90-2770-717-8. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G.W.F. Werke in zwanzig Bänden; Suhrkamp: Frankfurt am Main, Germany, 1986; Volume 19, ISBN 978-3-518-28219-9. [Google Scholar]
- Menn, S. The Origins of Aristotle’s Concept of ἐνέργεια: ἐνέργεια and δύναμις. Anc. Philos. 1994, 14, 73–114. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Heinaman, R. Aristotle and the Mind-Body Problem. Phronesis 1990, 35, 83–102. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Menn, S. Aristotle’s Definition of the Soul and the Programme of De Anima. In Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, volume XXII; Sedley, D., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2002; pp. 83–139. ISBN 978-01-9925-590-0. [Google Scholar]
- Ferrini, C. From Geological to Animal Nature in Hegel’s Ideal of Life. Hegel-Studien 2009, 44, 45–93. [Google Scholar]
- de Laurentiis, A. Natural and Unnatural Movements of the Soul. In Hegels Philosophie der Realität; Plevrakis, E., Ed.; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 2024; pp. 252–271. ISBN 978-90-0470-553-1. [Google Scholar]
- Spahn, C. Lebendiger Begriff–Begriffenes Lebens. Zur Grundlegung des Organischen bei G.W.F. Hegel; Königshausen & Neumann: Würzburg, Germany, 2007; ISBN 978-38-2603-573-9. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G.W.F. The Science of Logic; Miller, A.V., Translator; with a foreword by Findlay, J.N.; Humanity Books: Amherst, NY, USA, 1969; ISBN 978-15-7392-280-7. [Google Scholar]
- Petry, M.J. Introduction. In Hegel. G.W.F., Philosophy of Subjective Spirit; Petry, M.J., Translator; Reidel Publishing: Dordrecht, Netherlands; Boston, MA, USA, 1978; pp. ix–cxlviii. Volume 1, ISBN 978-9027707154. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, I. Critique of the Power of Judgment; Guyer, P., Ed.; Guyer, P.; Matthews, E., Translators; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2000; ISBN 978-05-2134-892-8. References followed by reference to the Akademie Ausgabe. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, I. First Introduction to the Critique of the Power of Judgment. In Critique of the Power of Judgment; Guyer, P., Ed.; Guyer, P.; Matthews, E., Translators; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2000; pp. 1–51. ISBN 978-05-2134-892-8. References followed by reference to the Akademie Ausgabe. [Google Scholar]
- Maraguat, E. Hegel’s Organizational Account of Biological Functions. Hegel Bulletin 2020, 41, 407–425. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Maraguat, E. True Purposes in Hegel’s Logic; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2023; ISBN 978-10-0930-492-4. [Google Scholar]
- Mills, N.G. Hegel on the Normativity of Animal Life. Hegel Bulletin 2020, 41, 446–464. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dahlstrom, D.O. Hegel’s Appropriation of Kant’s Teleology. In Hegel and the Philosophy of Nature; Houlgate, S., Ed.; State University of New York Press: Albany, NY, USA, 1998; pp. 167–188. ISBN 978-14-3840-710-4. [Google Scholar]
- de Laurentiis, A. On Hegel’s interpretation of Aristotle’s psyche: A qualified defense. In Hegel: New Directions; Deligiorgi, K., Ed.; Acumen: Chesham, UK, 2006; pp. 227–242. ISBN 978-18-4465-063-4. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G.W.F. The Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences in Basic Outline. Part I: Science of Logic; Brinkmann, K.; Dahlstrom, D.O., Translators; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2010; ISBN 978-05-2182-914-4. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G.W.F. The Encyclopaedia Logic. Part I of the Encyclopaedia of Philosophical Sciences with the Zusätze; Geraets, T.F.; Suchting, W.A.; Harris, H.S., Translators; with Introduction and notes by Geraets, T.F., Suchting, W.A., and Harris, H.S; Hackett Publishing: Indianapolis, IN, USA; Cambridge, UK, 1991; ISBN 978-08-7220-070-8. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. History of Animals. In Aristotle, The Complete Works of Aristotle. The Revised Oxford Translation; Barnes, J., Ed.; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1984; Volume 1, ISBN 978-06-9101-650-4. Page references are followed by the reference to Immanuel Bekker’s standard edition of the Greek text of Aristotle of 1831. [Google Scholar]
- Lear, J. Aristotle: The Desire to Understand; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1988; ISBN 978-05-2134-762-4. [Google Scholar]
- Houlgate, S. An Introduction to Hegel. Freedom, Truth and History, 2nd ed.; Blackwell: Malden, MA, USA, 2005; ISBN 978-06-3123-063-2. [Google Scholar]
- Rosenkranz, K. Hegels Naturphilosophie und die Bearbeitung derselben durch den Italienischen Philosophen A. Véra; Nicolaische Verlagsbuchhandlung: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 1868. [Google Scholar]
- Kreines, J. The Logic of Life: Hegel’s Philosophical Defense of Teleological Explanation of Living Beings. In The Cambridge Companion to Hegel and Nineteenth-Century Philosophy; Beiser, F.C., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2008; pp. 344–377. ISBN 978-11-3900-194-6. [Google Scholar]
- Spahn, C. Zwischen Naturnotwendigkeit und geistiger Freiheit: Das Organische als unfreie Freiheit bei G.W.F. Hegel. Hegel Yeongu (=Korean Hegel-Studies) 2014, 36, 47–66. [Google Scholar]
- Ferrini, C. The Transition to Organics: Hegel’s Idea of Life. In A Companion to Hegel; Houlgate, S., Baur, M., Eds.; Blackwell: Malden, MA, USA, 2011; pp. 203–224. ISBN 978-11-1914-483-0. [Google Scholar]
- Kalatzis, A. Sein als absoluter Anfang? Begründungskonzeption und Begriffsbildung am Beispiel des Anfangs von Hegels Wissenschaft der Logik. In Proceedings of the 12. German Congress for Philosophy (Welt der Gründe), Munich, Germany, 11–15 September 2011; Available online: https://epub.ub.uni-muenchen.de/12576/1/Kalatzis_12576.pdf (accessed on 2 August 2025).
- von Goethe, J.W. Zur Naturwissenschaft überhaupt, besonders zur Morphologie (1817); Cotta’sche Buchhandlung: Stuttgart, Germany; Tübingen, Germany, 1820; Volume 1. [Google Scholar]
- García Mills, N. Human Beings as the “Perfect Animals”. Hegel on the Difference between Animal Life and Human Spirit. In Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature: A Critical Guide; Bykova, M.F., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2024; pp. 238–256. ISBN 978-10-0902-316-0. [Google Scholar]
- Kalatzis, A. In-Adequacy Hegel’s Concept of Truth. In Pleroma. Logic, God and Man in the Philosophy of Hegel; Nissos Academic Publishing: Athens, Greece, forthcoming; ISBN 978-96-0589-132-9.
- Drüe, H. Psychologie aus dem Begriff. Hegels Persönlichkeitstheorie; De Gruyter: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany; New York, NY, USA, 1976; ISBN 978-31-1004-603-8. [Google Scholar]
- Winfield, R.D. Hegel and Mind. Rethinking Philosophical Psychology; Palgrave Macmillan: London, UK, 2010; ISBN 978-02-3024-100-8. [Google Scholar]
- Wiehl, R. Seele und Bewußtsein. Zum Zusammenhang von Hegels “Anthropologie und Phänomenologie des Geistes”. In Der Idealismus und Seiner Gegenwart. Festschrift für Werner Marx Zum 65. Geburtstag; Guzzoni, U., Rang, B., Siep, L., Eds.; Meiner: Hamburg, Germany, 1976; pp. 424–451. ISBN 978-37-8730-351-9. [Google Scholar]
- Kalatzis, A. Philosophy as Habit. The Twofold Nature of Hegel’s Science of Logic. In Pleroma. Logic, God and Man in the Philosophy of G.W.F. Hegel; Nissos Academic Publishing: Athens, Greece, forthcoming; ISBN 978-96-0589-132-9.
- van der Meulen, J. Hegels Lehre von Leib, Seele und Geist. Hegel-Studien 1963, 2, 251–274. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G.W.F. Lectures on the Philosophy of Spirit 1827-1828; Williams, R.R., Translator; with an introduction by Williams, R.R.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2007; ISBN 978-01-9921-702-1. [Google Scholar]
- Illetterati, L. The Concept of Organism in Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature. Verifiche 2014, 42, 155–165. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Kalatzis, A. Hegel’s Souls: Aristotle, Kant, and the Climax of Life. Philosophies 2025, 10, 92. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10040092
Kalatzis A. Hegel’s Souls: Aristotle, Kant, and the Climax of Life. Philosophies. 2025; 10(4):92. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10040092
Chicago/Turabian StyleKalatzis, Antonios. 2025. "Hegel’s Souls: Aristotle, Kant, and the Climax of Life" Philosophies 10, no. 4: 92. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10040092
APA StyleKalatzis, A. (2025). Hegel’s Souls: Aristotle, Kant, and the Climax of Life. Philosophies, 10(4), 92. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10040092