Next Article in Journal
Aesthetic Communication in Infancy: A Layered Aesthetic Self
Previous Article in Journal
Which Intelligible Words? Reading Femicide Through Rancière’s Concept of ‘La Mésentente
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

Language and Consciousness in Early Buddhist Thought: On the Early Reflections on the Theme of Language and the Perception of Reality in the Pāli Canon

Department of Communication Studies, University of Antwerp, Sint-Jacobstraat 2, 2000 Antwerpen, Belgium
Philosophies 2025, 10(2), 31; https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10020031
Submission received: 17 January 2025 / Revised: 26 February 2025 / Accepted: 26 February 2025 / Published: 10 March 2025

Abstract

:
In this paper, the Buddhist view on language and its implications for perception and cognition will be analyzed. The aim of this paper is to demonstrate that archaic Buddhism, as documented in the suttas of the Pāli Canon, already presents a well-articulated theory of knowledge, and that Buddhist considerations on the problem of language are comparable to Saussure’s early linguistic theories, as well as to fundamental issues in the philosophy of perception and theories of cognition. This comparison with Buddhist thought seeks to provide a technical approach to the problem of consciousness in order to structure a systematic dialogue between the philosophy of mind and language, cognitive sciences, and linguistics, offering an original perspective on these topics through Buddhist thought.

1. Introduction

This paper investigates how early Buddhist thought conceptualizes language, particularly in relation to cognition and perception. It further explores whether and how these conceptions anticipate certain elements of modern linguistic theories, with a focus on structuralism and the works of Saussure. Through an analysis of primary Pāli sources1, we seek to determine whether the Buddhist approach to language forms an independent, internally consistent system.
Several studies have recognized a distinct inclination of major Buddhist schools toward reflection on language [1,2,3,4,5,6,7,8]. Generally, the theme of language appears to hold a position of prominence in most Buddhist schools. Nonetheless, scholars have paid little attention to the Pāli canon, perhaps considering the analyses of Diṅnāga, Vasubandhu, Candrakīrti, and the Yogācāra school in general to be more profound. Nāgārjuna is also acknowledged as a significant thinker on language [9,10], although he is mainly recognized to be a thinker of ontological and metaphysical problems, which can be seen as strongly related to the problem of language [11,12,13,14,15,16].
In this paper, my aim is to demonstrate that the Pāli canon does not merely contain the precursors to later considerations on language; rather, the Pāli suttas already exhibit a well-developed and complex reflection on language and its relationship to the problem of perceiving reality. Naturally, there have been authors who have contemplated the theme of language in the Pāli canon, and part of my work seeks to reinvigorate these studies, also highlighting possible reasons why Buddhism, from the outset, presents such refined reflections, formulated in a specific manner and guided by certain key concepts. Finally, through a comparative philosophical analysis of conceptions of language and the relationship between language and perception provided by structural linguistics, I will attempt to demonstrate the comparability of certain notions. It is plausible to hypothesize inspiration from Indian grammarians, with whom Saussure was well acquainted, but more importantly, to establish the possibility of a dialogue between Buddhist and structuralist linguistic thought2. This can prompt us to reflect on the implications that a theory of language has for analyzing the experience of perceived phenomena, the construction of cognitive systems, and the role of consciousness3.
There are several fundamental elements concerning the Buddhist conception of language that I will introduce before elucidating their motivations, as found in the suttas. Discussing a “philosophy of language” in early Buddhism may not seem appropriate if we understand reflections on language as addressing a specific and determined object—namely, the faculty of speakers to articulate thoughts through the emission of sounds or other physical mediums (such as writing) to encode communication. However, reflection on language as a faculty is present in Buddhism in the form of a theory of language as part of a broader theory of knowledge. Language is indeed analyzed in early Buddhism, but we must clarify the nature of the object in question. Firstly, there is no perfect equivalent to the concept of “language”; rather, there exist a series of faculties such as name, word, discourse, expression, designation, and convention4, which are interconnected with the theory of knowledge, cognitive mechanisms, and, above all, consciousness. This complex network of relationships among these diverse “objects” can certainly be considered part of a theory of language, but it must be contextualized within the specific reflections produced by these thinkers, who view the listed terms as components of a unified system.
When comparing some of these notions with the fundamental themes of structural linguistics, particularly the thought of Saussure, on which much of this comparative analysis will focus, we should also remember that certain linguistic notions are systematically formulated as part of a science of language which seeks to establish itself as autonomous, drawing on a long tradition of reflections on words, concepts, and names. Some of these notions, especially those articulated by Saussure, could offer better contextualization of Buddhist thought as well. Building upon an already established sanctity of language and reflection on the power of words, the Indian tradition inherited tools for constructing a more systematic theory of language and knowledge.

2. Conceptions of the Name

In early Buddhism, reflection on one particular concept dominates: that of the “name” (nāma). Beyond its shared etymological root with the English “name” (cf. the Proto-West Germanic root *namō with Latin nōmen, Greek ὄνομα, and Hittite ḫannai-), we must not assume that this concept is perfectly equivalent. First and foremost, the Buddhist nāma serves a very specific function. While it partially overlaps with the Western linguistic notion of “name”, it also exceeds its boundaries in significant ways.
A careful analysis of the texts suggests that, in early Buddhist thought, nāma is primarily understood as a function capable of organizing the phenomenal continuum into discrete, recognizable units. However, the nature of this division is not derived from the phenomenal continuum itself but from the requirements shaped by sociocultural convictions, which expect that a given “thing” can be isolated, and thus manipulated. This expectation necessitates the intervention of “isolating cognitions” aimed at achieving this end. The rationale is therefore purely the convenience of knowledge systems that structure language. In short, the organizing principle is primarily one of usability. I will call this principle “isolating cognitions” for reasons that will become evident in the description of cognitive mechanisms.
Nāma appears, in fact, to be the pivot around which the entire early Buddhist conception of language revolves. It is part of a fundamental cognitive dyad (which it forms alongside rūpa), yet it also functions as an agent with its own specific characteristics. Furthermore, whether as part of the dyad or as an individual function (nāma indeed possesses its own characteristics), it holds a unique relationship with consciousness.
A concise but remarkably clear text on the idea of nāma can be found in SN 1.61, where we read:
  • kiṃsu sabbaṃ addhabhavi,
  • kismā bhiyyo na vijjati;
  • kissassu ekadhammassa,
  • sabbeva vasamanvagu
  • “What oppresses everything?
  • What has nothing greater than itself?
  • What is the one thing that holds everything under
  • its sway?”
The answer to these three questions is always nāma. From this brief text, it is already evident that early Buddhism did not regard language as a trivial matter. The name is seen as a universal oppressor so powerful that it holds everything beneath it, with none greater than itself (nāmaṃ sabbaṃ addhabhavi, nāmā bhiyyo na vijjati; nāmassa ekadhammassa, sabbeva vasamanvagu).
We must exercise great caution regarding this idea of the seemingly boundless power of a linguistic element and determine whether this is truly an exaggeration by the authors or whether their reflections on language lead them to such conclusions. To better understand this discussion, it is useful to analyze the suttas following SN 1.61, as well as the preceding one. A triplet very similar to sabbaṃ addhabhavi, bhiyyo na vijjati, and ekadhammassa, sabbeva vasamanvagu is, in fact, applied not only to nāma (name) but also to citta (cognition). In the subsequent sutta (SN 1.62), we find the following statements: “Cognition is what leads the world” (cittena nīyati loko), “By cognition [the world] is drawn along” (cittena parikassati), and finally, “Cognition is that one thing which has everything under its control” (cittassa ekadhammassa, sabbeva vasamanvagu). This is, again, a very intriguing triad, partially overlapping with the functions of nāma (name). Thus, we observe not only that name and cognition are interconnected, but also that cognition specifically relates to loka (the world) and that both are functions associated with control. Moreover, they represent forces to which, in some way, we are yoked (they control us). This specific nuance is subtle but present in the text, especially when examined in relation to other suttas addressing the same themes. The following suttas more or less maintain the same line of argumentation but address different topics. In Table 1, I have correlated all these assertions for comparative purposes.
From this comparison, we note further similarities. First, it must be noted that even though SN 1.64-65 are titled “fetters” and “bonds”, the theme is, in fact, desire, recognized as capable of creating (or acting as) fetters and bonds toward the world.
In the table, I compared the suttas from SN 1.61 to 1.65, but it should be said that the analysis continues in greater depth and involves numerous other concepts examined in this particular series of suttas. From a comprehensive analysis, we realize that the general theme appears to be loka, i.e., the “world”. This theme is thus linked to these five suttas but is also the central theme of the subsequent ones. SN 1.66 focuses on what harms the world (kenassubbhāhato loko), what surrounds it, and what has struck it down (namely: death, old age, and the dart of craving). SN 1.67 centers on what ensnares the world (uḍḍito loko), what surrounds it, and what grounds it (craving, old age, and suffering). We begin to recognize a very precise pattern. SN 1.68 discusses what closes off the world (pihito loko), what grounds it, what ensnares it, and what surrounds it (morality, suffering, craving, and old age). SN 1.69 addresses what imprisons, “binds”, the world (bajjhatī loko); that is, desire and craving; their removal will sever all bonds (icchāya vippahānena, sabbaṃ chindati bandhanaṃ). Finally, with SN 1.70, we arrive at the world itself. The suttas proceed with further analyses, such as health (SN 1.73), but these are not of interest in this context.
The description of the world provided in SN 1.70 is that it is “arisen in six” (chasu loko samuppanno), forms a close bond in six (chasu kubbati santhavaṃ), and through attachment to these six, the world is tormented (channameva upādāya, chasu loko vihaññati). This sixfold structure, which constitutes what allows the arising of the phenomenon (samuppanno) called loka (“world”), and which is the foundation of its binding as well as the origin of its torment, refers to the only other significant sixfold structure known in the Pāli canon, namely the sensory spheres (saḷāyatana) ([20], pp. 116–117).
There is a reason I chose to analyze the suttas from SN 1.60 (which we will examine shortly) to SN 1.70. The reason is that they are part of a particular group of suttas dedicated to reflection on language and its relationship with the “world” [21,22,23,24,25].
In a previous study, it has been demonstrated how the concept of loka in early Buddhism is closely tied to perceptual–cognitive experience ([20], p. 112). For this reason, the sixfold structure with which SN 1.70 associates it can only be the set of six sensory spheres, as evidenced by suttas that explicitly link the “phenomenon” of loka to the perceptual–cognitive structure arising from contact (phassa) between the effector and the sensor, producing a specific sensory consciousness (see, for example, SN 12.44, 35.107, 56.28, AN 4.23, Ud 3.10, Iti 112, and compare them, for example, with MN 146.6, SN 35.60, and AN 4.23). In all the major discourses on the theme of the “world”, it is treated as a “phenomenon” that “arises” from specific causes and conditions and that, in the absence of these bases to sustain its phenomenal appearance, naturally ceases along with its influence on human experience (see, for example, SN 35.85).
However, it is precisely the experiential dimension that is central to the conception of the world, which is primarily tied to sensory dynamics and the social conventions that organize these into recognizable percepts. The fact that the linguistic sign is a matter of convention, and not of presumed natural laws determining the identities of “things” independently of perceivers, is something Saussure emphasizes strongly ([18], pp. 160–162). In particular, the proof of the arbitrariness of the linguistic sign lies in the mutability of semantic values ([18], p. 154). Time leads to shifts in semantics, and thus signs never remain identical in their value. Time also brings about other changes: those of the signifier. Phonic execution is never perfectly identical, and languages “evolve”, i.e., they “change” the pronunciation of words over time ([18], pp. 163–168), leading to considerable diachronic transformation ([19], pp. 290–294). Above all, geographical and historical–cultural discontinuities are what also determine differences in the values of signs. Speaking of the perception of linguistic sounds as something believed to be objectively determinable, as well as the relationship between the idea and the word associated with it, Saussure cautions, “Elle aussi ne représentera jamais qu’un des éléments de la valeur, et ce sera une illusion de croire qu’au nom de cette élément on puisse traiter par la psychologie pure les différents unités de la langue” ([19], p. 290).
Variability is observed synchronically, as well, as languages evolve independently, and a certain community of speakers may develop tendencies that another nearby community does not ([18], pp. 163–168). This was a fact well known to the Buddha, who, in a famous sutta, explicitly uses the issue of dialectal variability to illustrate how language is not, in itself, a reliable means for understanding reality or truth, but is rather a source of “opinions”, and thus of conflicts5.
The fact that language (nirutti) and nominal labeling (adhivacana) is fundamentally a convention, a common agreement, and not a faithful representation of reality is also expressed through specific technical terms, such as paññatti (“designation”, “convention”), applied specifically to language (see SN 22.62: niruttipathā adhivacanapathā paññattipathā).
From the relationship connecting the group of suttas SN 1.61-70, we also understand that certain functions of the “world” are in fact closely linked to a particular aspect of language, which is determined by the peculiar object nāma, which I will proceed to define.

3. Origin of Conceptions on Language

The reasons behind the Buddhist focus on language likely have very ancient roots. Buddhist considerations on the theme of language and its connections with cognition and perception are grounded in the significance that words held in the Vedic world, where the ability to encode a message in the form of verses for oral transmission was a highly complex art requiring genuine specialization. The importance language assumes in these conceptions is akin to a phenomenal performative power, and the linguistic object is treated with utmost caution due to its potential. It is undeniable that these foundations fostered an attention to the theme of words that led to technical analyses of language and refined reflections on linguistic phenomena. This is true even though the nature of linguistic focus differs fundamentally between the Vedic and Buddhist traditions. In the Vedic tradition, language holds a sacred significance; it is a tool of technical power with a “magical” nature, and mastering it is the prerogative of specific technicians versed in this sapiential tradition. In Buddhism, however, language is perceived as what “chains” (saṃyojana) human beings to a particular “world” (loka).
Here, too, there is a divergence from the Vedic conception, in which the loka is something founded and preserved by a certain order. This order, recognized by Buddhists as a perceptual–cognitive system—namely, a psychosemantic organization of perceptions into well-defined normative structures—systems and frameworks that influence our experience of reality and “conform” us to specific orders, is precisely what their contemplative practice aims to dismantle. This represents a fundamental difference between the two approaches to contemplative practice.
Nonetheless, Buddhism is not radically opposed to the Vedic order; it respects much of its traditions and knowledge, positioning itself as a new interpreter of these elements. Conceptions of language are a clear example of this. Central in this regard is the importance of Vāc, comparable to that of Agni in Ṛgveda ([26], p. 64). The sacred word has luminous properties, and Agni is its inventor (ṚV 2.9.4)6. The Vedic poets are also inspired by this light, by Agni himself (ṚV 4.11.3).
A sutta that helps us navigate this topic is SN 1.60, the first in the group mentioned in the previous section, which I have reserved for analysis here. This sutta is dedicated to the figure of the kavi, a term we can translate as poet, but which, as we shall see, denotes a much broader figure. The sutta asks what is the basis of poetic verses (kiṃsu nidānaṃ gāthānaṃ), what is their distinguishing feature (kiṃsu tāsaṃ viyañjanaṃ), on what do they depend, and what do they imply (kiṃsu sannissitā gāthā, kiṃsu gāthānamāsayo). This brief sutta is one of many attestations of the profound knowledge Buddhists had of the preceding tradition, the importance of composing verses for encoding and transmitting knowledge, and the role of the kavi in all this. It is no coincidence that this sutta precedes the one on the name discussed earlier; in fact, the answer to these questions is that “meter is the basis of poetic verses, syllables are their distinguishing feature, verses depend on names, and a poet is one who underpins the verses” (chando nidānaṃ gāthānaṃ, akkharā tāsaṃ viyañjanaṃ; nāmasannissitā gāthā, kavi gāthānamāsayo).
The roles of poet and seer (ṛṣi) in the Vedic world are closely connected. The authors of the Vedas, those who first began codifying sacred verses, are considered to possess power comparable to that of deities, and the families that initiated this tradition are revered as divine. The Pāli canon knows and mentions these ten seers (Aṭṭhaka, Vāmaka, Vāmadeva, Vessāmitta, Yamadaggi, Aṅgīrasa, Bhāradvāja, Vāseṭṭha, Kassapa, and Bhagu) in some suttas, such as AN 7.52, and in DN 32, the epithet of Aṅgīrasa, the name of one of the most significant of these authors, is even attributed to the Buddha (aṅgīrasassa namatthu, sakyaputtassa sirīmato).
In the Vedas, the figure of the technician is much more clearly linked to that of the seer and the poet. Through poetic expression, complex knowledge unveiling the underlying connections (bándhu) ([27], p. 17, note 9) that sustain the world’s mechanisms are expressed, and such insights can only be seen by the extraordinary power of the seers. However, this poetic capacity is in itself described as a technical power, not only because, as is well known, since antiquity, composing in verse has been a complex art, requiring refined skills to maintain meter and convey messages with equally refined mnemonic techniques, but also because the role of the poet (kaví) is closely connected to that of the ṛṣi [28], to the extent that it essentially embodies the same role, insofar as it is tied to the concept of possessing “potency” or “performative efficacy”7, particularly in the use of words. Language, as well as its masterful command, is another theme linked with the archaic concept of τέχνη.
The fact that the role of Vedic language, that is, of poetry, was analogous to that of τέχνη is confirmed not only by comparative philological studies but also by the very terminology employed. In this regard, comparative historical studies on the figure of the poet in various Indo-European cultures are useful, as they attest to how this role was markedly different from what the term “poet” conveys today. As Campanile perfectly summarizes, the poet “is the individual who masters the art of speech in all its possible purposes: that is, he is a priest, jurist, doctor, historian, enchanter, apologist of the aristocratic structure of Indo-European society, and the sole preserver of its most ancient traditions” ([30], p. 29). This is also justified by the intensive training that the poet had to undergo to become a master of speech, training in which attention to language and the art of its codification were essential priorities, thus far removed from the modern notion of the poet as a free composer of verses. Inspiration was mystical, yet it guided the poet in the rigorous codification of the message into an elevated linguistic form, closely linked to τέχνη not only as art but also as “power” ([31], p. 20). In other words, the poet is “the conservator and professional of speech: he is, by definition, competent in all domains where speech is, or is considered to be, operative” ([30], p. 32).
A clear example of the technical nature of this role, which also highlights the importance attributed to language, is the comparison drawn between the poet and the carpenter or the weaver. It should be noted, considering the contemplative function of language, that the carpenter is invoked metaphorically for his ability to “construct” something meticulously, precisely, and functionally. This is because, in the Vedic contemplative exercise (dhī), which represents the devotee’s aspiration toward the divine, the metaphor employed is precisely that of a chariot or vehicle, intended to “lead” the contemplator toward the divine realm or to deliver his prayers to the deity [26,28,32]. The contemplator must “construct” this chariot through his thought, and to achieve this, his skill must be comparable to that of a carpenter ([26], pp. 52–62). Thus, given the essential comparability between mastery in language and mastery in contemplation, the metaphor of the carpenter is dual in this context.
The term used in this instance is often derived from takṣa- or stoma-, but it is the former that is of particular interest. Although its etymological meaning is primarily connected to the concept of dividing (takṣati), it also denotes the quintessential act of the carpenter or artisan who “fashions” something. The reconstructed Indo-European root for this term is tetḱ- (cf. Avestan auui tāšti, Latin tēla, tēlum, or texō), and it is no coincidence that it also underpins the Greek τέχνη. The Greeks employed the concept of τέχνη in a manner strikingly similar to the Veda.
In ṚV 1.62.13 and ṚV 1.130.6, the crafting of prayers–contemplations (navyam atakṣad brahma hariyojanāya) is compared to the crafting of a chariot by an artisan (imāṃ te vācaṃ vasūyanta āyavo rathaṃ na dhīraḥ svapā atakṣiṣu sumnāya tvām atakṣiṣu). Furthermore, ṚV 3.38.1 emphasizes the focus and discipline required of the contemplator, likening it to that of a disciplined carpenter (abhi taṣṭevadīdhayā manīṣām atyo na vājī sudhuro jihānaḥ). Similar observations appear in ṚV 5.2.11 (etaṃ te stoma tuvijāta vipro rathaṃ na dhīraḥ svapā atakṣam), ṚV 5.73.10 (imā brahmāṇi vardhanāśvibhyāṃ santu śaṃtamā yā takāma rathāṃ ivāvocāma bṛhan namaḥ), ṚV 10.39.14 (etaṃ vāṃ stomam aśvināv akarmātakāma bhṛgavo na ratham), and ṚV 10.80.7 (agnaye brahmatatakṣur).
As Campanile points out, terms connected to the root *tetḱ- are also used in the Greek world to denote the same “poetic” action through the metaphor of the carpenter. In the Pythian Odes, Pindar refers to poets as τέκτονες σοφοί ([30], p. 35), Sophocles even defines the Muse as “chief carpenter” (τεκτόναρχος μοῦσα, ἀλλ᾽ οὐδὲ μὲν δὴ κάνθαρος τῶν αἰτναίων). Furthermore, in Ἑλλάδος Περιήγησις (10.5.1), we read τεκτάνατ’ἀοιδάν, an exhortation to craft songs as carpenters would, a comparison that, according to Campanile, arises from the technical nature of both the poet and the carpenter: “which does not tolerate individual fantasies, and which holds a significant and precise social function. A well-constructed song is akin to a cart that the carpenter can only build by repeating and preserving a form of knowledge far older than himself” ([30], p. 36). The same applies to the comparison with a weaver (ṚV 5.29.15 as well8, as the contemplation likened to weaving in ṚV 1.61.8 and 2.28.5), reflecting analogous operative methods of ποιητικὴ τέχνη. Even the Iliad (3.212) employs an expression involving weaving (ὕφαινον) in reference to narratives (μύθοι), thus again to language (ἀλλ᾽ ὅτε δὴ μύθους καὶ μήδεα πᾶσιν ὕφαινον).
It should also be noted that Buddhism employs these metaphors in the specific context of contemplative practice: “just as irrigators guide water, fletchers shape arrows, and carpenters plane timber, those who are virtuous tame themselves” (udakañhi nayanti nettikā, usukārā namayanti tejanaṃ; dāruṃ namayanti tacchakā, attānaṃ damayanti subbatā, Dhp 145). This notion of taming the self, where the term attā is used for self, is particularly interesting, especially considering the philosophy of anattā in Buddhism, which is markedly anti-Upaniṣadic and thus does not seem to be invoked here coincidentally. The carpenter also appears in AN 7.72, in a sutta titled Bhāvanā, a term that literally signifies growth but is, practically, a technical term for contemplative practice. Other mentions related to contemplation can be found in MN 20: cognition must become internally stilled, settle, and reach a unified state—a state of perfect immersion, akin to a carpenter or his apprentice carefully extracting a large peg with a finer one9. Perhaps the most notable and interesting mentions, however, are in MN 10 and DN 22, the two satipaṭṭhānasuttas. Here, the carpenter (and his apprentice) is again evoked in relation to meditation, but in the context of mindful attention. Just as a carpenter must focus keenly while cutting a mark and be present in the act of “cutting deeply or shallowly”, so too the meditator brings their present attention to the four satipaṭṭhānas (kāya, vedanā, citta, dhamma) with the same kind of awareness [33]10.
Faced with these exercises and these metaphors, the hypothesis under consideration is that, at least in the Buddhist context, such exercises were intended to function as anti-inhibitory processes; that is, to counteract the automatism [34,35,36] generally associated with the act of naming. It may seem counterintuitive to combat automatism with another automatism, but it is crucial to first understand the nature of habituation constituted by the nominal function in the Buddhist sense, and secondly, the difference between inhibitory automatism and the “conscious” or attentive discipline enacted by Buddhist contemplative practice ([33], pp. 10–11), [37,38,39].

4. The Inhibitory–Habitual Process of the Nāma

Under normal conditions, our body receives a certain number of environmental stimuli that are processed as sensory data. Sensation, even in the Buddhist system, constitutes the first level of processing. Sensory stimuli can be understood in various ways, but when considering them as organs capable of interacting in a particular manner with our sensory capacity, the dynamic between effector and sensor described by Uexküll [40,41,42] remains one of the most effective models for representing the relationship between rūpa and āyatana in the Buddhist system.
For Uexküll, each animal essentially experiences its own environment, as the perceptual markers populating it function as signs with a specific semiotic value for each animal, which may not hold the same value (or any value) for others.
What emerges in Figure 1 is a dynamic of constructing the experience of the world as an environment (Umwelt), which can be recognized as having two fundamental interacting dimensions: the “perceptual environment” (Merkwelt)—that is, how it is perceived by the organism—and the “effectual environment” (Wirkwelt), comprising the modifications produced in the environment by the organism’s actions. The Merkwelt is not “external” in an absolute sense; rather, it is that aspect of perceptual experience determined by the effectual organs. If the Merkwelt is responsible for perception (stimuli registered and interpreted by the animal), the effectors in the Wirkwelt are responsible for the animal’s active responses, such as movement or other actions that impact the external world.
I have identified in this dynamic the binomial relationship between ajjhatta and bahiddha, as Buddhism also recognizes the “external” world (bahiddha) not as an autonomous and self-sufficient dimension but rather as the locus of perceptions. The internal (ajjhatta), on the other hand, is specifically understood as the sensory spheres (āyatana), as demonstrated by Qian Lin ([43], pp. 343–348).
In my interpretation, as I will elaborate as we progress with this analysis, the Buddhist “world” (loka) should be understood strictly as a psycho-ecological dimension. This, which partially coincides with the Umwelt but does not fully align with Uexküll’s conception, is also responsible for that “sense of self” that Buddhists describe in the analysis of the five aggregates and the perception of natural identities. It is a complex construct, yet one that depends on the world (loka), exists in the world, and is of the world.
The contact (phassa) between an effector organ and a sensor is, in the system of the five aggregates, the starting point of the basic perceptual dynamic. The initiation of the process has rūpa as its apex, but it is important to emphasize that this term does not merely indicate a geometric form but rather a form cognitively apprehended through phassa. It is the initial datum susceptible to future elaborations, so much so that the system of the khandhas can be understood as a set of concentric nuclei: rūpa is the central element, around which the other aggregates layer themselves, dependent on the preceding state, around which they crystallize, and so forth. Moreover, there are multiple ways of understanding rūpa, just as there are various analyses of the perceptual process. The model of the five khandhas is extremely effective yet also nuclear, and it serves as the prototype for both the analysis of phenomenal processes and cognitive processes, which are, in reality, two aspects sharing the same nature. However, it is through the more in-depth analysis of factors like the nāma that the cognitive aspects will be examined in greater detail.
The principle of the five khandhas applies to any construct, from one’s self to the identity of a supposed “external thing”, such as a “tree”. As is well known, the teaching of the five aggregates focuses primarily on the interdependent nature of all phenomena, thereby refuting the belief that they are autonomous and self-sufficient: their close interrelation is also to be understood as mutual implication. Hence, the artificial division we may draw between phenomenon A and phenomenon B arises for reasons extraneous to the actual nature of phenomena. The construction of a given conception, such as the separateness of phenomena A and B, depends on the conviction that phenomena A and B are defined by autonomous entities inherent to their nature and that refer to an essence of A as A and of B as B, which is independent and self-existent11. Sensation (vedanā), constituted by the first level of apprehension of experiential data, is insufficient in itself to construct this conviction. Sensations, in fact, are undifferentiated in their raw data state: even recognizing “smooth”, “rough”, “hot”, or “cold” is a subsequent attribution of identity that reorganizes the bundle of sensations and fragments it from a complex continuum into a series of recognizable entities structured according to highly generic prototypes. It must not be naively assumed that a sensation of smoothness is always identical. Certainly, touching the surface of a book cover and then a wooden piece of furniture may lead us to classify both as “smooth”, yet it is evident that this is a generalization and that there are an infinite number of differences between the smoothness of the book and that of the furniture. Sensations must, therefore, be organized in a particular way, and the function tasked with this role is called “perception” (saññā). This function will also be encountered in the description of the cognitive apprehension of nāma, which will become central later on.
Figuratively speaking, every animal subject attacks its objects in a pincer movement—with one perceptive and one effective arm. With the first, it imparts each object a perception mark [Merkmal] and with the second an effect mark. Certain qualities of the object become thereby carriers of perception marks and others carriers of effect marks. Since all qualities of an object are connected with each other through the structure of the object, the qualities affected by the effect mark must exert their influence through the object upon the qualities that are carriers of the perception mark and have a transformative effect on the perception mark itself. One can best sum this up this way: The effect mark extinguishes the perception mark.
([42], pp. 48–49)
Perceptions represent a further stage of organized conceptualization. Perception already imparts a level of “sense”, and indeed, as has been argued in other works, [33,44,45,46], “perception” in Early Buddhism can be defined as psychosemantic, a force already of a semantic nature. Sensation, perception, and cognitive constructs (saṅkhāra) form part of a subgroup within the five aggregates defined as “cognitive factors” (cetasika). It is therefore plausible that the notion of saṅkhāra is associative in nature.
In the constitution of a given percept x (associated with one or more sensations that must confer recognizability at the moment of experience), it is necessary to associate specific factual “possibilities”. These possibilities are the qualities of the percept as it has been constituted, and they form a set of ideas, specific “constructs” (saṅkhāra). For example, considering that this system operates a priori—anticipating an acquisition, so to speak, of “immediate” sensory data while mediating them through cognitive associations—it resembles the perception of an object we identify as a “tree”: the apprehension of a series of sensations through phassa (contact) between the sensory organs and environmental stimuli is qualified into an indeterminate number of elements rendered recognizable by our mental associations. This phase permits sensations, now “qualified” in a certain way, to be reconciled with the cognitive form that was previously learned [47,48,49,50].
Out of the infinite possibilities for a phenomenon like “tree” to manifest, someone who possesses the notion of “tree” identifies a common denominator among these differences. It is evident that no two “trees” are perfectly identical, yet the observer classifies them all as “trees”. This is due to the processing of sensory data that the observer has learned to associate with the idealized phenomenon, which is transformed into a cognitive prototype of experience. This process does not occur solely and trivially through sight. If one closes their eyes and begins to touch the trunk of a tree, it will not take long before the sensations of roughness and woodiness are associated with the same phenomenon. Smells, too, can serve this purpose. Most of us could recognize the taste of a familiar food even without seeing it, merely by tasting it. The principle is the same.
At this point, psychosemantic association intervenes: this is where sign perception comes into play, organizing perceptions and presenting a “tree” to the conscious mind. The phase of association with eidetic constructs is always linked to cognitive factors, but it serves a practical purpose: once the object “tree” is recognized, a series of multiple eidetic elements qualifying its possibilities also presents itself. A carpenter, for instance, will see in the tree a “raw material”, valuable “wood”; this is one possibility. A child might see in it the possibility of a game involving climbing its branches. Someone else might see shade, and thus coolness and shelter from the scorching sun or from rain.
In this framework, Buddhists have described with remarkable precision the “semiological” process of sign recognition, a fundamental psychological (indeed, psychosemantic) principle [33]. This principle is integral to the invaluable reflections of Ferdinand de Saussure, which underpin modern linguistics, and it bears more than a coincidental resemblance to these Buddhist insights.
We know that each aggregate “links” to the previous one through a process of associations, thereby implying not only the immediately preceding aggregate but potentially all the aggregates preceding the one to which it is linked. Additionally, we know that the aggregates are functions that can be either simple or complex. Sensations (vedanā), for instance, are depicted as plural because they are processed by the six sensory spheres (āyatana), and thus, we can usually expect at least more than one sensation to be involved. For this reason, in Figure 2, I have represented the first aggregate as, in reality, dual: the contact (phassa) between form (rūpa) and the sensory spheres (represented as a hexagon because Buddhists include thought, manas, as the sixth sense).
By way of example, I have imagined the branching of five vedanā as associations arising from this initial form–sense contact, though there could also be fewer. For instance, in perceiving the aggregate “flower”, I will receive a series of visual sensations (the flower’s color and shape), olfactory sensations (its fragrance), and tactile sensations (if I hold it in my hand), but no auditory sensations unless I intentionally rub the flower near my ear to hear the sounds it produces.
I have represented perception as singular because saññā, as a process of synthesis (in the etymological sense of the term: indeed, σύνθεσις is related to putting together, σύν-; similarly, the term saññā is composed of saṃ- + √ñā, ([51], p. 1133), indicates a synthetic–associative type of knowledge that “brings together” all perceptions to associate them with a well-defined “sign’: “flower”).
Mental constructs (saṅkhāra) revert to being plural because the possible eidetic and volitional associations are multiple: the flower can be picked, trampled, observed, and so on. All these various possibilities are “volitions” branching out from ideas associated with that specific percept.
I will now proceed to conclude our analysis of the five aggregates before proceeding to the specific examination of nāma. At this point, only one element remains to be addressed: consciousness (viññāna). The importance of this term in early Buddhism is immense. Consciousness must be defined in its specific sense to avoid confusion with our preconceived ideas [4,52,53,54,55]. First and foremost, viññāna has a privileged relationship with nāma. These two functions mutually imply one another; that is, each is responsible for the functioning of the other. This peculiar relationship of mutual generation and co-implication is specific to the nāma-viññāna axis, but it also clarifies certain functions of consciousness as such, which we will examine later.
Secondly, viññāna is also part of another cycle—that of the five aggregates themselves (see Figure 2). These aggregates are not to be understood merely as a stratification process of concepts “usable” by an individual; rather, they form a cyclical system without a clear origin. One of the functions of viññāna, explicitly revealed by its etymology, which is sufficiently transparent in this sense, is to “separate” and “organize by dividing.” The form of knowledge (ñāna, < jñāna) managed by consciousness is primarily divisive in nature (vi-, < dvi-) ([51], p. 961).
Let us return for a moment to the beginning of the process of the five aggregates: from a complex continuum of sensory stimuli, the perceptual–cognitive system “isolates” certain sensations to reduce them to specific and recognizable percepts. This divisive process constitutes the act of discernment, which is concretely enacted by consciousness. To understand rūpa in only one way would be incorrect in light of the Pāli texts, where the meanings of rūpa are manifold. Two, in particular, are of interest here: “form” can be understood both as an undifferentiated formal datum, aspectual and indicative of a specific epiphenomenology, and as a “recognizable” and “recognized” form by a cognitive system. At this point, “form” is no longer merely the aspectuality of a phenomenon—an undeniable part of the phenomenology of the world we observe, which does not necessarily imply independence, separateness, or isolation between formal aspect A and formal aspect B that follows it temporally or spatially (e.g., the form of seed A appearing first, then that of sprout B). Instead, it becomes an in vitro form, a functional prototype to which a whole series of similar but not identical phenomena can be referred, phenomena that must nonetheless be organized by isolating cognitions.
With this necessary premise established, the remaining aspect of viññāna to consider is its “organizational” function, which is predominant. Certainly, the organization carried out by viññāna is primarily based on divisions. However, having established this, it becomes clearer how a “system of knowledge” functions within Buddhist theory. The theory of knowledge involves methodically organizing a series of discrete “notions”12.
The “world” that results from this operation is exclusively experiential in nature. It must be noted that, for Buddhists, the concept of “world” refers solely to this [20,21,22,23,24,25,53,56]. To speak of a reality independent of these constructs and re-elaborations means engaging with a different level of knowledge, and “truth” (sacca), understood as that which “is” (sat-) in its most genuine sense, is neither an “other world” nor something reducible to mundanity. On the contrary, mundane realities appear as reductions in truth, and while they are not outside of it, they do not coincide with it perfectly.
This also explains the etymological nuance of the term loka (“world”) and of related terms derived from the same root, such as the verb oloketi, which means “to look at”, “to examine”, or “to look down (at)”. The reconstructed Indo-European root *leu̯k- relates to shining, and to light, which elucidates its fundamental etymological significance. Light is obviously an instrument to clarify something that would otherwise remain unrecognizable. Light has always served as the quintessential metaphor for phenomena. A phenomenon is that which reveals itself in the light, becoming available to our perception and thereby comprehensible. In the Vedic world, however, this term also denoted an “open space”, as reflected in Old English lēah (“open field, meadow”) or Lithuanian laũkas (“field”). The meaning of “open space”, particularly “free”, is primary, followed by those of “world”, “realm”, or a collective of people organized into a society, “inhabitants [of the world]”. All these meanings, including the one linking this root to perception (cf. oloketi) ([46], p. 71) to the concept of perception or vision (cf. locate and locana), [(49], p. 907), ([52], p. 79) are far from being in conflict with one another. The “open” (that is, “available”) space serves as a metaphor not only for the primordial conquest performed by the Vedic warrior–hero in the original establishment of the world—making the Earth, previously free from human dominion ([57], p. 230], available—but also reflects the expulsion of darkness by Agni, who, in Vedic myth, emerges from the primordial waters to dispel the darkness [58,59,60,61,62,63,64]. The mechanism is the same: Agni, as the bearer of light, makes previously uninhabitable lands “knowable” [65]. By casting light upon them, Agni not only makes them knowable but also “available” for human dominion, as these lands are, through the harnessing of fire’s power (agniyojana) [66], “conquered” and “known” by humans. However, the resulting “world” is merely the specific portion, the “field”, within which this perceptual–cognitive dominion operates and within which the organization of norms takes effect. This inevitably leaves an “other”, apparently outside these boundaries. Yet even when this “other” is conceptually reintegrated as a possibility within the normative structure—via the mechanism of anomie, the non-normed, the otherness, the beyond “unknown’—it remains, in every sense, “untilled land”. This metaphor, which is already Indo-European, is found, for example, in Ovid (as tellus inarata) and in the Uttarakāṇḍa (akṛṣṭapacyā pṛthivī) ([67], p. 211).
Much thought has been given to Buddhist asceticism. As is well known, one of the most prominent aspects of ascetic discipline is precisely the aim of exiting the “world” (the “field”, the “boundaries” of organized society), and the reasons for this exit can be manifold. For one, the normative order that would otherwise act as a coercive force on subjectivities is absent, which significantly facilitates a contemplative practice aimed precisely at disengaging from everyday habits. Here, we arrive at the fundamental crux of the matter, reconnecting with the problem of naming, and beyond.
The outcome of this intricate network of perceptual–cognitive processes can be summarized in one of the existential dramas characteristic of Early Buddhism, aptly captured by a formula found in Snp 4.13: “When a person sees, they see nothing but name-and-form; and having seen this, they will know only in this way” (passaṃ naro dakkhati nāmarūpaṃ, disvāna vā ñassati tānimeva). This passage is highly significant, as it introduces us to one of the fundamental dyads of Early Buddhism, arguably the cornerstone of early Buddhist psychology. The term nāmarūpa connects the concept of “name” with that of “form”, as we have delineated thus far. It is often translated as “name-and-form”, but since it is a dyad endowed with properties that operate only in the interplay of its two components, I will henceforth refer to it as n/r.
This passage establishes a connection between the act of seeing, expressed in two different ways: passaṃ and dakkhati. The former verb genuinely means “to observe” (Sanskrit paśyati, derived from speḱ-, vaguely implying “to inspect” or “to observe attentively”) ([51], p. 611) and seems to alternate with dakkhati, which is instead related to dṛś, “to look something” (< *derḱ-) ([51], p. 491). However, it must be noted that it is likely the context that clarifies the specific nuance in this case. There is, in fact, an ingenuous, spontaneous observation defined by passaṃ, and one conditioned by the factor n/r. Moreover, dakkhati does not merely mean “to observe” but also “to find something as a result of observation”. The observer of Snp 4.13 “realizes” that in the act of observation, they find nothing but n/r. But what does this mean? Clearly, the n/r dyad acts as a factor capable of conditioning ordinary lived experience, though it remains implicit, not overtly manifest. Nevertheless, upon more careful observation, it becomes evident that “everything” that seems to be “seen” is, in reality, n/r.
Finally, the verse connects the pervasive action of n/r to knowledge: “Having seen this, they will know [only] in this way”. The key term here is tānimeva, “only in this way”, which evidently refers to the modality governed by n/r—a factor capable of conditioning the way of knowing. The seer who “having seen” (disvāna) only through n/r will consequently “know” (ñassati) only “in this way”, that is, through n/r.
It is crucial to emphasize this point, as it prompts reflection on the quasi-obstructive nature of n/r, an element that interposes itself like lenses between the eyes and what is seen. It also becomes evident that, in this passage, the sutta does not refer to the continuous sense of rūpa—firstly because it forms part of a compound—but at this juncture, it is legitimate to ask whether the rūpa that forms part of the n/r dyad differs from the rūpa that begins the chain of the five aggregates. If so, we must inquire into the nature of this difference. For now, I will preemptively state that the n/r dyad has a peculiar relationship with consciousness. Furthermore, of the two elements composing it, it is nāma that serves as the principal driver of its functions, and I will explain why.

5. The Functions of the Cognitive Binomial n/r

The cognitive binomial n/r constitutes a semiosic coordination of perceptions [68,69,70,71,72,73]. Within this dyad, the term rūpa refers not only to the cognitive form—a definition that can be broadly applied to the term—but also to its physical or material aspect. Additionally, rūpa signifies the body, and as defined in the canonical texts, within the pair n/r, rūpa primarily denotes the four great elements (mahābhūtā). This distinction, which we may loosely summarize as psycho/somatic or psychological/physical, should not mislead us. Buddhism does not endorse a real separation between the psychic and physical dimensions, just as the internal/external (ajjhatta/bahiddhā) binary is evoked for practical purposes but is critically deconstructed in contemplative practice. While the distinction between the internal (psychological) and the external (physical) may have practical utility, at a deeper level, this binary must be abandoned.
avijjānīvaraṇassa, bhikkhave, bālassa taṇhāya sampayuttassa evamayaṃ kāyo samudāgato. eti ayañceva kāyo bahiddhā ca nāmarūpaṃ, itthetaṃ dvayaṃ, dvayaṃ paṭicca phasso saḷevāyatanāni, yehi phuṭṭho bālo sukhadukkhaṃ paṭisaṃvedayati etesaṃ vā aññatarena.
O mendicants, for a fool who is dominated by ignorance and bound by attachment, his body has been produced. There is thus a dualism between such a body and an external name-and-form. Contact depends on this dualism. When contact occurs between one or the other of the six sensory spheres [and the object of the senses], the fool thereby experiences pleasure and pain.
(SN 12.19)
The reason is not that the internal and external do not exist, but that they are not closed, independent dimensions; rather, they are two parts of a continuum. Consequently, their invocation serves functional purposes, as in the case of MN 28, but it is quite evident that these categories are conceptual fictions.
For example, MN 28 states: “Though the eye is intact internally, so long as exterior sights do not come into range and there is no corresponding engagement, there is no manifestation of the corresponding type of consciousness” (ajjhattikañceva cakkhuṃ aparibhinnaṃ hoti, bāhirā ca rūpā na āpāthaṃ āgacchanti, no ca tajjo samannāhāro hoti, neva tāva tajjassa viññāṇabhāgassa pātubhāvo hoti). This refers to a classical model of Early Buddhist psychology, for which any sensorial organ produces its own consciousness when it enters into contact with a specific form. For example,
Philosophies 10 00031 i003
This model can be translated concretely into the processual development of any consciousness, such as “visual consciousness” (cakkhuviññāṇa), that arises from the contact (phassa) between the āyatana of vision, i.e., the eye (cakkhu), and the visual form.
Another significant example is found in MN 109, which addresses the origin of the five aggregates: “Sir, how can one know and see that there is no formation of “I”, no underlying tendency that substantiates this perceiving body and all the external stimuli [lit. “external signs’]?” (‘kathaṃ pana, bhante, jānato kathaṃ passato imasmiñca saviññāṇake kāye bahiddhā ca sabbanimittesu ahaṅkāramamaṅkāramānānusayā na hontī’ti).
Thus, beyond their practical significance—which frames the ajjhatta/bahiddhā pair as a relationship between sensor and effector—it must be noted that this dyad also accurately describes the phenomenological mechanism of the appearance of the five aggregates. It is important to understand that any given phenomenon x, such as the formation of the psychological self (ahaṅkāra), involves the five aggregates as fundamental elements that are simultaneously present within the phenomenon, interconnected and interacting. The phenomenon called ahaṅkāra is composed of at least five simpler categories of phenomena, which, in their aggregation, enable its manifestation—much like a house of cards.
What is particularly noteworthy about MN 109 is the type of relationship it establishes between the last of the five aggregates (viññāṇa) and the n/r pair. It states that the n/r pair constitutes the phenomenal condition for the arising of consciousness (nāmarūpaṃ kho… hetu, nāmarūpaṃ paccayo viññāṇakkhandhassa paññāpanāyā). This is intriguing because it does not refer merely to form, as the first aggregate does, and thus it does not allude to the cyclical structure we examined in the preceding section. Another important sutta that establishes a relation between the n/r dyad and consciousness is SN 12.64, in which we read that the two entities are related by a process of phenomenological appearing (avakkanti) and development (patiṭṭhitaṃ). For instance, it is said that “once consciousness is established and developed, there is the appearing of n/r” (attha patiṭṭhitaṃ viññāṇaṃ virūḷhaṃ, atthi tattha nāmarūpassa avakkanti).
It remains true that consciousness, in its role as an element discerning the sensible reality, segments “forms” into recognizable cognitive prototypes, thereby perpetuating the circular nature of the five aggregates. From the apprehension of a given form as a cognitive datum, the mechanism proceeds with the elaboration of sensations, their association with fundamental percepts, the correlation of these percepts with related eidetic constructs, and thus their relationship with consciousness. From here, the cycle continues: consciousness will preferentially recognize, in its explored environment, those same forms that align with prototypical cognitive models. Consequently, consciousness continues to act as an agent that “segments” the formal phenomenological continuum into individual, discrete phenomena that can be cognitively isolated and thus apprehended as distinct “forms”.
This cycle involves two aspects of the concept of form: the original aspect of the phenomenological continuum and the discrete aspect of the learned cognitive form. However, it does not encompass the relational nexus between form and name that comprises the n/r pair, in which the formal aspect must be understood as co-dependent with the nominal aspect [43,74,75].
We better understand this problem when we see that MN 109 connects it to the conception of identity (sakkāyadiṭṭhi) ([51], p. 1134). To form the conception (the term diṭṭhi is not used accidentally) of the autonomy of a given psychophysical entity (sakkāya, from sat-kāya, the existence of a body), it is necessary for a particular element of a psychosemantic nature, such as the agent n/r, to be perceived as something self-standing. Observing a certain entity in the world—a body not merely understood as an organism but anything that constitutes, in itself, an identity boundary in our perceptions—we realize that the perception of its autonomy, translated into an identity conception (sakkāya), is derived precisely from its being an n/r; that is, a certain formal givenness (rūpa) associated with a nominal identity (nāma). Of a certain formal continuum, we determine that, under certain conditions, some of those formal aspects, and not others, are to be considered autonomous. We then associate with that precise formality a given nominal identity, something that qualifies it as distinct from others.
In other words, “internal” refers to the subjective aspects of experience, namely, the six senses and their corresponding consciousnesses. Therefore, the six sense bases constitute the body (kāya), and the body is accompanied by or possessing (sa-) consciousness (vijñāna). “Externally”, meanwhile, are the objects of experience, which are names (nāman) and forms (rūpa), or more generally, “all signs (sarvanimitta)”. These can be further analyzed as being of six types, and are objective in the sense that they are not taken as part of the sentient being that is considered the subjective experiencer. This interpretation of internal and external as the subjective and objective aspects of experience can be further confirmed by the sūtras’ explicit references to the six sense bases (āyatana) as “internal” (ajjhattika), and to their respective objects as “external” (bāhira).
([43], p. 346)
In this sense, the n/r dyad is the fundamental quality of any psychosemantic construct, from our self-perception of identity to that of an object such as a “vase”. The determining principle is the same, which is why MN 109 recognizes that the n/r dyad is the condition for the functioning of discernment (viññāṇakkhandha). My identity is defined by a series of qualities nominally attributed to me: from my registered name to my profession or education, my address, physical characteristics, and so forth. All these qualities, coordinated by specific names, are the various x, y, and z that define me: I “am” x, y, z. These qualities associate with my identity to define me by opposition. This, it should be noted, is their sole function: distinguishing who is x, y, z, from who “is not” x, y, z, and who may instead be a, b, c. The “vase” is not a “table”, and the “table” is not a “chair”, and so forth.
The issue, which for the Buddha is the core of this cognitive deception, lies in attributing ontological autonomy to these characteristics instead of recognizing them as epiphenomena that we have surreptitiously abstracted from a continuum, and which therefore remain inseparable from that fundamental complex web of relationships. This does not mean denying the differences in their aspects, but rather that these differences do not imply, as the human cognitive apparatus unconsciously seems to assume, autonomy in essence. Believing that a thing “is a self” means, in these Buddhist terms, believing that it is autonomous and self-sufficient; nothing more. And this is the true core of the problem: “they regard the form as self, as having a form, as self in form, or form in self” (rūpaṃ attato samanupassati rūpavantaṃ vā attānaṃ attani vā rūpaṃ rūpasmiṃ vā attānaṃ).
In this sense, nāma can be better understood as an inhibitory process that reduces cognitive responses to certain perceptual stimuli, systematically relating them to known determinations, to already acquired identities, and thus not experiencing perceptual stimuli as new but as part of a recognizable system. For this reason, we can say that nāma, heading the n/r dyad, is a process of habituation of perceptions. Habituation is any inhibitory process that progressively suppresses a response to certain recurring stimuli. Just as someone wearing a tight bracelet will, after a certain period, grow accustomed to the presence of that stimulus and no longer notice the bracelet, in our “world” (understood as loka, and thus especially as a network of incorporated sociocultural dynamics), the fundamental recurring stimuli are reiterated through systems of values conveyed by linguistic signs or ordered by them.
We somatically respond to certain conceptual stimuli, and just as we “conform” our body to certain stimuli automatically, other stimuli are inhibited in their novelty value because they are recognized as something familiar and manageable. In our psycholinguistical dimensions, the recurring stimuli acts as “signs”, and the Buddhist contemplative practice aims to attain a state of complete liberation from the influence of any sign; that is, a state of complete signlessness (animitta) [76,77].
In the cultural world where the concept of the “president” has a certain value, the body of the individual holding the presidential office becomes an emitter of psychosemantic signals recognizable to other subjects for whom those particular signs hold a certain value. Conforming to those signals, our body reacts: it “bends”, it bows in deference. This is a mechanism far from merely theoretical but stimulates significant bodily reactions: it is the actualization of Hegel’s master–slave dynamic.
This is not even a uniquely human prerogative. In the world of bees, a body capable of emitting signals that hold value for some but not for others is, for instance, a flower. The bee can recognize the signs/signals of the flower as having value for it because it has a particular relationship with that body and thus recognizes its effectors. The flower, too, benefits from its relationship with the bee, constituting a functional circuit with it, as part of a shared ecological environment. A rock, as is evident, will not emit signals of the same value to the bee. Another example is described below:
We see the bees in their surroundings, a meadow in bloom, in which blossoming flowers alternate with closed buds. If one places the bees in their environment and transforms the blooms according to their shape into stars or crosses, the buds will take the form of circles. From this, the biological meaning of this newly discovered characteristic of the bees is effortlessly apparent. Only the blooms, not the buds, have meaning for the bees.
([42], p. 84)
Habit prevents us from marveling each time certain values act in our daily lives. In the complexification of cognition that humans achieve through language, there is also the expectation that the world is populated by “things” and “names”; that is, by identities inherent to each thing. This expectation is so strong that even when we do not know the name of something, we are nonetheless certain that it possesses an identity, and we can assume “not knowing the name”; such is the conviction that the world is populated by “things” merely awaiting their appropriate labels. Thus, when we walk in the park and see a “flower” or a “tree”, we are not amazed: we are “accustomed” to these stimuli because we immediately associate them with known identities. Even if we were to encounter a flower we have never seen before, our astonishment would still be minimal: it would be a flower with an unknown name, but it is necessarily “something”.
This mechanism also operates as a function of conformity to specific sociocultural norms that are not questioned by the bodies assimilating them. The “king”, along with all the values connected to his figure, such as superiority over “lower classes” (“class” being another value—values, of course, exist within a network of relationships that define their interconnections), imposes his semiotic value with a force that is not contested by the “subject”, who has accepted the value of their social identity and conforms automatically, fulfilling their “social duties” without objection (see, for example, Snp 1.10, Snp 1.7 and variants found in Snp 3.9 and MN 98) ([78], p. 152), ([79], p. 178), ([80], pp. 21–22), [81,82,83,84].
Although Buddhists give a decidedly unique characterization to the n/r binomial, and their psychological conception of this factor’s functioning is undoubtedly part of their innovations, it should be noted that it is already mentioned in the Upaniṣadic world13.
The n/r dyad produces yoking (see SN 12.58), chaining, “fettering” (saṃyojaniya), and possesses the nature of a bond. It can be understood in two ways: either it yokes the subject to its power, or it “binds” or “chains” itself to the subject to act. In both cases, the pervasiveness and invasiveness of its mechanism are unquestionable. The term saṃyojaniya also relates to obstruction in addition to chaining (fettering, bonding): n/r is an obstructive element to immediate perception. Furthermore, the n/r dyad is the phenomenal condition for the six sense organs (nāmarūpapaccayā saḷāyatanaṃ).
DN 14 emphasizes not only the relationship between n/r and the sensory spheres (‘nāmarūpe kho sati saḷāyatanaṃ hoti, nāmarūpapaccayā saḷāyatanan’ti) but also the direct connection between n/r and consciousness (‘nāmarūpe kho sati viññāṇaṃ hoti, nāmarūpapaccayā viññāṇan’ti), further relating the two phenomena (nāmarūpapaccayā viññāṇaṃ, viññāṇapaccayā nāmarūpaṃ, nāmarūpapaccayā saḷāyatanaṃ).
DN 15 elucidates the rationale for this interconnection. Here, it is explained that n/r serves as the condition both for consciousness and for sensory phenomena due to its pervasiveness in the relational nexus, i.e., in contact (phassa). On the other hand, its obstructive nature (saṃyojaniya) already suggests that n/r is the quintessential mediating element in experiential processes. DN 15 identifies n/r as the specific condition for contact (‘nāmarūpapaccayā phasso’ti iccassa vacanīyaṃ).
This signifies something crucial: Buddhists do not conceive of contact as a purely relational nexus, such as the interdependence of phenomena—the idea that every phenomenon is tightly interconnected with every other. Instead, contact is an apprehensive agency, a grasping in the Husserlian sense (Erfassen), ([85], pp. 14–15), and thus an act of relating to something after having cognitively isolated it beforehand, i.e., having conceived it as an autonomous phenomenal aggregation. For this reason, n/r is a condition of phassa, and the circle closes in the following two phrases, where the n/r dyad is identified as being “conditioned” by consciousness itself (viññāṇapaccayā nāmarūpaṃ).
This leads to an apparent paradox: mutual conditionality. The fundamental contact with form, which initiates the chain of the five aggregates, is evidently the contact with the sensory spheres (saḷāyatana), as these are the only ones producing “sensation”. However, the sensory spheres are themselves conditioned by n/r: “name-and-form is the condition for consciousness, consciousness is the condition for name-and-form; name-and-form is the condition for contact, contact is the condition for sensation” (nāmarūpapaccayā viññāṇaṃ, viññāṇapaccayā nāmarūpaṃ, nāmarūpapaccayā phasso, phassapaccayā vedanā). We can observe several examples of this process in the Pāli canon. For instance, Iti 41 discusses a genuine form of habituation to n/r, a condition in which this force is fully established (niviṭṭhaṃ nāmarūpasmiṃ) and leads to the belief in absolute truths (idaṃ saccanti maññati). Dhp 221 attributes to the n/r dyad a nature connected to attachment14, or at least suggests that attachment fuels the mechanism underlying it. The same is stated in SN 1.34 (taṃ nāmarūpasmimasajjamānaṃ, akiñcanaṃ nānupatanti dukkhā) and SN 1.36 (saṃyojanaṃ sabbamatikkameyya; taṃ nāmarūpasmimasajjamānaṃ…). DN 15 further informs us that name is something seen as possessing “features, attributes, signs, and details through which the aggregate of phenomena” allows what is called name to be recognized (ākārehi yehi liṅgehi yehi nimittehi yehi uddesehi nāmakāyassa paññatti hoti). In the absence of these factors enabling the appearance of the nominal phenomenon, even form could not be found (tesu ākāresu tesu liṅgesu tesu nimittesu tesu uddesesu asati api nu kho rūpakāye adhivacanasamphasso paññāyetha).

6. The n/r Dyad Is a Primary Semiosis Function

There are several reasons to hypothesize that Buddhists attribute the origin of the sensory spheres to the n/r dyad, but the most probable is the fact that the n/r dyad, being fundamental to consciousness, has a direct impact on the sensory spheres. This is because the sensory spheres are considered functional only insofar as they lead to the arising of their corresponding consciousness. Indeed, each of the six sensory spheres has its respective consciousness, which arises in relation to the contact between the sensory organ and the formal effector. Since every consciousness is solely a consciousness of something, and since the specific consciousness of an organ exists only in relation to its interaction with an effector, it follows that the consciousness of the sensory organs has merely a functional basis and does not represent a distinct entity: it is implicit in the functions of the sensory organ. For example, from the contact between the eye and a visual form arises visual consciousness; similarly, from the contact between the ear and an acoustic form—such as a sound or a given “acoustic image”, to use Saussure’s terminology (image acoustique)—arises a specific auditory consciousness suited to analyze it, and so forth.
Le caractère psychique de nos images acoustiques apparaît bien quand nous observons notre propre langage. Sans remuer les lèvres ni la langue, nous pouvons nous parler à nous-mêmes ou nous réciter mentalement une pièce de vers. C’est parce que les mots de la langue sont pour nous des images acoustiques qu’il faut éviter de parler des « phonèmes » dont ils sont composés.
([18], p. 152)
Nonetheless, the suttas also highlight the merely semantic nature of the n/r dyad, and thus its grounding in a primarily linguistic function. This is not necessarily understood as articulated language, but as something upon which even articulated language is based: the essential processes of discernment and organization of entities in the world into “things” endowed with their specific “names”. For example, the nāma forms another dyad in MN 98, namely nāmagotta (name-clan). Belonging to a specific clan as a determining factor in an individual’s life is another of those mechanisms of attribution and designation to which the Buddha appeared particularly averse: “the householder cannot compete with the mendicant: the sage who meditates sheltered in the forest” (evaṃ gihī nānukaroti bhikkhuno, munino vivittassa vanamhi jhāyatoti, Snp 1.12). Countless sections of the canon attest to the Buddha’s strong rejection of the idea that family or “birth” (jāti) should determine an individual’s life (Snp 1.7), as is also evident in MN 98.
  • samaññā hesā lokasmiṃ,
  • nāmagottaṃ pakappitaṃ;
  • sammuccā samudāgataṃ,
  • tattha tattha pakappitaṃ.
  • Merely by designation in the world,
  • is the name-and-family conceived;
  • Arise by virtue of common consensus,
  • Thus conceived for everyone.
It appears evident that the name, at the head of the n/r binomial, renders the latter essentially a semiosis device, much like consciousness, which primarily enacts the divisive aspect of semiosis; that is, the discernment between two signs perceived as distinct. Semiosis is the process through which a sign acquires a certain meaning and is perceptively interpreted by its recipient, thereby enabling communication and mutual understanding [68,72,73]. In other words, it is the activity of producing, transmitting, and interpreting signs through which meaning is constructed and shared. The semiosis of division is also what makes the binomial langue/parole possible within the Saussurean framework. It must be noted that this distinction is primarily based on “psychic” facts (to use Saussure’s terminology)15 that conform to historically established social and cultural networks.
La partie physique peut être écartée d’emblée. Quand nous entendons parler une langue que nous ignorons, nous percevons bien les sons, mais, par notre incompréhension, nous restons en dehors du fait social. La partie physique n’est pas non plus tout entière en jeu: le côté exécutif reste hors de cause, car l’exécution n’est jamais faite par la masse; elle est toujours le maître; nous l’appellerons la *parole*. C’est par le fonctionnement des facultés réceptive er coordinative que se forment chez les sujets parlants des empreintes qui arrivent à être sensiblement les mêmes chez tous. Comment faut-il se représenter ce produit social pour que la langue apparaisse parfaitement dégagée du reste? Si nous pouvons embrasser la somme des images verbales emmagasinées chez tous les individus, nous toucherions le lien social qui constitue la langue.
([18], pp. 78–79)
The first work to compare semiosis to the n/r binomial was an article by Edward Small [86], which engaged in a comparative dialogue with Saussure. However, Small argues that the n/r binomial allows for epistemological possibilities that Saussure chose to ignore, despite his knowledge of Sanskrit. Today, we know that Small was partially mistaken: with the publication of Saussure’s unpublished writings [87], we gain further insight into his conceptions, and many similarities between his thought and Buddhist philosophy acquire new significance. Certainly, Small correctly identifies the potential of the n/r binomial, particularly in view of its mutual dependence with “the human sensorium”, which indicates a conception “that is neither positivist nor materialist but which rather suggests that signs are constitutive devices for cognitive-perceptual categorization” ([86], p. 458).
Regarding the claim that Saussure ignored this literature, I am, however, skeptical. The publication of the Harvard manuscripts suggests the exact opposite ([17], p. 79), and although these writings are disorganized, it is evident that Saussure’s passion transcended mere dialogue with Indian grammarians (where the concept of nāmarūpa does not appear prominently). He was a conscious and attentive reader of Buddhist issues as well, and there is reason to suspect that a dualistic model (such as that of nāmarūpa, though not necessarily confined to it) permeating all descriptions of cognitive deceptions as understood in Pāli Buddhism might underlie the antinomy between signifier and signified. Here, the signifier, which Saussure himself understands as a cognitively learned datum rather than a physical fact (physicality itself is relatively marginal to the interests of Saussurean “semiology”) ([18], p. 81), ([19], pp. 43–44), may be comparable to the idea of nāma, understood as a nominal signifier paired with a given cognitive form (for Saussure, they are merely “faits de conscience” that determine the functional circuit underlying language) ([18], pp. 76–77), a formal meaning (rūpa) that, again, is understood as a specific cognitive prototype: the mental image of the ideal tree, which serves as the model to which the perception of every phenomenal tree is associated.
Le fond ou le tréfond de la réflexion hindoue sur les choses réside, à ce que je crois, dans l’idée de substance qui a dominé entièrement l’imagination de ces peuples, car une substance est à la fois ce qui développe des effets et ce qui reste inaltérable à travers les formes.
([87], p. 220)
But the most interesting reflection that Saussure makes in the Harvard manuscripts concerns precisely the concept of identity as a psychosemantic obstruction:
Le procédé philosophique de l’esprit hindou est invariablement le même: 1° il écarte le monde, et les sensations qui en proviennent/2° il lui reste « l’intime » et il suppose que ce moi sans qualités ni affections possibles est identique à la substance universelle. Les différences ne sont que des variations sur ces deux thèmes, même quand elles aboutissent (beaucoup de ratures) à modifier un des 2 centres fondamentaux en niant absolument le moi, comme dans l’idée bouddhique, ou en multipliant les moi comme dans la philosophie sânkhya.
([87], p. 221)
On pourrait caractériser comme suit le conflit fondamental entre l’Inde et notre pensée occidentale. Pour cette dernière la question s’est posée séculairement entre le moi, comprenant ses sensations, et le non-moi/et pour l’Inde, éternellement, entre le non-moi et le moi en excluant du moi les sensations elles-mêmes, comme non différentes de l’objet […].
([87], p. 222)
It may not primarily assume the form of “conflict”, as Saussure notes in his writings, but it is certain that the conception of the psychological, as we have seen in the problem of sakkāyadiṭṭhi—that of perceived psychological identities—is fundamentally a psychosemantic issue. In its critique of dualism and the semiosis of dividing, Buddhism emphasizes this central aspect: the division between perceiving subject and perceived object may hold practical utility, but it does not concretely reflect reality, which is rather a complex network of phenomena that are distinct yet not autonomous, differentiated yet not self-sufficient, characteristic yet not truly separate from one another16.
This is the fundamental critique of perceptual dualism (ultimately extending into a critique of dualism, in general, as a system insufficient to account for phenomenological complexities). Beyond this theme, which is fascinating but merits separate treatment, Buddhists understand—and Saussure perceives—that the principle of divisive semiosis, namely a mechanism that organizes perceptions on a dualistic basis, underpins the construction of human “worlds”. This principle also applies to the n/r binomial, which is a dualistic principle of biosemiotic systems. Saussure further identifies this level of complexity, speaking of “unceasing duality” in psycholinguistic systems ([19], pp. 17–18). He views linguistics as a science closely related to psychology precisely because the principles of language essentially describe problems of a perceptual and cognitive nature.
In this sense, Saussure’s unpublished writings are extremely valuable to us, as they help better define the problem—one that Saussure clearly grasped—of the relationship between language and perception. In defining the actual object of linguistic study, he writes that the issue primarily concerns the constitution of “points of view” (points de vue). Buddhists might refer to this as diṭṭhi. The essence of this reflection is as follows: prior to language, it can be said that there are no determined points of view. At the same time, precisely because language determines “points of view” in the cognition of speakers, studying language while attempting to position oneself outside a point of view becomes a rather arduous endeavor ([19], p. 19). The proximity of this reasoning to the same problems highlighted in Pāli Buddhism is, of course, striking—particularly in the suttas like Snp 4.317, Snp 4.918, or Snp 4.1419, which critiques the problematic nature of adherence to any “point of view”. This is comparable to Saussure’s discussion of the indefinite referral of points of view: for instance, positioning oneself in a stance that seeks to exclude a certain point of view A means adopting another determined point of view, such as B, whose identity is defined by its intent to be non-A but which does not escape the problem itself. The issue persists as long as one seeks to define a science through the specification of names and concepts: “parler d’un objet, nommer un objet, ce n’est pas autre chose que d’invoquer un point de vue A déterminé” ([19], p. 23). Furthermore, Saussure continues, a given point of view A is equipped with its corresponding concepts/names, which have value only relative to the determined point of view A. Establishing a different order, B, would not resolve the problem but would merely create a different system based on the same functional principle.
One of the most comprehensive explanations of the nominal function is provided in MN 9. In this sutta, it is explicitly explained what is meant by nāmarūpa, and specifically how to understand nāma and rūpa. As previously mentioned, rūpa is essentially understood as cognitively apprehensible phenomenal possibilities. While it is not of primary interest in this context, it would certainly be relevant in a paper focused on the physical ontological conceptions of early Buddhism, given that such phenomenal aspects are substantially described through the model of the four elements (cattāri ca mahābhūtāni).
As for nāma, it is identified as consisting of five fundamental elements, three of which are also part of the five aggregates (technically two, since “contact” is implicitly considered part of the aggregates as it enables perceptual processes, but it is not included in the list beginning with rūpa). These constituents are sensation (vedanā), perception (saññā), intention (the term cetanā has a broad connotation of volition, but we must understand it more in the sense of the Latin intendō), contact, and attention (the term manasikāra also has a broad volitional connotation, but since it pertains to thought, manas, we can interpret it as a set of conceivable possibilities of the perceived “thing”, its “thinkabilities”).
  • yato kho, āvuso, ariyasāvako nāmarūpañca pajānāti, nāmarūpa-samudayañca pajānāti, nāmarūpanirodhañca pajānāti, nāmarūpanirodhagāminiṃ paṭipadañca pajānāti—
  • katamaṃ panāvuso, nāmarūpaṃ, katamo nāmarūpasamudayo, katamo nāmarūpanirodho, katamā nāmarūpanirodhagāminī paṭipadā?
  • vedanā, saññā, cetanā, phasso, manasikāro—idaṃ vuccatāvuso, nāmaṃ;
  • cattāri ca mahābhūtāni, catunnañca mahābhūtānaṃ upādāyarūpaṃ—idaṃ vuccatāvuso, rūpaṃ.
  • iti idañca nāmaṃ idañca rūpaṃ—
  • idaṃ vuccatāvuso, nāmarūpaṃ.
  • viññāṇasamudayā nāmarūpasamudayo, viññāṇanirodhā nāmarūpanirodho, ayameva ariyo aṭṭhaṅgiko maggo nāmarūpanirodhagāminī paṭipadā, seyyathidaṃ—
  • A noble disciple perfectly understands what names and forms are, what their origin is, their cessation, and what practices lead to their cessation. But what are name and form? What is their origin, their cessation, and the practice that leads to their cessation?
  • Sensation, perception, intention, contact, and attention;
  • This is called “name”;
  • The four primary elements and the form derived from the four primary elements;
  • This is called “form”.
  • Thus, this is name and this is form.
  • This (together) is called name-and-form.
  • Name and form arise from consciousness. Name and form cease when consciousness ceases. The practice leading to the cessation of name and form is simply the noble eightfold path.
  • (MN 9)
Apart from reiterating the mutual dependence of the n/r dyad with consciousness, this text further clarifies that the dyad itself indeed has its own constituents or, at least, modes through which it should be understood. The nominal aspect is a functional ensemble very similar to that of the five aggregates and can, in fact, plausibly be traced back to the same model of reasoning. However, since these are nominal entities, and not phenomena in a broader sense, they exhibit certain modifications that characterize their cognitive nature: sensation and perception constitute the first two elements, followed by volition (cetanā), contact, and a second volitional aspect referred to as manasikāra.
nāma ⇆ (vedanā, saññā, cetanā, phassa, manasikāra)
The term cetanā, which is easy to understand, derives from the same root as citta—that is, cognition—and specifically represents its volitional aspect. When used in combination with the genitive, cetanā conveys the concept of “having the intention” to do something, or, in English, “with will to”. In this case, it functions as an adjective. The feminine noun cetanā, on the other hand, means “intending” or “willing”. However, I would not translate cetanā simply as “intention”, because this term, beyond its strictly volitional sense, also encompasses another meaning, akin to the Latin intentiō: “tension”, “effort”, or “tending toward” (intendō, in-tendō) [88].
Although the two meanings—“volitional intention” and “intention as tension toward”—share a common etymological origin, the technical use of the latter term refers to the directing of consciousness’s attention toward a specific object. This act establishes a relationship between consciousness and the object, creating the characteristic connection whereby consciousness is “of something” and that something is “the object of attention”.
The term manasikāra, which I translate here as “attention” due to its common rendering, also implies an intentional element. In this analysis, I will use “intention” in the specific sense of an investment of attention. For the time being, therefore, we will translate manasikāra as “attention” and cetanā as “volition”, avoiding rendering both as “intention”. It is important to note, however, that the term “intention” will later be adopted in a technical sense to refer exclusively to manasikāra.
The two terms cetanā and manasikāra, respectively, represent volitional intentionality and attentive intentionality, describing two distinct moments of cognitive experience. The order in which the factors composing what we call “name” (nāma) are listed is significant. Just as the five aggregates form a dynamic cycle with a precise sequence, so too is the order of the components of nāma non-arbitrary. The description of the nāma phenomenon indeed illustrates the process through which it operates in our experience, following the stages of sensation, perception, volition, contact, and attention.
We can also understand this analysis of cognitive processes as a complex structure of relationships between three different sets, whose elements, which are fundamental moments of the perceptual–cognitive process, are partly in intersection with each other. Thus, we will have three main sets, which I will refer to as K (the five khandhas), S (the sign understood as signifier and signified, i.e., nāma and rūpa), and a specific set for the signifier (Σ).
Σ = {vedanā, saññā, cetanā, phassa, manasikāra}
K = {rūpa, vedanā, saññā, saṅkhāra, viññāṇa}
S = nāma ∪ {rūpa}
Relationships between the sets:
1. Σ ⊆ S
2. Σ ∩ K = {vedanā, saññā}
3. nāma ∉ K
In this representation, the term rūpa is not indicated as signified solely because this specific meaning is part of rūpa in its semiotic association with nāma. In the nāmarūpa dyad, in fact, the sign is represented in Saussurean terms as a bifacial entity formed by a concept (which in this dyad is a formal, acquired datum) and an acoustic image (the nominal signifier). However, rūpa also lends itself to indicating any potential form, and for this reason, the suttas also identifies it simply as the four great elements (mahābhūtāni)20, which constitute the starting basis for constructing conceptual prototypes.
If nāma is the signifier within the system of psycho-semantic experiences, then this sequence must be interpreted as the progressive acquisition of elements necessary for attributing a specific meaning. The acoustic image serves as the counterpart of the concept, and while the latter is a cognitively structured form, the former assigns the appropriate signifier only after the corresponding concept has been recognized.
The notion that form should be understood exclusively as a cognitive form—and hence as a cognitively apprehended datum rather than a simple geometric or visual form—is also confirmed by Saussurean theory, where the concept of form encompasses any cognitively structured datum that serves a functional role within the linguistic system. Accordingly, we encounter not only visual forms but also acoustic forms, among others. Form, therefore, is primarily a type of information: the organization of data into a specific structure. The essence of formality lies in the structuring of differences. Form x is shaped in a way that distinguishes it from form y, but these distinctions are determined by specific organizational principles: the datum x is recognizable by virtue of the configuration (adoption of form) attributed to it as its own, which differentiates it from that of y. For this reason, Saussure conceives of form as a relation of diversity and plurality, which is the very manner in which the “significant value” (valeur significative) of each specific form is structured ([19], pp. 35–36). Difference (différence), a principle similarly described in Buddhist thought, is indeed what enables the determination of meaning: “1° Un signe n’existe qu’en vertu de sa signification; 2° une signification n’existe qu’en vertu de son signe; 3° signes et significations n’existent qu’en vertu de la différence des signes” ([19], p. 37).
In Saussurean linguistics, this fundamental duality forms the basis of the linguistic sign. In Saussure’s theory, the sign is a psychic entity (and Saussure emphasizes its primarily psychic nature) with “two faces” (entité psychique à deux faces) ([18], p. 153). These two faces are technically defined as “concept” and “acoustic image”. Saussure insists that this is not about “things” and “names”, which are already embedded in a cultural dimension. At the level of linguistic technicality, the concept is an ideal prototypical form [89,90], preceding any specific “thing”, which is already characterized by its historical, cultural, and value-laden dimensions. Similarly, the acoustic image is not a physical ensemble of sounds but a codified set of phonemes; that is, sounds which are psychically recognized as bearing a specific value within the linguistic system that incorporates them into its phonological inventory. For example, English does not utilize sounds like [ʎ] and [ɳ] to construct its lexemes, and therefore, they are not productive within its system. Even if these sounds are physically perceived, an English speaker would not associate them with anything meaningful within their linguistic system.
Le signe linguistique unit non une chose et un nom, mais un concept et une image acoustique. Cette dernière n’est pas le son matériel, chose purement physique, mais l’empreinte psychique de ce son, la représentation que nous en donne le témoigne de nos sens; elle sensorielle, et s’il nous arrive de l’appeler « matérielle », c’est seulement dans ce sens et par opposition à l’autre terme de l’association, le concept, généralement plus abstrait.
([18], p. 152)
This process is fundamental to the definitive recognition of the “thing” we have before us. Just as the interpretation of a specific phonetic chain is made possible by psychological processes that associate certain phonemes with “recognizable” words through the associative principles enabled by one’s acquired phonetic apparatus and mental lexicon, similarly, the recognition of a particular thing, referring back to its prototypical concept of belonging, is fundamentally a semiotic mechanism.
The sign is, as stated, “la combinaison du concept et de l’image acoustique” ([18], p. 153), but the sign is evidently such in its completeness. Just as the n/r dyad functions as something seemingly autonomous and capable of semiotically characterizing our experience of the world, so too the linguistic sign, which we can understand as the unified dyad of signifier/signified—that is, acoustic-image/concept (A/C)—operates perceptually only when considered in its unity. Nonetheless, just as we can examine the n/r dyad in its fundamental components as distinct semiotic potencies, the composition of the sign should also be viewed in its constituent units, even though these components are interconnected when they function as a specific “sign”.
Saussure represents the A/C dyad with a famous oval diagram divided into two parts. I have adapted this A/C dyad for comparison with the n/r dyad, as the Buddhists place the name at the head of the sign, whereas Saussure inverts this, positioning the concept above and the acoustic image below.
Philosophies 10 00031 i001
The model above is used by Saussure to express the C/A binomial (signifié/significant). The concept in this example is the idea of a tree, whereas the signifier has been represented as one of the possible phonic executions of the word/tree/. We can easily apply this model to the n/r dyad, as shown in the example below.
Philosophies 10 00031 i004
What interests us in this representation is how it explains the semiological process of perception. The concept functions as a fundamental prototypical idea, rather than as a defined image: the drawing of the tree represents how the process works. However, the mental image of the tree that a speaker forms when acquiring the concept associated with the word “tree” obviously differs for each individual and is especially subject to change over time. The role of the “conceptual form” is solely to serve as a reference prototype: it must constitute the ideal tree, a set of general characteristics (it has branches, a trunk, and leaves; is large; and grows from the ground…) that allow this ideal–typical conception to be associated with all the “trees” designated by the sign of which this concept is a part. While Saussure does not delve into the process of semiotic apprehension, Buddhists focus on how such “recognition” occurs in the experiential dimension.
As we have seen, sensation represents the most elementary experience: it does not have a clearly defined identity, which will only be determined later. We use terms such as “smooth”, “rough”, “warm”, or “cold”, but every sensory experience is extremely complex. Sensation is this raw experience, distinct from the idea of “smooth” or “cold”, which instead represents already well-defined and delimited identities.
Perception follows sensation as the next step in determining identity. If sensation still resides in the “indistinct nebula of meaning”, as Saussure would say, perception begins to trace semantic boundaries (see Figure 3). It is the first intervention that organizes and delineates that nebula, assigning specific identities, such as A, B, or C, to its various areas ([18], p. 216).
This state of primordial indistinction that precedes conscious determinations is also a fact discussed in Buddhism. Specifically, MN 43 serves as an excellent example of this dynamic. In this sutta, we also find a precise definition of the functions of the five aggregates, based on verbs constructed from the same semantic root as the corresponding nouns. For instance: “It is called consciousness because it discerns” (vijānāti vijānātī’ti kho, āvuso, tasmā viññāṇanti vuccati). The use of the verb vijānāti to further specify the function of viññāṇa is particularly helpful. Both terms are constructed from vi- (“to divide”) and -(j)ñā (“to know”), and this text reiterates that the relationship between the two is also functional: viññāṇa is “something” that performs an action described by vijānāti. The text further specifies that “It discerns (things such as) “pleasure”, “pain”, and “neutral’” (sukhantipi vijānāti, dukkhantipi vijānāti, adukkhamasukhantipi vijānāti). This cognitive act is precisely what I defined at the beginning as discernment. Consciousness is able to distinguish, to organize things by dividing them into A, B, C, and the example provided is indeed nominal in nature: consciousness “recognizes”, that is, discerns, what can be defined as “pleasant” from what can be defined as “unpleasant”, or even from what is neither one nor the other21.
The text also provides further significant considerations regarding the definition of the other aggregates, all of which are described using verbs derived from the same semantic root as the associated term. Thus, sensation (vedanā) is defined as that which “feels” (vedeti), while perception (saññā) is that which “perceives” (sañjānāti). Sensation is always linked to what is pleasant, unpleasant, or neutral, but we might suppose that in this case, these terms are not being used conceptually but rather sensorially (vedeti). Sensation “feels” like something that can be defined as pleasant or unpleasant, and so forth. Regarding perception, we encounter an interesting definition: the verb sañjānāti pertains to synthetic–associative knowledge (it puts together saṃ-), but we also know that it is a form of semantic and prototypical perception, awaiting clearer classification through eidetic associations and consciousness. If sañjānāti is a form of primary semantic association, this definition would align with that provided in MN 43, which states that perception “perceives” things such as “blue, yellow, red, white” (nīlakampi sañjānāti, pītakampi sañjānāti, lohitakampi sañjānāti, odātampi sañjānāti). These are fundamental associations based on semantic prototypes—a level necessarily followed by further stratification, brought about by eidetic associations. Fundamental perception begins by associating sensory elements with primary semantic identities: if I extend my hand and grasp a pen, I will receive a series of tactile and visual sensory stimuli from it, which I will subsequently “qualify” by associating them with the corresponding cognitive prototypes—“blue”, if the pen is blue. The eidetic associations will then lead toward the discernment of that object as a “pen”, linking all perceptions to the corresponding conceptual possibilities: what is oblong, cylindrical, blue, light, smooth, etc.?
However, MN 43 tells us that this mechanism of association and recognition of the object by the perceptual–cognitive system operates upon something that, in itself, is undivided: “Sensation, perception, and consciousness; these things are interwoven, not separate, and you will never be able to completely separate them in order to describe the differences between them, since you perceive what you feel and you know what you perceive” (vedanā yā ca saññā yañca viññāṇaṃ—ime dhammā saṃsaṭṭhā, no visaṃsaṭṭhā; na ca labbhā imesaṃ dhammānaṃ vinibbhujitvā vinibbhujitvā nānākaraṇaṃ paññāpetuṃ; yaṃ… vedeti taṃ sañjānāti, yaṃ sañjānāti taṃ vijānāti).
Once the object is recognized through sañjānāti, we can direct our intention toward it, although at this stage it remains an embryonic and volitional intentionality. After recognizing the object as, for example, a “cup”, or a “pen”, we can think of the cup in various ways: we might grasp it, observe it, move it, or break it. Contemplating these possibilities involves associating the object identified as a “cup” with a range of potential actions. This process represents the initial form of intentionality: volition.
At this stage, contact serves to confirm the object’s actual identity and its potentialities. It is important to note that contact is implicit in every process of nominal identity attribution: perceiving a sensation, such as the whiteness of a cup, necessitates contact between the sensory organ and the object. However, here, contact is explicitly addressed only after the volitional phase, as it describes a specific process of nominal recognition. For example, when we touch a table and perceive its smoothness, we are processing the data provided by the contact between our body and the object. Yet, to attribute a name such as “table”, we must advance to a subsequent phase, which elevates the raw sensory data to the semantic level.
At this stage, the object is recognized as a “table” and becomes available for use. Once an identity is attributed, the table presents itself as something manipulable. This process culminates in volition (cetanā), which implies the ability to use the identified object.
The three phases of semantic apprehension of nāma thus unfold as follows (based on MN 9):
  • Processing sensory data and associating perception with semantic identity (vedanā, saññā).
  • Correct attribution of identity and investment of will in the recognized object (cetanā).
  • Active use of the identified object, accompanied by intentional contact (phasso, manasikāro).
Initially, contact occurs involuntarily, serving the purpose of collecting sensory data. Subsequently, contact becomes voluntary, as in the case of intentionally grasping an object. This is not merely a physical action: even a focused gaze upon the object as “usable” constitutes intentional contact. After identifying the object as a “cup”, this volitional contact enables the association of the object with a range of practical possibilities, such as using it to drink tea22.
Finally, manasikāra represents the intentional act of actualizing these possibilities. It is the active aspect of “doing” (kara), originating from the mind (manas). This process translates thought into practical action directed toward the recognized object. For example, the cup, initially perceived solely through sensory data, is identified as a container of hot tea and, through primary volition, becomes the focus of concrete actions such as grasping it and drinking.

7. The Action of the Semiosis of Division: Value and Perception

A final problem remains to be addressed regarding the “determinative” power of the n/r binary, and this issue pertains to the force of valorization. I have previously mentioned the term “value”, but I intend to clarify precisely what this term describes and how it applies to Buddhist semiological theory23.
Valorization is a process inherent to the semiosis of the division enacted by n/r, which assigns a specific culturally and historically determined meaning to the concept delineated by the semiotic boundaries of n/r. Value is something primarily perceived by subjects and encompasses various aspects, such as the “functions” of the determined entity, its “utility” within the historical–cultural dimension, and thus its “possibilities” for interaction with us. This logic, embedded within the problem of identity, also applies to us as subjects existing in the world. To return to the Buddhist discourse, it becomes evident that those endowed with a certain “familial” identity (a particular nāmagotta) also carry with them specific values: individuals belonging to nobler castes are inevitably perceived as “superior” and impose upon “inferior” individuals the obligation to conform to these logics. In the presence of a king, one bows; the body conforms, bends (literally) before the “sign” emanated by the sovereign—a sign of royalty that carries a specific value. Just as this applies to subjects, so too are objects yoked to the same logics. And this does not pertain merely to “value” in economic terms, though it is undeniable that in a culture where a particular monetary value is attributed to a precious metal, it will be perceived as having greater “value” than in a culture where such a conception is absent. However, the logics of valorization extend far beyond this.
Yet identity, it is evident, does not serve the unfolding of the ratio governing the discourse of utility, just as equality is ill-suited to serve as the handmaiden of exploitative logics, which instead require sharp divisions and clear dialectical, partitioning, and distinguishing significations. […] Once roles are assigned, the execution of the task can begin. Indeed, much of the history of human ecological discourse rests upon and moves forward from the claim to possess the power and knowledge to organize and arrange the meaning of the elements of a habitat in the best possible way, so that it appears more ordered, logical, regular, a faithful witness to and reflection of ‘natural laws.’ But this is insufficient to remove from the visible scene the fact that every human claim to logically re-arrange the logistics of the habitat is predicated on the suppression of the fundamental equivalence of the habitat itself, which, by contrast, does not require any ‘other ecology’—particularly one anthropocentrically organized and arranged—to continue its process.
([91], p. 209)
To assign a nominal identity to a discrete phenomenon means, first and foremost, to confer upon it a value recognized by a historically determined sociocultural system. This mechanism is part of the phenomenological theory developed by the anthropologist Ernesto de Martino [92], who builds upon the application of Husserl’s and Heidegger’s philosophies to his ethnographic and historical–religious investigations. The theory of valorization is not merely an application of usability concepts to sociocultural dynamics—although it constitutes a significant part of it—but also extends to how individuals shape and are shaped.
First, we should note that tradition is transmitted not only through language but that everything has a language, so to speak, and transmits cultural messages: the instruments we use, a dwelling, ways of working, the landscape, forms of social relations, gestures, attitudes and behaviors, customs and habits, fashions, ceremonial etiquettes, and so forth.
([92], p. 79)
The “value” is the fundamental functional element of language and organizes both biological and sociocultural systems, revealing an essential unity obscured by our cognitive systems. These systems tend to ignore causal connections and their participation in a complex relational network, favoring compartmentalized notions which are useful for organizing the “world” from an economic perspective. This term is understood not in an economistic sense but etymologically (οἰκονομία), as the management of a shared ecological space (οἶκος) through the organization of fundamental values (νέμω). In this sense, de Martino elucidates the following.
The economic is the horizon of the domestic, of at hand givenness, of a world of “things” and “names” related according to a communitarian project of possible or actual handiness. Something useful can be made of this world precisely because it is given, and its givenness, indeed, indicates its character of practicable resistance.
([93], p. 243)
Squarcini also acknowledges that the semiosis of division has, as its primary function, the control of the environment in a biosemiotic sense. Without the divisive organization enacted by functions of identity attribution—such as the binary n/r—it would be impossible to exercise control over a specific area within our ecological niche. This process is observed in all animals, for whom the process of valorization operates even before that of naming. A bee does not need to call a flower “flower” to know that “that thing there” possesses a particular value for her which is distinct from that of a stone. The process of nominal attribution performed by humans is, in some respects, a more complex development of this more primordial mechanism. However, it is not different in its functional principles; rather, it represents a further evolution, enabling environmental transformation with a view to broader and more effective dominion:
The act of division, therefore, is the fundamental operation of any ordering system, as evidenced by centuries of tireless reflection on the subject. For centuries, the semiosis of “division” has been scrutinized: it was already examined in the fragments of Parmenides’ work Peri Physeos, while the Aristotelian school’s catalog of partitions and pairs of opposites, titled Divisions, illustrates the utility of its effects. […]
The act of establishing distinctions and divisions is, therefore, at the foundation of every “form of order” (nomos […]), through which the undivided potentiality of reality is subordinated to specific practical interests and particular economic purposes. While humans find it useful to divide and partition the totality of reality, it is not difficult to observe that this operation is rooted in a fundamental contradiction, a visceral conflict of interests: just as it happens between object and subject, humans are both servants and masters of themselves, both slaves and lords of the world.
([91], pp. 211, 212)
This allows us to close the cycle initially opened with the analysis of the group of suttas from SN 1.60 to 1.70, particularly concerning the theme of the relationship between language, perception, and “world”. Saussure recalls the semiosis of division in a famous metaphor found in the Cours: the metaphor of the indistinct nebula ([18], pp. 216–217). For Saussure, thought and perception are a continuum of indeterminate meaning. Determination is a divisive and semantic act directed by sociocultural facts, which intervene to “divide” and “segment” the originally continuous and thus “indistinct” nebula into a series of discrete and recognizable elements. This occurs both in the dimension of meaning (the separation into specific “concepts”) and in that of the signifier (which must separate and “distinguish” specific “sounds”). It should be noted that phonetic distinction is entirely arbitrary. Physically, what distinguishes two phones is not a naturalistic fact. The sound frequencies that characterize the phone [e] in comparison to the phone [o], or [o] compared to [u], do not represent a clear-cut fact. Our linguistic system distinguishes [o] and [u] as discrete phonetic entities by referencing ideal phonemes. However, if we were to measure the frequencies of the two, particularly when transitioning smoothly from the execution of [o] to that of [u] and vice versa, we would realize that the boundary between the two is entirely conventional.
Non seulement les deux domaines reliés par le fait linguistique sont confus et amorphes, mais le choix qui appelle telle tranche acoustique pour telle idée est parfaitement arbitraire. Si ce n’était pas le cas, la notion de valeur perdrait quelque chose de son caractère, puisqu’elle contiendrait un élément imposé du dehors, Mais en fait les valeurs restent entièrement relatives, et voilà pourquoi le lien de l’idée et du son est radicalement arbitraire.
([18], p. 217)
In conclusion, we have seen that early Buddhist thought possesses numerous points of contact with Saussurean semiology. This is probably partly attributable to the influence that Indian thought had on Saussure, who was not only a scholar of Indo-European studies but also an attentive reader of Indian philosophical issues, as clearly demonstrated by his notes ([87], pp. 215–231). Beyond the question of influence, however, the comparability may also be attributed to a subsequent convergence in the reflections of both philosophical systems, which arrived at similar conclusions regarding the relationship between processes of perception, the organization of cognitions, and the system of language.
The theory I have proposed in this paper focuses particularly on interpreting the n/r dichotomy in early Buddhism in light of the divisive semiosis hypothesized by Squarcini, which allows for the connection of psycho-ecological theories on environmental perception [94,95] and the organization of sociocultural systems to processes of sign determination and the attribution of historically determined values (de Martino’s valorizzazione) to certain concepts. On this issue, the Pāli canon has offered significant insights, and it is therefore desirable that future studies on the problem of language and perception take these fundamental contributions into account, as they may open unexplored pathways through comparative studies.
One final crucial aspect of this incessant duality discussed by Saussure is the strongly relational nature of the elements within the linguistic–cognitive system, and their consequent possession of a “value”; that is, their being endowed with a certain identity or function solely and exclusively within the reciprocal relational framework that binds them (aut simul stabunt aut simul cadent). This appears quite evident in phonological, semantic, and morphological systems, and so forth. We know that an element within a given system has value only in relation to the other elements to which it stands in opposition and which contribute to defining its identity, and thus its functions. The vowel [i] is not [u], and in a system where both vowels hold a distinctive function, their phonological property is precisely determined by their having distinct identities in opposition to one another. The same holds for lexemes, and there is no need here to provide examples.
Lorsqu’on dit « signe », en s’imaginant très faussement que cela pourra être ensuite séparé à volonté de « signification » et que cela ne désigne que la « partie matérielle », on pourrait s’instruire rien qu’en considérant que le signe a une limite matérielle, comme sa loi absolue, et que déjà cette limite est en elle-même « un signe », une porteuse de signification. Il est donc entièrement illusoire d’opposer à aucun instant le signe à la signification. Ce sont deux formes du même concept de l’esprit, vu que la signification n’existerait pas sans un signe, et qu’elle n’est que l’expérience à rebours du signe, comme on ne peut pas découper une feuille de papier sans entamer l’envers et l’endroit de ce papier, du même coup de ciseaux.
([19], p. 96)
What is even more intriguing, however, is how this system applies, for Saussure, to the very nucleus of the semiotic system itself: in his writings, the linguistic sign is characterized as a relational entity composed of two specific elements, which together constitute what he defines as associative σῆμα (sème associatif). What Saussure seeks to demonstrate is that a given element of the associative σῆμα is, in itself, “empty”; that is, devoid of any inherent meaning. In isolation, separated from its fundamental relational nature and thus from its connection to another element within the associative σῆμα, it is nothing but a κένωμα ([19], pp. 93–94).
Saussure’s use of this term is of immense importance: his neologism (kénôme in French), based on the Greek term κένωμα, directly stems from its meaning of “emptiness”, which is why he defines a relational element of the associative σῆμα as a κένωμα, a vacuity, something that in itself is void. In his schema, Saussure represents a κένωμα in a manner similar to this: ⋂; that is, as a cavity. His aim is to offer a visual representation of his semiological concept. A given sign, defined as σῆμα, emerges from the intersection of two κένωμα; that is, two voids, which, through their relational intersection, form a fullness: Saussure brings two cavities closer together: ⊃⊂ until they intersect in a symbol that produces a “fullness” at the point of intersection between the two voids, like this: Philosophies 10 00031 i002 which produces the effect of a “full” interaction (relation) between two voids: “Vous pouvez seulement constater le kénôme ⋂ et le sème associatif Philosophies 10 00031 i002 ” ([19], p. 93).
This idea, as I have mentioned, is of immense importance because it serves as the fundamental clue as to how Saussure conceived of the very foundation of language as a relational force, whose constitutive elements hold value only within their relationships and cannot exist in isolation, since in isolation, they are void. The choice of the term κένωμα to describe this nature of an isolated semantic element is, in my view, not a casual one: it is a clear reference to the Buddhist philosophy of emptiness (suñña), whose foundation precisely describes the same principle: “Buddhism initially conceived of non-identity (anattā) and subsequently emptiness (suññatā). However, asserting that an entity is empty does not imply that it is nothing. The concept of emptiness is aimed solely at explaining the absence of independence, its inherent conditionality, and co-conditionality” ([96], p. 10).
The choice is not only conceptually akin to Buddhist thought but also appears to be deliberately considered from a terminological perspective. The term suñña (Sanskrit śūnya) is also etymologically related to the Greek κένωμα. Both mean “empty”, yet semantically, they derive from a term indicating a cavity—see, for example, Greek κύαρ and κοῖλος ([97], pp. 730–731), as well as Latin cavus ([98], pp. 101–102), all terms which, like Sanskrit śūnya, sūna, śūcī, and śūra ([99], p. 650), can be traced back to the Indo-European root *ḱówH- ([100], p. 592).

Funding

This research received no external funding.

Data Availability Statement

Data is contained within the article. The original contributions presented in this study are included in the article. Further inquiries can be directed to the corresponding author.

Conflicts of Interest

The author declares no conflicts of interest.

Abbreviations

ṚVgveda, Rajwade, V. K., Abhyankar, V. S., Sontakke, N. S. et al. (1965) (eds.), Ṛgveda-Samhitā with the Commentary of Sāyaṇācārya, vol. 1, Mandal 1 (Poona: N. S. Sontakke for the Vaidic SamshodhanMandal).
SnpSuttanipāta, Andersen, Dines, and Smith, Helmer (1913) (eds.), Sutta-Nipāta (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
DhpDhammapada, Ānandajoti Bhikkhu (2020), A Comparatve Edition of the Dhammapada.with Parallels from Sanskritised Prakrit Edited Together with a Study of the Dhammapada Collection (4th edn., Colombo: University of Peredeniya).
ItiItivuttaka, Kashyap, Bhikkhu (1959) (ed.), The Khuddakapāṭha-Dhammapada-Udāna-Itivuttaka-Suttanipāta (Bihar: Pāli Publication Board). Other reference edition: Mahāsaṅgīti Tipiṭaka Buddhavasse 2500.
DNDīghanikāya, Davids, T. W. Rhys, and Carpenter, J. Estlin (1890–1911) (eds.), The Dīgha Nikāya (London: Henry Frowde for the Pali Text Society).
MNMajjhimanikāya, Trenckner, Vilhelm, and Chalmers, Robert (1888–1925), TheMajjhima-nikāya (Pali Text Society Text Series, 60; London: Published for the Pali Text Society, by H. Frowde).
SNSaṃyuttanikāya, Feer, Léon (1884–1904) (ed.), Saṃyutta-nikāya, 6 vols (London:Henry Frowde for the Pali Text Society).
ANAṅguttaranikāya, Morris, Richard, Hardy, E., Hunt, Mabel, and Davids, C. A. F. Rhys (1885–1910) (eds.), The Aṅguttara-Nikâya, v, 6 vols (London: Pali Text Society).

Notes

1
This study adopts a comparative and textual approach, integrating linguistic (mainly from Saussure’s theory), cognitive, and philosophical perspectives. By analyzing key terms and concepts from early Buddhist texts, I trace their implications for cognition and perception. Furthermore, I compare these Buddhist insights with structuralist linguistic theories of the arbitrary nature of signs. The study relies primarily on textual evidence from the Pāli Canon, interpreting these texts within their historical and philosophical contexts.
2
According to Atlani-Voisin, “on ne peut qu’être étonné de la place qu’y occupent le sanskrit et la philosophie de la Parole en Inde et cela dans une réflexion apparemment éloignée du Cours de Linguistique Générale, mais aussi, ce qui est plus surprenant, loin de toute problématique indo-européenne” ([17], p. 79).
3
In this paper, the term “theory” is not used in the strictest sense of a formally systematized doctrine, as found in later scholastic developments such as the Abhidhamma. Rather, it is employed to denote a structured set of ideas and classifications that are clearly recognizable as part of the same considerations, and that reflect an underlying conceptual framework. While it is true that the Buddha’s teachings were adapted to his audience, the organization of knowledge in the suttas—especially regarding language and perception—demonstrates a level of internal coherence that can be analyzed philosophically. The classifications found in the Pāli Canon, though intended primarily as pedagogical tools for monks, also reveal a systematic reflection on the nature of linguistic conventions and cognitive processes, making it reasonable to approach them as an implicit “theory” in a functional sense. Early Buddhist texts frequently engage in critical reflections on perception, naming, and conceptualization, which bear significant theoretical implications. Consequently, while the term “theory” is not meant to imply a rigid doctrinal system, its use here aligns with the structured analytical approach found in the suttas.
4
The conventional nature of names and language in general is perfectly acknowledged by the Buddha, who often employs the term samaññā to convey this arbitrary nature of identities, names, and concepts. The act of designation is considered dangerous, as it leads to opinions and conflicts. Nonetheless, the Buddha has the ability to use terms, labels, and designations without being misled by them: “these are the worldly designations, terminologies, means of communication and conventions, which the Realized One uses to communicate, without getting stuck on them” (imā kho… lokasamaññā lokaniruttiyo lokavohārā lokapaññattiyo, yāhi tathāgato voharati aparāmasaṃ, DN 9). Another example is found in Snp 3.9, where it is said that one’s name and family are “formulated” as “mere convention in the world”, or “mere worldly conventions”; that is, a “product of common agreement, devised for each individual” (samaññā hesā lokasmiṃ, nāmagottaṃ pakappitaṃ; sammuccā samudāgataṃ, tattha tattha pakappitaṃ). Interestingly, this passage uses the term sammuccā, meaning “common agreement”, “conventional designation”, “arbitrariness”. This sutta affirms that identities are mere names that an act of common agreement “assigns” to each individual. The term pakappita indicates something “imagined”, “fabricated”, “designed”. Identity is thus an act of cognitive construction, “devised”, “concocted” (these are all possible meanings of the term pakappita) only to be “assigned” to the individuals. Another aspect of the conventionality of designation (samaññā) is its historical development. Identities do not remain stable and unchanged. In historical linguistics, this fact is known as the diachronic evolution of the sign. ([18], p. 163), ([19], p. 209) For example, “there was a time, o mendicants, when this Mount Vepulla was known as Pācīnavaṃsa”. To convey this change in name designation, the text uses the word samaññā: bhūtapubbaṃ, bhikkhave, imassa vepullassa pabbatassa “pācīnavaṃso’tveva samaññā udapādi (SN 15.20). This sutta highlights the impermanent nature of everything. Like the name of things, any phenomenon is subject to change or transformation, for every phenomenal condition is impermanent (evaṃ aniccā, bhikkhave, saṅkhārā). A similar discourse can be found in MN 116. Nonetheless, this does not suggest that phenomena are isolate, divided. On the contrary, their division is merely perceptive: any phenomenon is actually part of the same continuum. It is because of the designations, which assign distinct identities, that we perceive them as isolated. This is true also for divisions among humans: “in single human bodies you cannot find such distinctions. Distinctions among humans are only a matter of designation, convention” (paccattañca sarīresu, manussesvetaṃ na vijjati; vokārañca manussesu, samaññāya pavuccati, Snp 3.9).
5
Cf. MN 139: “Whatever mode of speech is known among these various peoples, you conform your speech, stubbornly insisting, “this is the only truth, all else is superfluous”. In this way, you insist on commonly used terms, overestimating designations. And how can you not insist on popular language, overestimating designations? When among different peoples you see that the same thing is perceived as “pāti”, “patta”, “vitta”, “sarāva’ “dhāropa”, “poṇa”, “pisīlava’” (iti yathā yathā naṃ tesu tesu janapadesu sañjānanti tathā tathā thāmasā parāmāsā abhinivissa voharati: “idameva saccaṃ, moghamaññan’ti. evaṃ kho, bhikkhave, janapadaniruttiyā ca abhiniveso hoti samaññāya ca atisāro. kathañca, bhikkhave, janapadaniruttiyā ca anabhiniveso hoti samaññāya ca anatisāro? idha, bhikkhave, tadevekaccesu janapadesu “pātī’ti sañjānanti”, “pattan’ti sañjānanti”, “vittan’ti sañjānanti”, “sarāvan’ti sañjānanti”, “dhāropan’ti sañjānanti”, “poṇan’ti sañjānanti”, “pisīlavan’ti sañjānanti”).
6
Moreover, the relationship between voice–word and light is not something present solely in the Ṛgveda, where it is explicitly expressed, but is also partly implicit in the etymology of the term ṛc-, connected to prayer, which can be traced back to the root h1erkw-, whose primary meaning is indeed “to pray” (cf. Old Armenian erg, “sing”; Hittite ārku-zi, “to sing”; Tocharian B yarke, “honor, reverence”) but also “to shine” or “to sound bright” (cf. Old Irish erc, “sky, heaven”). This curious connection is also present in other Indo-European languages: Greek φωνή (“sound”) is, in fact, related to φῶς (“light”), as both can be traced back to the reconstructed Indo-European root bheh2-, which thus bears both the meaning of “to speak” and “to shine” (cf. Greek φαίνω, “to cause to appear”; φάσις, “appearance”; φάντα, “shining”; Latin fātus and Greek φατός, “spoken”; Sanskrit bhāṣā, “speech”, “language”; Vedic bhanati, “to sound”, but also bhāna, “appearance”). It remains unclear whether bheh2- is a homophonic archetype of two distinct terms or whether both meanings were indeed considered semantically contiguous and thus traced back to the same archetype.
7
Remarkably similar conceptions regarding the performative potency of language have also been preserved in later Buddhist traditions. For instance, the borān meditative techniques studied by Kate Crosby place a strong focus on language and the correct execution of phonemes ([29], p. 117). Furthermore, the meditative exercises seem to be heavily inspired by grammatical principles, demonstrating a correlation between language and contemplative practice, as shown in the example of substitution, a meditative exercise inspired by the grammatical principle of deletion (lopa) ([29], p. 123). In this exercise, a specific “sign” (nimitta) is visualized in the process of substituting a cognitive factor (cetasika) that the meditator wants to purify: “The use of substitution in the representation of cetasika by nimitta or letter symbols might draw on a certain similarity between substitute and substituted” ([29], p. 125). Another important theme is the issue of language itself. In these traditions, Pāli becomes central as the language of the Buddha, and thus a sacred language: “The use of letter syllables in borān practice only uses Pali language and this reflects an understanding of the Pali language as potent in a way that is different from ordinary language. All language is potent in that it has the power to convey meaning” ([29], p. 126). Finally, the use of sacred syllables and formulas, recited as mantras and evoked during the contemplative exercise, is integral part of the borān practice but it is an aspect possibly of much greater antiquity. The importance that language has for Pāli Buddhism is exemplified in this line from the grammar of Kaccāyana: “[The Buddha thus proclaimed,] “Meaning (attha) is perceived (saññāto) through sounds (akkhara). The Meaning of all (sabba) language (vacanāṃ) is perceived only (eva) through sounds. When there is an error (vipatti) in the phonic sounds, the meaning is confused (dunnayatā). Therefore (tasmā), the phonetic skill (kosalla) is helpful (bahū-pakāraṃ) in [understanding] the teachings of the suttas (suttantesu)”” (attho akkharasaññāto. sabbavacanāṃattho akkhareh’eva saññāyate. akkharavipattiyaṃhi atthassa dunnayatā hoti; tasmā akkharakosallaṃbahūpakāraṃsuttantesu) ([29], p. 252).
8
vastreva bhadrā sukṛtā vasūyū rathaṃ na dhīraḥ svapā atakṣam.
9
tesaṃ pahānā ajjhattameva cittaṃ santiṭṭhati sannisīdati ekodi hoti samādhiyati; seyyathāpi, bhikkhave, dakkho palagaṇḍo vā palagaṇḍantevāsī vā sukhumāya āṇiyā oḷārikaṃ āṇiṃ abhinihaneyya abhinīhareyya abhinivatteyya.
10
dakkho bhamakāro vā bhamakārantevāsī vā dīghaṃ vā añchanto “dīghaṃ añchāmī’ti pajānāti, rassaṃ vā añchanto “rassaṃ añchāmī’ti pajānāti; evameva kho… bhikkhu dīghaṃ vā assasanto “dīghaṃ assasāmī’ti pajānāti, dīghaṃ vā passasanto “dīghaṃ passasāmī’ti pajānāti, rassaṃ vā assasanto “rassaṃ assasāmī’ti pajānāti, rassaṃ vā passasanto “rassaṃ passasāmī’ti pajānāti; “sabbakāyapaṭisaṃvedī assasissāmī’ti sikkhati, “sabbakāyapaṭisaṃvedī passasissāmī’ti sikkhati; “passambhayaṃ kāyasaṅkhāraṃ assasissāmī’ti sikkhati, “passambhayaṃ kāyasaṅkhāraṃ passasissāmī’ti sikkhati.
11
This is also the founding principle of the faculty of language: “la langue est un système dont tous les termes sont solidaires et où la valeur de l’un ne résulte que de la présence simultanée des autres” ([18], p. 219). In other words, “la partie conceptuelle de la valeur est constituée uniquement par des rapports et des différences avec les autres termes de la langue”, but this holds true also for the physical aspect, as “on peut en dire autant de sa partie matérielle” ([18], p. 223). Language is thus a differential system, where the relational aspects are based on the opposition of the values of its constituents: “dans la langue il n’y a que des différences” ([18], p. 226).
12
An example of this circularity can be found in MN 38: cakkhuñca paṭicca rūpe ca uppajjati viññāṇaṃ, cakkhuviññāṇantveva saṅkhyaṃ gacchati… evameva kho… yaṃ yadeva paccayaṃ paṭicca uppajjati viññāṇaṃ, tena teneva saṅkhyaṃ gacchati. This is attributed to the very conception that Buddhists have of consciousness, whereby it is specific to the object of reference. Indeed, an autonomous and isolated consciousness that interacts freely with given “objects” cannot exist. Rather, it is the very relationship between the sense organ and the corresponding effector, established through “contact”, that enables the arising of consciousness. Consciousness is thus always and necessarily consciousness of something, as it is dependent on the relationship it has with the object of which it is conscious. As we read in MN 38, a fire of logs is called a “logs fire”, while a fire of twigs is called a “twig fire”, and so on. Similarly, consciousness is essentially a relational property; it is always and only consciousness-of something. For this reason, Buddhists distinguish at least six types of consciousness, one for each perceptual organ, and thus one for each specific relational modality of consciousness. This implies, at the most essential level, a specific relational consciousness for every rūpa. In fact, we could say that viññāṇa is always viññāṇa-of-something; that is, viññāṇa-of-rūpa, or more precisely, of a specific rūpa (cakkhuñca paṭicca rūpe ca uppajjati viññāṇaṃ, cakkhuviññāṇantveva saṅkhyaṃ gacchati). However, we also know that consciousness is the element that anticipates finding “forms” in the world, divides them a priori, and therefore does not engage with them in a purely immediate way. Rather, it is always mediated by its own expectations. From this perspective, consciousness is not, for Buddhists, a reliable mechanism in the least, as it cannot help but perceive “trees”, expecting to find them in forests or parks, recognizing them as it acts by preemptively dividing the formal continuum into distinct forms. This serves to render “discrete” something that otherwise would not be experientially accessible in the manner to which we are accustomed.
13
Cf. Bṛhadāraṇyaka Upaniṣad 1.4.7: “In the beginning, indeed, the world was undivided. It was divided by name and form, so it is said: this thing has this name and this form” (tad dhedhaṃ tarhy avyākṛtam āsīt; tan nāmarūpābhyām eva vyākriyatāsaunāmāyam idaṃrūpa iti; tad idam apy etarhi nāmarūpābhyām eva vyākriyate saunāmāyam idaṃrūpa iti). See also the nāmarūpa-vyākaraṇa conception in Vedantic philosophy. In the Chāndogya Upaniṣad 7.1.5, we find a similar conception to that encountered in SN 1.61. However, in this case, the extraordinary power of nomination is depicted as positive, for the knowledge of the real name of something guarantee incredible powers: “for those who worship the name as Brahman, they can do whatever they please within the limits of the name. “Sir, is there anything higher than name?” — Nārada asked” (sa yo nāma brahmetyupāste yāvannāmno gataṃ tatrāsya yathākāmacāro bhavati yo nāma brahmetyupāste’sti…). In this case, the positive conception related to language clearly derives from the Vedic tradition. As explained in 7.2.1, there is also something higher than name: speech, as speech is that which makes known the Vedas (vāgvāva nāmno bhūyasī vāgvā ṛgvedaṃ vijñāpayati yajurvedaṃ sāmavedamātharvaṇaṃ caturthamitihāsapurāṇaṃ pañcamaṃ vedānāṃ vedaṃ) and the Purāṇas; also, grammar, funeral rites, mathematics, the science of omens, the science of underground resources, logic, moral science, astrology, Vedic knowledge, and so on (pitryaṃrāśiṃ daivaṃ nidhiṃ vākovākyamekāyanaṃ devavidyāṃ brahmavidyāṃ bhūtavidyāṃ kṣatravidyāṃ sarpadevajanavidyāṃ…).
14
See also Snp 4.15: “one free from a sense of ownership in the whole name-and-form does not grieve for that which is not, he does not suffer for any loss in the world” (sabbaso nāmarūpasmiṃ, yassa natthi mamāyitaṃ; asatā ca na socati, sa ve loke na jīyati).
15
Any linguistic process, including the act of communication, takes place mostly in this “psychic” dimension: “Suppose qu’un concept donné déclenche dans le cerveau une image acoustique correspondante: c’est un phénomène entièrement psychique, suivi à son tour d’un procès physiologique: le cerveau transmet aux organes de la phonation une impulsion corrélative à l’image; puis les ondes sonores se propagent de la bouche de A à l’oreille de B: procès purement physique”([18], p. 76). However, we must not confuse this reading with a dualism between mentalism and physicalism. The two dimensions are strictly connected, as Saussure will specify in his writings, and when we speak of the linguistic sign, we do so as something that is equally between the two domains in its own way: “Il y a un premier domaine intérieur, psychique, où existe le signe autant que la signification, l’un indissolublement lié à l’autre; il y a un second, extérieur, où n’existe plus que le « signe », mais à cet instant le signe réduit à une succession d’ondes sonores ne mérite pour nous que le nom de figure vocale” ([19], p. 21).
16
See, for instance, concepts such as dvayadhamma, which is regarded as the foundational principle of the loka in Snp 4.12, or terms like dvayanissita (from dvayassa, “duality”) explained in SN 12.15 and 22.90 in similarly operational terms.
17
A mendicant “does not take pride in attributing a “this-is” to things” (lit. “he does not make a habit of the “thus-I-am’”: itihanti sīlesu akatthamāno, since sīla can be intended both as “ethical conduct” and as “behavior” or “habit”), even though “visions-opinions are not something to be easily overcame” (diṭṭhīnivesā na hi svātivattā).
18
“A master of knowledge does not follow any conceit due to views or thoughts, for he does not identify with these things” (na vedagū diṭṭhiyāyako na mutiyā, sa mānameti na hi tammayo so).
19
A good mendicant would eliminate “the idea ‘I am a thinker’, which is the root of every concept of identity due to proliferation” (mūlaṃ papañcasaṅkhāya, mantā asmīti sabbamuparundhe). In MN 32, it is said that “a mendicant is master of their cognition and is not mastered by that cognition” (bhikkhu cittaṃ vasaṃ vatteti, no ca bhikkhu cittassa vasena vattati).
20
Therefore, according to MN 9, we could also build a specific rūpa set as follows: rūpa = {āpodhātu, tejodhātu, vāyodhātu, pathavīdhātu}, see also MN 28.
21
The text then provides another fundamental piece of information, relating consciousness to wisdom (paññā): “Wisdom and consciousness are two interwoven, inseparable things, and you will never be able to completely separate them in order to describe the differences between the two, since you understand what you know and know what you understand” (paññā yañca viññāṇaṃ—ime dhammā saṃsaṭṭhā, no visaṃsaṭṭhā; na ca labbhā imesaṃ dhammānaṃ vinibbhujitvā vinibbhujitvā nānākaraṇaṃ paññāpetuṃ… yaṃ… pajānāti taṃ vijānāti, yaṃ vijānāti taṃ pajānāti). We thus see that even wisdom, a fundamental objective of contemplative practice, is something that can be described by a specific verb: pajānāti, constructed, as in the case of viññāṇa/vijānāti, from the same root as the term with which it is associated. The verb pajānāti pertains to direct knowing, clear understanding, deep and unmediated apprehension. This passage is crucial because the text tells us that the fundamental nature of consciousness leads to the acquisition of paññā, which we know to be a central goal of Buddhist contemplative practice. In other words, the Buddha’s philosophy requires an understanding of the fundamental nature of consciousness, which in turn leads to the attainment of paññā, a state fundamentally inseparable from consciousness.
22
Another term used to refer to volitional aspects of thoughts is saṅkappavitakkā, composed of saṅkappa (“intention”, “volition”) and vitakka (“thought”). We find it In AN 9.14, when the disciple Samiddhi is asked: “On what basis do thoughts arise in a person?” (kimārammaṇā purisassa saṅkappavitakkā uppajjanti). The answer is nāmarūpārammaṇā, “through name-form”. This further demonstrates how the n/r binomial is directly responsible for volition and proliferation of thoughts.
23
To be precise, I do not consider the n/r binomial to be the authentic divisive semiosis; rather, I regard n/r as a fundamental semiosis that coordinates two distinct semiotic aspects: that of a divisive semiosis and that of an associative semiosis, both of which are integral to the dynamics between consciousness and recognition. However, addressing this issue necessitates engaging with Peirce’s discourse, which I intend to develop in a subsequent article following this study. For the sake of convenience, we will therefore limit our discussion to divisive semiosis as a component of n/r, which is the claim I aim to make. Nevertheless, it should be kept in mind that n/r semiosis encompasses much more than merely its divisive aspect.

References

  1. Bronkhorst, J. Language and Reality: On An Episode in Indian Thought; BRILL: Leiden, The Netherlands, 2011. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  2. Lysenko, V. The Buddhist Philosophy of Language in India: An Overview. In Buddhism and Linguistics; Herat, M., Ed.; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Switzerland, 2018; pp. 19–33. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  3. Waldron, W. Yogācāra Buddhist views on the causal relation between language, cognition and the evolution of worlds. In Origins of Religion, Cognition and Culture; Geertz, A., Ed.; Routledge: London, UK, 2014; Chapter 14; pp. 285–300. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  4. Polak, G. Language, Conscious Experience and the Self in Early Buddhism A Cross-cultural Interdisciplinary Study. J. Oxf. Cent. Buddh. Stud. 2018, 14, 37–76. [Google Scholar]
  5. Blomberg, J.; Żywiczyński, P. Language and Its Limits: Meaning, Reference and the Ineffable in Buddhist Philosophy. Topoi 2022, 41, 483–496. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  6. Tzohar, R. A Yogacara Buddhist Theory of Metaphor; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
  7. Genjun, S. Linguistic Approach to Buddhist Thought; Motilal Banarsidass: Delhi, India, 1986. [Google Scholar]
  8. Herat, M. (Ed.) Buddhism and Linguistics; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Switzerland, 2018. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  9. Westerhoff, J. Nāgārjuna and the Philosophy of Language. J. Indian Philos. 2019, 47, 779–793. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  10. Westerhoff, J. Some remarks on a problem in Madhyamaka philosophy of language. Ratio 2018, 31, 415–423. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  11. Rahlwes, C. Nāgārjuna’s Negation. J. Indian Philos. 2022, 50, 307–344. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  12. Mills, E. Skepticism and Religious Practice in Sextus and Nāgārjuna. In Ethics Without Self, Dharma Without Atman: Western and Buddhist Philosophical Traditions in Dialogue; Davis, G., Ed.; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2018; pp. 91–106. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  13. Westerhoff, J. Nāgārjuna’s Madhyamaka: A Philosophical Introduction; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
  14. Jones, R. Dialetheism, Paradox, and Nāgārjuna’s Way of Thinking. Comp. Philos. 2018, 9, 41–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  15. Jones, R.H. On What is Real in Nāgārjuna’s “Middle Way”. Comp. Philos. 2020, 11, 5. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  16. Westerhoff, J. The Madhyamaka Concept of Svabhāva: Ontological and Cognitive Aspects. Asian Philos. 2007, 17, 17–45. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  17. Atlani-Voisin, F. Le don de l’Inde. In L’Herne—Ferdinand de Saussure; Éditions de l’Herne: Paris, France, 2003; pp. 79–93. [Google Scholar]
  18. de Saussure, F. Cours de Linguistique Générale; Payot & Rivages: Paris, France, 2016. [Google Scholar]
  19. de Saussure, F. Écrits de linguistique Générale; Gallimard: Paris, France, 2002. [Google Scholar]
  20. Divino, F. In This World or the Next: Investigation Over the “End of the World” in Contemplative Practice Through the Pāli Canon. Ann. Sez. Orient. 2023, 83, 99–129. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  21. Hashimoto, T. The Concept of Loka in Early Buddhism (IV). J. Indian Buddh. Stud. (Indogaku Bukkyogaku Kenkyu) 1985, 33, 861–855. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  22. Hamilton, S. The “External World”: Its Status and Relevance in the Pali Nikāyas. Religion 1999, 29, 73–90. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  23. Katz, N. Does the “Cessation of the World” Entail the Cessation of Emotions? Buddh. Stud. Rev. 1980, 4, 53–65. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  24. Friedlander, P.G. The Body And The World In Buddhism. In Medicine, Religion, and the Body; Coleman, E.B., White, K., Eds.; BRILL: Leiden, The Netherlands, 2010; Chapter 3; pp. 51–67. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  25. Divino, F.; Di Lenardo, A. The World and the Desert: A Comparative Perspective on the “Apocalypse” between Buddhism and Christianity. Buddh.-Christ. Stud. 2023, 43, 141–162. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  26. Miller, J. The Vedas: Harmony, Meditation and Fulfilment; Rider & Company: London, UK, 1974. [Google Scholar]
  27. Squarcini, F. Tradens, Traditum, Recipiens: Introductory Remarks on the Semiotics, Pragmatics and Politics of Tradition. In Boundaries, Dynamics and Construction of Traditions in South Asia; Anthem Press: London, UK, 2011; pp. 11–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  28. Gonda, J. The Vision of Vedic Poets; De Gruyter Mouton: The Hague, The Netherlands, 1963. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  29. Crosby, K. Esoteric Theravada: The Story of the Forgotten Meditation Tradition of Southeast Asia; Shambhala Publications: Boulder, CO, USA, 2020. [Google Scholar]
  30. Campanile, E. Ricerche di Cultura Poetica Indoeuropea; Giardini Editori: Pisa, Italy, 1977. [Google Scholar]
  31. Severino, E. Beyond Language; Bloomsbury: London, UK; New York, NY, USA; Dublin, Ireland, 2024. [Google Scholar]
  32. Jurewicz, J. The Metaphor of Journey in Early Indian Thought. In Journeys and Travellers in Indian Literature and Art; Stasik, D., Trynkowska, A., Eds.; Elipsa Dom Wydawniczy: Kraków, Poland, 2018; pp. 15–33. [Google Scholar]
  33. Divino, F. Dualism and Psychosemantics: Holography and Pansematism in Early Buddhist Philosophy. Comp. Philos. 2023, 14, 4. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  34. Janet, P.; Craparo, G.; van der Hart, O. Catalepsy, Memory, and Suggestion in Psychological Automatism; Routledge: London, UK, 2021. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  35. Fedi, L. Automatisme et volonté dans la thèse de Pierre Janet. Psychiatr. Sci. Hum. Neurosci. 2007, 5, 36–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  36. Bacopoulos-Viau, A. Automatism, Surrealism and the making of French psychopathology: The case of Pierre Janet. Hist. Psychiatry 2012, 23, 259–276. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  37. Kihlstrom, J.F. Meditation and Deautomatization. In Encyclopedia of Religious Psychology and Behavior; Springer Nature: Cham, Switzerland, 2024; pp. 1–11. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  38. Chattopadhyay, M. Contemplation: Its Cultivation and Culmination Through the Buddhist Glasses. Front. Psychol. 2022, 12, 800281. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  39. Antonova, E.; Chadwick, P.; Kumari, V. Correction: More Meditation, Less Habituation? The Effect of Mindfulness Practice on the Acoustic Startle Reflex. PLoS ONE 2015, 10, e0133099. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  40. Augustyn, P. Uexküll, Peirce, and Other Affinities Between Biosemiotics and Biolinguistics. Biosemiotics 2009, 2, 1–17. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  41. Campion, Y. L’Umweltraum de Jakob von Uexküll. Le signe, l’espace, le temps et les philosophes. Cah. François Viète 2020, 3, 155–181. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  42. von Uexküll, J. A Foray into the Worlds of Animals and Humans; University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, MN, USA; London, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
  43. Lin, Q. How to Contemplate “Internally” and “Externally” in the Satipaṭṭhāna Meditation: A Philological Investigation. J. Int. Assoc. Buddh. Stud. 2019, 41, 315–360. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  44. Del Toso, K. The Function of Saññā in the Perceptual Process according to the Suttapiṭaka: An Appraisal. Philos. East West 2015, 65, 690–716. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  45. Attwood, J. Defining Vedanā: Through the Looking Glass. Contemp. Buddhism 2018, 19, 31–46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  46. Shulman, E. Rethinking the Buddha: Early Buddhist Philosophy as Meditative Perception; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
  47. Gibson, J.J. The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception; Psychology Press: New York, NY, USA, 2014. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  48. Brier, S. Biosemiotics. In Encyclopedia of Language & Linguistics; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2006; pp. 31–40. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  49. Alter, J. Biosemiotics and Religion: Theoretical Perspectives on Language, Society and the Supernatural. Theory Cult. Soc. 2022, 39, 101–121. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  50. Rama, T. Biosemiotics at the bridge between Eco-Devo and representational theories of mind. Riv. Ital. Filos. Linguaggio 2021, 15, 59–92. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  51. Monier-Williams, M. A Dictionary English and Sanskrit; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1899. [Google Scholar]
  52. Harvey, P. The Selfless Mind: Personality, Consciousness and Nirvana in Early Buddhism; Routledge: London, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  53. Metzner, R. The Buddhist Six-Worlds Model of Consciousness and Reality. J. Transpers. Psychol. 1996, 28, 155–166. [Google Scholar]
  54. Laukkonen, R.E.; Sacchet, M.D.; Barendregt, H.; Devaney, K.J.; Chowdhury, A.; Slagter, H.A. Cessations of consciousness in meditation: Advancing a scientific understanding of nirodha samāpatti. In Progress in Brain Research; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2023; Volume 280, Chapter 4; pp. 61–87. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  55. Lettner, A.T. Semiotic Roots and Buddhist Routes in Phenomenology and Intercultural Philosophy: A Peircean Study of Abhidharma Buddhist Theories of Consciousness and Perception. In Roots, Routes and a New Awakening; Springer: Singapore, 2021; pp. 47–74. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  56. Olivelle, P. Village vs. Wilderness: Ascetic Ideals and the Hindu World. In Ascetics and Brahmins: Studies in Ideologies and Institutions (Kykéion 6); Firenze University Press: Florence, Italy, 2006; Volume 1, Chapter 3. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  57. Wiltshire, M.G. Ascetic Figures Before and in Early Buddhism; DE GRUYTER: Berlin, Germany, 1990. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  58. Varenne, J. Agni’s role in the Ṛgvedic cosmogonic Myth. Ann. Bhandarkar Orient. Res. Inst. 1977, 58/59, 375–386. [Google Scholar]
  59. Shende, N.J. Agni in the Brāhmaṇas of the Ṛgveda. Ann. Bhandarkar Orient. Res. Inst. 1965, 46, 1–28. [Google Scholar]
  60. Izawa, A. The Myth of Agni’s Flight and Search for the Clay for the Ukhā. J. Indian Buddh. Stud. (Indogaku Bukkyogaku Kenkyu) 2017, 65, 1047–1053. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  61. Brown, W.N. Agni, Sun, Sacrifice, and Vāc: A Sacerdotal Ode by Dīrghatamas (Rig Veda 1.164). J. Am. Orient. Soc. 1968, 88, 199. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  62. Magoun, H.W. Apāṁ Napāt in the Rig-Veda. J. Am. Orient. Soc. 1898, 19, 137. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  63. Brown, W.N. The Creation Myth of the Rig Veda. J. Am. Orient. Soc. 1942, 62, 85. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  64. Brown, W.N. Theories of Creation in the Rig Veda. J. Am. Orient. Soc. 1965, 85, 23–34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  65. Divino, F. What Dawned First: Early Buddhist Philosophy on the Problem of Phenomenon and Origin in a Comparative Perspective. Philosophies 2024, 9, 135. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  66. Ginevra, R. Loki’s chains, Agni’s yoke, Prometheus Bound, and the Old English Boethius. Indogermanische Forschungen 2023, 128, 203–252. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  67. Ronzitti, R. L’età dell’oro sotto Vrtra e la formula indoeuropea ‘terra inarata’. Atti Sodal. Glottol. Milan. 2016, 8–9, 205–217. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  68. Kull, K. On semiosis, Umwelt, and semiosphere. Semiotica 1998, 120, 299–310. [Google Scholar]
  69. Pelc, J. Semiosis and semiosics vs. semiotics. Semiotica 2000, 128, 425–434. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  70. Kruse, F. Nature and Semiosis. Trans. Charles S Peirce Soc. 1990, 26, 211–224. [Google Scholar]
  71. Barbieri, M. Three Types of Semiosis. Biosemiotics 2009, 2, 19–30. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  72. Queiroz, J.; El-Hani, C.N. Semiosis as an Emergent Process. Trans. Charles S Peirce Soc. 2006, 42, 78–116. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  73. Violi, P. Beyond the body: Towards a full embodied semiosis. In Sociocultural Situatedness; de Gruyter: Mouton, France, 2008; pp. 53–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  74. Saito, A. The Meaning of Satkāyadṛṣṭi. Bull. Int. Inst. Buddh. Stud. 2022, 5, 1–12. [Google Scholar]
  75. Giustarini, G. A Note on Saḷāyatanas in Pāli Nikāyas. Ann. Dell’università Degli Studi Napoli 2005, 65, 153–178. [Google Scholar]
  76. D’Amato, M. The semiotics of signlessness: A Buddhist doctrine of signs. Semiotica 2003, 2003, 185–207. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  77. Squarcini, F. La cimosa e il ‘nichilista’. Fra ontologia, evacuazione e neutralizzazione dei segni figurali in Nāgārjuna. Consonanze 2020, 11, 69–86. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  78. Chakravarti, U. The Social Dimensions of Early Buddhism; Munshiram Manoharlal: New Delhi, India, 1996. [Google Scholar]
  79. Karunadasa, Y. Early Buddhist Teachings. The Middle Position on Theory and Practice; Wisdom Publications: Somerville, MA, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
  80. Bailey, G.; Mabbett, I. The Sociology of Early Buddhism; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2003. [Google Scholar]
  81. Gokhale, P.P. Classical Buddhism, Neo-Buddhism and the Question of Caste; Routledge: Delhi, India, 2020. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  82. Squarcini, F. Tradition, Veda and Law: Studies on South Asian Classical Intellectual Traditions; Società Editrice Fiorentina: Florence, Italy, 2008. [Google Scholar]
  83. Krishan, Y. Buddhism and the Caste System. J. Int. Assoc. Buddh. Stud. 1986, 9, 7183. [Google Scholar]
  84. Ellis, G. Early Buddhism and Caste. Rocz. Orient./Yearb. Orient. Stud. 2019, LXXII, 55–71. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  85. Husserl, E. Ideen zu Einer Reinen Phänomenologie und Phänomenologischen Philosophie—Erstes Buch (Gesammelte Werke Band III/1); Martinus Nijhoff: Den Haag, The Netherlands, 1976; Volume 1–3 Auflage. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  86. Small, E.S. Semiotic Referentiality: Saussure’s Sign and the Sanskrit Nama-Rupa. Am. J. Semiot. 1987, 5, 447–459. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  87. Parret, H. Les manuscrits saussuriens de Harvard. Cah. Ferdinand Saussure 1993, 47, 179–234. [Google Scholar]
  88. De Giovanni, L. Husserl on Intentionality and Attention: From the Logical Investigations to Genetic Phenomenology. Phänomenologische Forschungen 2018, 2, 81–98. [Google Scholar]
  89. Cruse, D.A. Prototype theory and lexical semantics. Meanings and Prototypes (RLE Linguistics B: Grammar). In Cognitive Linguistics: Basic Readings; Geeraerts, D., Ed.; de Gruyter: Mouton, France, 2006; pp. 392–412. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  90. Geeraerts, D. Prototypes, stereotypes, and semantic norms. In Cognitive Sociolinguistics; Kristiansen, G., Dirven, R., Eds.; de Gruyter: Mouton, France, 2008; pp. 21–40. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  91. Squarcini, F. Le colombe e gli avvoltoi Sull’economia politica delle ‘ecologie religiose’ del passato, in India e non solo. Ann. Ca’ Foscari. Ser. Orient. 2018, 54, 205–238. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  92. de Martino, E. The End of the World: Cultural Apocalypse and Transcendence; University of Chicago Press: London, UK, 2023. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  93. Divino, F. Reaching the End of the World: An Anthropological Reading of Early Buddhist Medicine and Ascetic Practices. Religions 2023, 14, 249. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  94. Favareau, D.; Kull, K. On Biosemiotics and Its Possible Relevance to Linguistics. In Biosemiotic Perspectives on Language and Linguistics; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2015; pp. 13–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  95. Velmezova, E.; Kull, K.; Cowley, S.J. (Eds.) Biosemiotic Perspectives on Language and Linguistics; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Switzerland, 2015; Volume 13. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  96. Stella, A.; Divino, F. The Metaphysical Turn in the History of Thought: Anaximander and Buddhist Philosophy. Philosophies 2023, 8, 99. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  97. Beekes, R. Etymological Dictionary of Greek (2 Vols.); BRILL: Leiden, The Netherlands, 2010. [Google Scholar]
  98. De Vaan, M. Etymological Dictionary of Latin and the Other Italic Languages—Leiden Indo-European Etymological Dictionary; BRILL: Leiden, The Netherlands, 2008. [Google Scholar]
  99. Mayrhofer, M. Etymologisches Wörterbuch des Altindoarischen; Carl Winter Universitätsverlag: Heidelberg, Germany, 1996; Volume 2. [Google Scholar]
  100. Pokorny, J. Indogermanisches etymologisches Wörterbuch; Francke Verlag: Bern, Switzerland; München, Germany, 1959; Volume 3. [Google Scholar]
Figure 1. The present schema is an adaptation of the model of the functional circle (Funktionskreis) developed by Uexküll ([42], p. 49). In biosemiotics, the experience of the world results from a complex interaction between the individual and the environment. The environment exists in a special relationship with the beings inhabiting it, who conform to the environment and, in turn, contribute to shaping it by modifying it.
Figure 1. The present schema is an adaptation of the model of the functional circle (Funktionskreis) developed by Uexküll ([42], p. 49). In biosemiotics, the experience of the world results from a complex interaction between the individual and the environment. The environment exists in a special relationship with the beings inhabiting it, who conform to the environment and, in turn, contribute to shaping it by modifying it.
Philosophies 10 00031 g001
Figure 2. Representation of the five aggregates as a functional circuit. This is a very general and hypothetical model describing the functioning of the five aggregates.
Figure 2. Representation of the five aggregates as a functional circuit. This is a very general and hypothetical model describing the functioning of the five aggregates.
Philosophies 10 00031 g002
Figure 3. Example of the process of segmentation (determination) of distinct nāma-rūpas starting from the “indistinct nebula” of which Saussure spoke during his lectures.
Figure 3. Example of the process of segmentation (determination) of distinct nāma-rūpas starting from the “indistinct nebula” of which Saussure spoke during his lectures.
Philosophies 10 00031 g003
Table 1. Comparison of the content of the first five suttas of the series.
Table 1. Comparison of the content of the first five suttas of the series.
SN 1.61SN 1.62SN 1.63SN 1.64SN 1.65
Name (nāma)Cognition (citta)Craving (taṇhā)Fetter (saṃyojana)Bonds (bandhana)
Pleasure (nandī)
It oppresses everything (sabbaṃ addhabhavi)It conducts the world (nīyati loko)It fetters the world (saṃyojano loko)It binds the world (sambandhano loko)
It has nothing bigger than it (bhiyyo na vijjati)It drags the world around (loko… parikassati)It conducts the world through thought (loko… vitakkassa vicāraṇaṃ)
It is the one thing that has everything under its sway (ekadhammassa sabbeva vasamanvagu)When craving is given up, nibbāna is realized (taṇhāya vippahānena, nibbānaṃ iti vuccati)When craving is given up, all bonds are severed (taṇhāya vippahānena, sabbaṃ chindati bandhanaṃ)
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Divino, F. Language and Consciousness in Early Buddhist Thought: On the Early Reflections on the Theme of Language and the Perception of Reality in the Pāli Canon. Philosophies 2025, 10, 31. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10020031

AMA Style

Divino F. Language and Consciousness in Early Buddhist Thought: On the Early Reflections on the Theme of Language and the Perception of Reality in the Pāli Canon. Philosophies. 2025; 10(2):31. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10020031

Chicago/Turabian Style

Divino, Federico. 2025. "Language and Consciousness in Early Buddhist Thought: On the Early Reflections on the Theme of Language and the Perception of Reality in the Pāli Canon" Philosophies 10, no. 2: 31. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10020031

APA Style

Divino, F. (2025). Language and Consciousness in Early Buddhist Thought: On the Early Reflections on the Theme of Language and the Perception of Reality in the Pāli Canon. Philosophies, 10(2), 31. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10020031

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop