Next Article in Journal
The Effectiveness of Dance Interventions on Health-Related Outcomes in Perimenopausal, Menopausal, and Postmenopausal Women: A Systematic Review and Meta-Analysis
Previous Article in Journal
The Role of Direct-Acting Antivirals in Enhancing Quality of Life Among Individuals with Chronic Hepatitis C
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Review

Ethical and Psychosocial Issues Associated with Genetic Testing for Hereditary Tumor Predisposition Syndromes

1
Department of Medical Genetics, Medical University Varna, 9000 Varna, Bulgaria
2
Laboratory of Medical Genetics, University Hospital “Sveta Marina”, 1 Hristo Smirnensky Str., 9000 Varna, Bulgaria
3
Department of Oncology, Medical University Varna, 9000 Varna, Bulgaria
*
Author to whom correspondence should be addressed.
Healthcare 2025, 13(8), 880; https://doi.org/10.3390/healthcare13080880
Submission received: 11 March 2025 / Revised: 9 April 2025 / Accepted: 10 April 2025 / Published: 11 April 2025

Abstract

:
Hereditary tumor predisposition syndromes (HTPSs) significantly increase the risk of developing various cancers, often at earlier ages than seen in the general population. The development and application of next-generation sequencing (NGS) has revolutionized the identification of individuals with HTPS, facilitating early diagnosis, personalized risk assessment, and tailored preventive strategies. However, the widespread implementation of genetic testing for HTPS presents complex ethical and psychosocial issues. This paper examines key ethical considerations surrounding genetic testing for HTPS, including the following: the distinct nature of genetic information and its implications for families; the challenges of informed consent amidst evolving genetic knowledge and direct-to-consumer testing; the complexities of predictive and presymptomatic testing, particularly in minors; and the implications of incidental findings. It further explores the critical issue of genetic discrimination, particularly concerning insurance, employment, and social stigmatization. This paper highlights the importance of balancing individual rights, such as autonomy and privacy, with familial responsibilities and the potential benefits of early detection and intervention. It also underscores the need for robust legal frameworks, comprehensive genetic counseling, and ongoing public education to address the ethical and psychosocial challenges associated with genetic testing for HTPS, with the ultimate goal of maximizing the benefits of genomic medicine while minimizing potential harms.

1. Introduction

Hereditary tumor predisposition syndromes (HTPSs), also widely known as hereditary cancer syndromes, are characterized by an increased risk of developing specific cancers, often at a younger age than typically seen in the general population. Routinely applied genomic diagnostic methods, such as next-generation sequencing (NGS), have created opportunities for early diagnosis, risk assessment, and crucially, personalized medicine approaches. Identifying the specific genetic basis of cancer risk allows for tailored treatment selection (e.g., targeted therapies like PARP inhibitors for individuals with BRCA mutations), personalized prevention strategies (such as decisions about prophylactic surgery), and individualized surveillance plans (determining the type and frequency of screening). The integration of these genetic tests into clinical practice raises complex ethical and psychosocial issues. As Van Rensselaer Potter [1], who introduced the term “bioethics” in 1970, noted, rapid scientific advances can potentially outpace due consideration of their moral and ethical implications. This observation remains profoundly relevant today. While ethical guidelines in research and medical practice have been implemented to provide adequate and clear ethical standards, care must be taken to ensure that these guidelines do not unduly hinder the development and responsible application of beneficial technologies [2]. Balancing innovation with ethical considerations is paramount in realizing the full potential of genomic medicine for individuals and families affected by HTPS.

2. Specificity of Genetic Information and Balancing Responsibility and Individual Rights

The unique nature of genetic information compared to other medical data raises ethical questions, particularly due to its “shared” nature among family members [3]. Although initially restrictive, normative documents, such as position statements from the American Society of Human Genetics (ASHG) [4] and the World Health Organization [5], have increasingly supported the disclosure of genetic information without patient consent in limited circumstances; however, the conditions for such disclosure often remain poorly defined [6]. Genetic risk information for medically actionable conditions offers potential benefits for early detection and prevention but can also complicate family relationships, for instance, by creating feelings of guilt in carriers or blame towards the side of the family the mutation originated from or through the unwanted disclosure of risk status to relatives who preferred not to know. Cascade genetic testing, which involves systematically offering genetic testing to biological relatives of an individual found to have a specific pathogenic variant to identify others who may also be at increased risk, is crucial for maximizing the preventative potential within families. Uptake in at-risk families is often below 50% [7], particularly in conditions like Hereditary Breast and Ovarian Cancer (HBOC) syndrome involving BRCA1/2 mutations or Lynch syndrome, where structured cascade screening programs aim to identify affected relatives. Relatives may decline testing due to various reasons, including anxiety about the result, fear of genetic discrimination, potential impact on insurance, denial, or simply asserting their right not to know. Furthermore, the burden of contacting relatives, traditionally falling on the initially tested individual (the proband) although sometimes facilitated by healthcare professionals with patient consent, presents a significant barrier to the dissemination of risk information [8]. Still, the duty of care to inform relatives about potential genetic risks must be carefully balanced against an individual’s rights to privacy and autonomy in making decisions about their own health information.

3. Uncertainty in Genetic Testing

Genetic testing, particularly for HTPS, holds immense promise for proactive healthcare. However, a significant challenge lies in the inherent uncertainty associated with interpreting the results. For instance, discovering a pathogenic variant in a high-risk gene (e.g., BRCA1/2, PALB2) provides information about the likelihood of developing specific cancers or elevated risk compared to the general population [9]. However, for many moderate- or low-risk genes, testing often cannot definitively predict disease severity or the age of onset [10]. This limitation stems from complex factors such as incomplete penetrance, variable expressivity, modifier genes, and environmental and lifestyle factors influencing disease development and progression. While polygenic risk scores (PRSs), which aggregate the small effects of many common genetic variants (polymorphisms) across the genome to estimate an individual’s overall genetic susceptibility to a specific disease, are increasingly incorporated into risk prediction models alongside traditional risk factors, their clinical application is still evolving. Unlike tests for high-penetrance mutations in single genes (like BRCA1) that confer a large, relatively well-defined risk, PRSs assess a more generalized, probabilistic risk based on common variations. Consequently, their ability to accurately predict outcomes like breast cancer subtypes on a population-wide scale and their readiness for widespread clinical use still face challenges [11], although research is rapidly advancing.
This inherent lack of a precise genotype–phenotype correlation can significantly complicate the decision-making process for both patients and healthcare providers, particularly when considering preventive measures. For example, a woman with a pathogenic variant in BRCA1, BRCA2, or PALB2 faces a difficult choice regarding prophylactic mastectomy or oophorectomy. While these interventions can significantly reduce cancer risk, they can involve major surgery with potential physical and psychological consequences [12].
Moreover, our understanding of the human genome remains incomplete. Many genes and genetic variants currently lack established correlations with specific diseases. Most individuals receive results that are clinically uninformative, meaning either no pathogenic or likely pathogenic variants are identified in the genes tested, or only variants of uncertain significance (VUS) are found, for which the impact on disease risk is unknown. Notably, a study by Rao et al. [13] found no significant psychosocial harm among adults receiving negative genomic screening results for adult-onset hereditary conditions and only about 10% planned health-related behavior changes. In addition, ongoing research may reclassify variants of uncertain significance in the future, highlighting the dynamic and evolving nature of genetic knowledge and its impact on the interpretation of test results [14]. Professional societies like the American College of Medical Genetics and Genomics (ACMG) and the Clinical Genome Resource (ClinGen) provide guidelines on the interpretation and reporting of VUSs, acknowledging their limited clinical utility while emphasizing the need for periodic re-evaluation [15,16].
Therefore, pre-test and post-test genetic counseling plays a vital role. Counselors help individuals understand the limitations and uncertainties inherent in genetic testing, provide crucial support in navigating complex decisions, and assist individuals in weighing the potential benefits and risks considering their personal values and preferences [17,18].

4. Informed Consent in the Context of Oncogenetic Testing

Oncogenetic testing, with its profound implications for individuals and their families, necessitates a rigorous approach to informed consent. This process is further complicated by the sensitive nature of genetic information and its potential for broad use, including research. The General Data Protection Regulation (GDPR) (Regulation (EU) 2016/679), implemented by the European Union and effective since 2018 across the European Economic Area (EEA), provides a crucial framework for the protection of personal data, applying specifically to any information relating to an identified or identifiable natural person. It designates genetic data and health data as “special categories of personal data” under Article 9, affording them a higher level of protection.
In the context of oncogenetics, informed consent is not merely a formality but a dynamic process. The dialog should cover the purpose, procedures, potential benefits, and risks of the specific oncogenetic test, as well as the implications of the results for the individual and their family. It should also address issues of data storage, access, and potential future use. To facilitate participation, especially for geographically dispersed individuals, parts or all of the informed consent process can occur remotely (e.g., telephone, video conferencing, web-based methods). While web-based platforms offer feasibility for dynamic consent, their full utility requires further investigation [19].
Furthermore, to advance knowledge in oncogenetics and improve patient care, samples, genomic data, and health information collected during routine clinical care are often stored and used for research purposes. It is a common misunderstanding of current European data protection law that processing personal data is prohibited when consent does not have a lawful basis [20,21]. Article 9 (2) (j) of the GDPR allows exceptions to the prohibition of processing genetic data for such research, stating that processing is permissible when it is “necessary for archiving purposes in the public interest, scientific or historical research purposes, or statistical purposes”, subject to appropriate safeguards. In addition, Article 9 (4) allows Member States to introduce further conditions or limitations regarding the processing of genetic data. This has led to some variability in national regulations across the EU. For instance, some countries have explored using genomic data for research without explicit consent under certain conditions, potentially granting access to international bodies [22].
This debate connects directly to different models of consent for secondary data use. An opt-in system requires individuals to explicitly agree (give active consent) before their data can be used for a specific secondary purpose, such as research. Conversely, an opt-out system assumes consent for secondary use unless the individual actively refuses or objects (expresses dissent). The approval by European Parliamentarians of a proposal favoring an opt-in system for the secondary use of health data, including genetic data, in the proposed European Health Data Space (EHDS), provoked dissatisfaction from the European Society of Human Genetics (ESHG). This highlights the ongoing debate surrounding the balance between individual rights and control over data (emphasized by opt-in systems) and the potential benefits of facilitating broader data use in research (potentially enabled more easily by opt-out models allowed under specific GDPR provisions like Article 9 (2) (j), provided safeguards are met) [23].

5. Unsolicited/Secondary Findings

The application of next-generation sequencing (NGS) technologies, which encompass various high-throughput methods allowing for the simultaneous sequencing of millions or billions of DNA fragments, has profoundly impacted medical genetics, offering the potential to identify genetic information related to conditions other than the primary indication for testing, known as unsolicited or secondary findings (SFs). Although unsolicited findings (sometimes defined as findings in genes related to the tested indication but not the primary target) and secondary findings (in genes unrelated to the tested indication) can be distinguished, the broader term SFs is often used. Therefore, clinical genetics centers need to establish clear protocols, in accordance with ethical committee decisions and relevant guidelines, offering patients opt-in or opt-out choices regarding receiving SFs besides the initial diagnostic result [24]. The chance of identifying SFs in a gene panel depends on the scope of the panel and the specific genes included.
Van der Schoot et al. [25] found that SFs predisposing to medically actionable disorders affect a broader range of genes than those listed on the influential ACMG SF list, suggesting pre-defined lists may be too restrictive and that the evaluation of medical actionability may need to occur on a case-by-case basis. While the identification and disclosure of SFs depend on local policies, their study provides essential insights into the nature and odds of SFs in clinical exome sequencing (CES). CES specifically targets the sequencing of the exome—the protein-coding regions of the genome (approximately 1–2% of the total genome)—and is primarily used clinically for diagnosing individuals with suspected rare monogenic disorders or complex phenotypes unexplained by other testing or in cancer genomics to identify somatic and germline variants relevant to diagnosis, prognosis, or treatment. The American College of Medical Genetics and Genomics (ACMG) published 2013 recommendations for reporting SFs in clinical exome and genome sequencing, initially recommending the mandatory reporting of pathogenic variants in a predefined list of genes. The most recent recommendations (ACMG SF v3.2, 2023) expanded the list of genes associated with medically actionable conditions, including variants linked to numerous cancer predispositions [26].
Key points of contention surrounding SF reporting include potential infringement upon patient autonomy (if reporting is mandatory regardless of preference), the balance between potential benefits (early detection/prevention) and harms (anxiety, cost, and overtreatment) of disclosure, and the practical challenges of implementation in diverse clinical settings. Moreover, the legal framework governing the disclosure of genetic information to relatives varies considerably between jurisdictions, adding another layer of complexity.

6. Predictive and Presymptomatic Testing in Hereditary Cancer Syndromes

In the realm of hereditary cancer syndromes, genetic testing plays a crucial role in identifying at-risk individuals before the onset of symptoms. This testing generally falls into two categories: presymptomatic and predictive. While both aim to identify currently healthy individuals at risk, they differ significantly in their implications. Presymptomatic testing is used when a specific genetic mutation is known to inevitably cause a disease if the individual lives long enough (assuming complete penetrance); a positive result essentially confirms future disease development. Predictive testing, on the other hand, applies when a genetic variant is associated with an increased risk of developing a disease but does not guarantee its manifestation (due to factors like incomplete penetrance or variable expressivity). Predictive testing, therefore, deals with probabilities rather than certainties.
Regardless of whether testing is presymptomatic or predictive, the primary purpose is to maximize medical benefits. This includes enabling early detection through increased surveillance and screening, facilitating preventative measures such as prophylactic surgery or chemoprevention, and informing personalized treatment plans. When successful prevention or treatment is not possible, the information gained can still be valuable for life planning, making informed reproductive decisions, and allowing individuals to prepare for potential psychological and emotional challenges. However, it is crucial to acknowledge the potential downsides of such testing, even in healthy individuals. The psychological impact can be substantial, ranging from anxiety and depression to disruptions in family dynamics. Ironically, individuals who test negative for a known familial mutation might experience ‘survivor’s guilt’ [27], a complex emotional response.
Therefore, pre-test and post-test genetic counseling is paramount, providing comprehensive and accurate information about the specific syndrome, the genes involved, the limitations of testing (including the possibility of uninformative results or VUS), the potential psychosocial ramifications, and available support resources [28,29].
The landscape of genetic testing is becoming more widely available within clinical genetic and mainstream medical services. The potential consequences, which vary depending on the type of test (diagnostic, screening, presymptomatic, or predictive), must be considered prior to testing, recognizing that the field is constantly evolving. While considerable skepticism existed regarding the clinical utility of some direct-to-consumer (DTC) genetic tests by 2010, leading to critical policy recommendations from the ESHG [30], the field remains dynamic. Interest in DTC testing persists alongside evolving regulatory measures and professional guidelines aimed at ensuring responsible application [6]. Therefore, genetic susceptibility testing for individuals with relevant family histories can be beneficial when the information can effectively guide prevention or treatment, aligning with the principle of beneficence.

7. Genetic Testing in Asymptomatic Minors

Genetic testing in asymptomatic minors presents unique ethical and clinical challenges, particularly within the context of HTPS. For the purposes of this discussion, minors are defined as individuals who have not attained the legal age of majority to provide informed consent for healthcare decisions independently. In the specific context of oncogenetics, predictive genetic testing of asymptomatic minors should generally only be considered after the identification of a known familial pathogenic variant and primarily when preventive measures or surveillance begin in childhood, offering clear medical benefit during minority.
The European Society of Human Genetics (ESHG) published influential recommendations for genetic testing in asymptomatic minors in 2009 [31]. These guidelines emphasize respecting the minor’s future autonomy and the right to an open future, often advocating for deferring testing unless immediate medical benefits during childhood exist. The field of genetics has since undergone substantial advancements, warranting critical reappraisal and updates to existing recommendations. This is particularly relevant given discussions around potentially incorporating genomic sequencing into newborn screening programs [32] or even prenatal testing for adult-onset conditions [33].
In addition, parents may face challenges in disclosing positive test results to their children due to concerns such as the child’s age, developmental appropriateness, and the emotional burden involved. Further research is needed to understand these communication dynamics and how best to support parental decision-making and communication regarding childhood genetic testing for predisposition syndromes [34].

8. Genetic Discrimination in the Context of Hereditary Cancer Syndromes

Genetic discrimination poses a significant ethical challenge in medical genetics, particularly concerning hereditary cancer syndromes. It raises profound ethical concerns regarding equity, privacy, and the potential for stigmatization based on genetic information.
Internationally, there has been a growing recognition of the need to protect individuals from genetic discrimination. A landmark example is the US Genetic Information Nondiscrimination Act (GINA) of 2008, which prohibits discrimination in health insurance and employment based on genetic information. The American Society of Human Genetics (ASHG) has consistently advocated for the robust enforcement of the GINA and the enactment of similar legislation globally [35]. However, despite such legislation, recent studies confirm ongoing challenges. For example, individuals with Neurofibromatosis type 1 (NF1) experience higher rates of unemployment and sickness absence [36], often due to the condition’s variable manifestations which can include the growth of benign and malignant tumors, chronic pain, orthopedic issues, cognitive challenges, and the need for frequent medical appointments or surgeries. Furthermore, evidence suggests continued experiences of genetic discrimination faced by individuals with various hereditary conditions, alongside a limited awareness of legal protections [37].
Concerns about the adequacy of existing legal frameworks in protecting the privacy and security of genetic data may also lead patients to seek testing outside traditional healthcare systems (e.g., paying out of pocket or using direct-to-consumer services). This can result in sensitive genetic information being held by private companies, potentially outside the purview of healthcare regulations and electronic health record systems.

9. Conclusions

Genetic testing for hereditary tumor predisposition syndromes (HTPSs) offers significant potential for early cancer detection, risk management, and personalized medicine. However, this powerful technology presents complex ethical and psychosocial challenges. Balancing individual rights (such as autonomy and privacy) with familial responsibilities is crucial, especially given the shared nature of genetic information. The inherent uncertainties of genetic testing, including incomplete penetrance, variable expressivity, and variants of uncertain significance, necessitate comprehensive pre-test and post-test genetic counseling. Incidental or secondary findings further complicate clinical management and patient decision-making.
While legal frameworks like the GDPR in Europe and the GINA in the US exist to protect genetic information and prevent discrimination, gaps and enforcement challenges remain, particularly regarding life insurance, long-term care insurance, and disability insurance in some jurisdictions, as well as potential social stigmatization. The rise in direct-to-consumer genetic testing also requires ongoing regulatory attention and adaptation.
Moving forward, robust legal protections against genetic discrimination, comprehensive public education about genetics and its implications, and specialized training for healthcare professionals involved in ordering or interpreting these tests are essential. A continued focus on psychosocial research investigating the experiences of individuals and families undergoing testing is also critical.
Realizing the full benefits of HTPS testing demands a commitment to ethical principles, ongoing multidisciplinary dialog, and proactive approaches to address evolving challenges. This will help ensure that individuals and families can benefit from the advances in genomic medicine while safeguarding their rights and well-being. Addressing these interconnected ethical, psychosocial, and practical considerations is therefore fundamental for the responsible integration of genomic technologies into current and future healthcare, ultimately shaping how we deliver equitable and effective personalized care in an era of genomic medicine.

Author Contributions

Conceptualization, M.H. and M.L.; methodology, E.D.; validation, M.S., D.Y. and M.L.; formal analysis, M.H.; investigation, M.H.; resources, M.H.; writing—original draft preparation, M.H.; writing—review and editing, M.L.; supervision, E.D. All authors have read and agreed to the published version of the manuscript.

Funding

This study is financed by European Union-NextGenerationEU through the National Recovery and Resilience Plan of the Republic of Bulgaria, project BG-RRP-2.004-0009-C02.

Institutional Review Board Statement

Not applicable.

Informed Consent Statement

Not applicable.

Data Availability Statement

No new data were created or analyzed in this study. Data sharing is not applicable to this article.

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

References

  1. Potter, V.R. Bioethics, the Science of Survival. Perspect. Biol. Med. 1970, 14, 127–153. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  2. Kendal, E. Ethical, Legal and Social Implications of Emerging Technology (ELSIET) Symposium. J. Bioeth. Inq. 2022, 19, 363–370. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  3. Kenny, J.; Burcher, S.; Kohut, K.; Eastman, N. Ethical Issues in Genetic Testing for Inherited Cancer Predisposition Syndromes: The Potentially Conflicting Interests of Patients and Their Relatives. Curr. Genet. Med. Rep. 2020, 8, 72–77. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  4. ASHG Statement. Professional disclosure of familial genetic information. The American Society of Human Genetics Social Issues Subcommittee on Familial Disclosure. Am. J. Hum. Genet. 1998, 62, 474–483. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  5. World Health Organization. Community Genetics Services: Report of a WHO Consultation on Community Genetics in Low- and Middle-Income Countries; World Health Organization: Geneva, Switzerland, 2011. [Google Scholar]
  6. Phillips, A.; Borry, P.; Van Hoyweghen, I.; Vears, D.F. Disclosure of genetic information to family members: A systematic review of normative documents. Genet. Med. 2021, 23, 2038–2046. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  7. Sarki, M.; Ming, C.; Aissaoui, S.; Bürki, N.; Caiata-Zufferey, M.; Erlanger, T.E.; Graffeo-Galbiati, R.; Heinimann, K.; Heinzelmann-Schwarz, V.; Monnerat, C.; et al. Intention to Inform Relatives, Rates of Cascade Testing, and Preference for Patient-Mediated Communication in Families Concerned with Hereditary Breast and Ovarian Cancer and Lynch Syndrome: The Swiss CASCADE Cohort. Cancers 2022, 14, 1636. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  8. Tiller, J.M.; Stott, A.; Finlay, K.; Boughtwood, T.; Madelli, E.O.; Horton, A.; Otlowski, M. Direct notification by health professionals of relatives at-risk of genetic conditions (with patient consent): Views of the Australian public. Eur. J. Hum. Genet. 2024, 32, 98–108. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  9. McDevitt, T.; Durkie, M.; Arnold, N.; Burghel, G.J.; Butler, S.; Claes, K.B.M.; Hume, S. EMQN best practice guidelines for genetic testing in hereditary breast and ovarian cancer. Eur. J. Hum. Genet. 2024, 32, 479–488. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  10. Graffeo, R.; Rana, H.Q.; Conforti, F.; Bonanni, B.; Cardoso, M.J.; Paluch-Shimon, S.; Garber, J.E. Moderate penetrance genes complicate genetic testing for breast cancer diagnosis: ATM, CHEK2, BARD1 and RAD51D. Breast 2022, 65, 32–40. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  11. Roberts, E.; Howell, S.; Evans, D.G. Polygenic risk scores and breast cancer risk prediction. Breast 2023, 67, 71–77. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  12. Luque Suárez, S.; Olivares Crespo, M.E.; Brenes Sánchez, J.M.; Herrera de la Muela, M. Immediate Psychological Implications of Risk-Reducing Mastectomies in Women with Increased Risk of Breast Cancer: A Comparative Study. Clin. Breast Cancer 2024, 24, 620–629. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  13. Rao, N.D.; King, K.M.; Kaganovsky, J.; Hassan, S.; Tsinajinne, D.; Fullerton, S.M.; Shirts, B.H. Risk perception and intended behavior change after uninformative genetic results for adult-onset hereditary conditions in unselected patients. Eur. J. Hum. Genet. 2024, 32, 77–82. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  14. Slavin, T.P.; Manjarrez, S.; Pritchard, C.C.; Gray, S.; Weitzel, J.N. The effects of genomic germline variant reclassification on clinical cancer care. Oncotarget 2019, 10, 417–423. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  15. Richards, S.; Aziz, N.; Bale, S.; Bick, D.; Das, S.; Gastier-Foster, J.; Rehm, H.L. Standards and guidelines for the interpretation of sequence variants: A joint consensus recommendation of the American College of Medical Genetics and Genomics and the Association for Molecular Pathology. Genet. Med. 2015, 17, 405–424. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  16. Steven Harrison, L.B.; On behalf of ACMG Interpreting Sequence Variants WG. Updating ACMG/AMP Guideline for Sequence Variant Interpretation 2021. Available online: https://www.clinicalgenome.org/site/assets/files/6887/acmg-amp_updated_guidelines_and_engaging_underrepresented_groups_in_clingen_main_session.pdf (accessed on 1 March 2025).
  17. Ciucă, A.; Moldovan, R.; Băban, A. Mapping psychosocial interventions in familial colorectal cancer: A rapid systematic review. BMC Cancer 2022, 22, 8. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  18. Schienda, J.; Stopfer, J. Cancer Genetic Counseling-Current Practice and Future Challenges. Cold Spring Harb. Perspect. Med. 2020, 10, a036541. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  19. Haas, M.A.; Madelli, E.O.; Brown, R.; Prictor, M.; Boughtwood, T. Evaluation of CTRL: A web application for dynamic consent and engagement with individuals involved in a cardiovascular genetic disorders cohort. Eur. J. Hum. Genet. 2024, 32, 61–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  20. Dove, E.S.; Chen, J. Should consent for data processing be privileged in health research? A comparative legal analysis. Int. Data Priv. Law 2020, 10, 117–131. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  21. Smit, J.-A.R.; Mostert, M.; van der Graaf, R.; Grobbee, D.E.; van Delden, J.J.M. Specific measures for data-intensive health research without consent: A systematic review of soft law instruments and academic literature. Eur. J. Hum. Genet. 2024, 32, 21–30. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  22. Johnson, S.B.; Slade, I.; Giubilini, A.; Graham, M. Rethinking the ethical principles of genomic medicine services. Eur. J. Hum. Genet. 2020, 28, 147–154. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  23. Opting-in to Data Sharing in the European Health Data Space Will Disadvantage Research on Personalised Medicine, Says ESHG. Available online: https://www.eshg.org/news/news-details?tx_news_pi1%5Baction%5D=detail&tx_news_pi1%5Bcontroller%5D=News&tx_news_pi1%5Bnews%5D=66&cHash=ef055b33ea95d43b17185ff76101996f (accessed on 1 March 2025).
  24. Matthijs, G.; Souche, E.; Alders, M.; Corveleyn, A.; Eck, S.; Feenstra, I.; Bauer, P. Guidelines for diagnostic next-generation sequencing. Eur. J. Hum. Genet. 2016, 24, 2–5. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  25. van der Schoot, V.; Haer-Wigman, L.; Feenstra, I.; Tammer, F.; Oerlemans, A.J.M.; van Koolwijk, M.P.A.; Yntema, H.G. Lessons learned from unsolicited findings in clinical exome sequencing of 16,482 individuals. Eur. J. Hum. Genet. 2022, 30, 170–177. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  26. Miller, D.T.; Lee, K.; Abul-Husn, N.S.; Amendola, L.M.; Brothers, K.; Chung, W.K.; Gollb, M.H. ACMG SF v3.2 list for reporting of secondary findings in clinical exome and genome sequencing: A policy statement of the American College of Medical Genetics and Genomics (ACMG). Genet. Med. 2023, 25, 100866. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  27. Hodgson, S.V.; Maher, E.R. A Practical Guide to Human Cancer Genetics, 3rd ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
  28. Vears, D.F.; McLean, A.; La Spina, C.; McInerney-Leo, A.; Education, E. Social Issues Committee of the Human Genetics Society of A. Human Genetics Society of Australasia Position Statement: Predictive and Presymptomatic Genetic Testing in Adults and Children. Twin Res. Hum. Genet. 2024, 27, 120–127. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  29. Vears, D.F.; Ayres, S.; Boyle, J.; Mansour, J.; Newson, A.J.; Education, E.; Newson, A.J. Human Genetics Society of Australasia Position Statement: Predictive and Presymptomatic Genetic Testing in Adults and Children. Twin Res. Hum. Genet. 2020, 23, 184–189. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  30. European Society of Human Genetics. Statement of the ESHG on direct-to-consumer genetic testing for health-related purposes. Eur. J. Hum. Genet. 2010, 18, 1271–1273. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  31. Borry, P.E.-K.G.; Cornel, M.C.; Clarke, A.; Dierickx, K. Public and Professional Policy Committee (PPPC) of the European Society of Human Genetics (ESHG). Genetic testing in asymptomatic minors: Recommendations of the European Society of Human Genetics. Eur. J. Hum. Genet. 2009, 17, 720–721. [Google Scholar]
  32. Knoppers, B.M.; Bonilha, A.E.; Laberge, A.-M.; Ahmed, A.; Newson, A.J. Genomic sequencing in newborn screening: Balancing consent with the right of the asymptomatic at-risk child to be found. Eur. J. Hum. Genet. 2025, 33, 182–188. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  33. Rosenblum, L.S.; Auger, S.M.; Zhu, H.; Zhou, Z.; Xin, W.; Reiner, J.; Leach, N.T. Prenatal Testing for Variants in Genes Associated with Hereditary Cancer Risk: Laboratory Experience and Considerations. J. Mol. Diagn. 2024, 26, 202–212. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  34. Rapoport, C.S.; Masser-Frye, D.; Mehta, S.; Choi, A.K.; Olfus, S.; Korhummel, M.; Kuo, D.J. Parent and patient knowledge and attitudes about cancer predisposition syndrome genetic testing in pediatric oncology: Understanding sociodemographic and parent-child differences. Cancer Rep. 2024, 7, e2119. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  35. Genetic Information Nondiscrimination Act of 2008. Available online: https://www.eeoc.gov/statutes/genetic-information-nondiscrimination-act-2008 (accessed on 1 March 2025).
  36. Kallionpää, R.A.; Johansson, E.; Böckerman, P.; Peltonen, J.; Peltonen, S. The contribution of morbidity and unemployment for the reduced labor market participation of individuals with neurofibromatosis 1 in Finland. Eur. J. Hum. Genet. 2024, 32, 83–90. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  37. Gopalakrishnan, R.; Sam, J.; Butkowsky, C.; Reble, E.; Clausen, M.; Rajeziesfahani, S.; Bombard, Y. “Should I Let Them Know I Have This?”: Multifaceted Genetic Discrimination and Limited Awareness of Legal Protections among Individuals with Hereditary Cancer Syndromes. Public Health Genom. 2024, 27, 240–254. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Hachmeriyan, M.; Levkova, M.; Yahya, D.; Stoyanova, M.; Dimitrova, E. Ethical and Psychosocial Issues Associated with Genetic Testing for Hereditary Tumor Predisposition Syndromes. Healthcare 2025, 13, 880. https://doi.org/10.3390/healthcare13080880

AMA Style

Hachmeriyan M, Levkova M, Yahya D, Stoyanova M, Dimitrova E. Ethical and Psychosocial Issues Associated with Genetic Testing for Hereditary Tumor Predisposition Syndromes. Healthcare. 2025; 13(8):880. https://doi.org/10.3390/healthcare13080880

Chicago/Turabian Style

Hachmeriyan, Mari, Mariya Levkova, Dinnar Yahya, Milena Stoyanova, and Eleonora Dimitrova. 2025. "Ethical and Psychosocial Issues Associated with Genetic Testing for Hereditary Tumor Predisposition Syndromes" Healthcare 13, no. 8: 880. https://doi.org/10.3390/healthcare13080880

APA Style

Hachmeriyan, M., Levkova, M., Yahya, D., Stoyanova, M., & Dimitrova, E. (2025). Ethical and Psychosocial Issues Associated with Genetic Testing for Hereditary Tumor Predisposition Syndromes. Healthcare, 13(8), 880. https://doi.org/10.3390/healthcare13080880

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop