Next Article in Journal
Non-Verbal Communication in Ancient Rome: Eyebrow Gestures
Next Article in Special Issue
The History of -eer in English: Suffix Competition or Symbiosis?
Previous Article in Journal
A Comparative Analysis of Declarative Sentences in the Spontaneous Speech of Two Puerto Rican Communities
Previous Article in Special Issue
Exploring Creativity and Extravagance: The Case of Double Suffixation in English
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

An Upper Take on Doubler-Uppers

by
Alexandra Bagasheva
Department of English and American Studies, Sofia University “St. Kliment Ohridski”, 1504 Sofia, Bulgaria
Languages 2024, 9(3), 91; https://doi.org/10.3390/languages9030091
Submission received: 15 December 2023 / Revised: 9 February 2024 / Accepted: 2 March 2024 / Published: 10 March 2024
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Word-Formation Processes in English)

Abstract

:
Against the background of comparatively insufficient, expressly dedicated studies on double particle verb person nominalisations, this paper offers a qualitative, cognitive-constructionist approach to the properties of doubler-upper nominalisations of particle verbs in English and a reappraisal of some of the available analyses thereof. On the assumption of the validity of the flexicon stance on the organisation of words in the human mind, and on the basis of a preliminary semantic analysis of 300 types of doubler-upper nouns extracted from two corpora and Urban Dictionary, it is claimed that there are no identifiable constraints on the possibility of double-er marking and no particular properties of particle verbs as bases to preclude double -er marking. A hypothesis is formulated that, despite their deviance, doubler-uppers strike the optimal balance between complexity and unity and appear to be the most natural and morphophonologically best-fitting pattern for particle verb -er nominalisation (at least in spoken discourse and the media).

1. Introduction

Doubler-upper nouns (Cappelle’s (2010) label) illustrate two of the “fundamental problems of derivational semantics”, as identified by Kotowski and Plag (2023, p. 2), ensuing from the nature of form-meaning mappings—“polysemy” and “form-meaning mismatches”. As one of the competitors in a quadruple-wide1 competition for the person nominalisation of multiword verbs in English, doubly -er marked de-particle verb2 nouns display polysemy in terms of possible readings, including agent (e.g., asker-outer), stimulus (e.g., calmer downer), entity (e.g., fixer-upper—with a potential patient reading as well, besides the agentive one), and event (e.g., cutter-offer, backer-outer), while the seemingly semantically empty doubling of the affix shows “form-meaning mismatches”.
Doubler-upper nouns raise uneasy questions with their mere identification—are they affixed phrasal compounds, reduplicative compounds, or affixed complex lexemes? They cannot be easily classified as phrasal compounds, such as do-it-yourselfer, since, according to the discussion in Bauer et al. (2013, pp. 509–17), suffixation on compound and phrasal bases occurs at the outer rightmost boundary (irrespective of whether precise differentiation can be established between a compound and a phrase), while, as the label iconically suggests, they display two instances of -er suffixation, one of which disrupts internal (phrasal) unity. Their affixed wordhood is not immediately or easily evident, even when Haspelmath’s (2023) newest definitions of word (as a text element and as a lexeme) are adopted. Multi-word expressions (MWEs) encompass compounds, complex verbs, and idioms (Schulte im Walde and Smolka 2020, p. iii) or “linguistic objects formed by two or more words that behave like a ‘unit’ by displaying formal and/or functional idiosyncratic properties with respect to free word combinations”, comprising “an extremely varied set of items (from idioms to collocations, from formulae to sayings)” (Masini 2019, p. 1). Subsuming doubler-uppers under MWEs resolves the issue of their participation as derivational bases in word formation processes, but leaves the problem with their double suffixal marking (where one of the instances of the suffix seems vacuous) open.
Atheoretically, we can use at least the following labels, each of which emphasises different properties of such nouns: reduplicative compound, agentively affixed multi-word verb (MWV), doubly affixed de-particle verb nouns, (constructional) template, and the product of non-semantic affix doubling, etc. The label ‘noun’ presupposes the following: it is a word with an identifiable part of speech membership, it allows pluralisation, and it can potentially perform the syntactic functions of nouns such as boy or stone. As nouns, doubler-uppers do not easily fit into the derivational ecosystem of English, as they are non-typical nominalisations (Lieber 2016), since coindexation with two separate bases of the same affix (if it is affixal reduplication) is hard to model. The multi-word verb itself has already been coindexically integrated into a single meaningful unit combining a verb and a particle, which can further be suffixally augmented, but typically with a single suffix.
The analysis offered below takes stock of these issues in relation to doubler-upper nouns and puts forward a cognitive-constructionist approach, which provides a few specific answers to some of the questions hovering around these nominalisations. The paper is structured as follows: Section 2 revises the nature of doubler-upper nouns, arguing against a reduplicative interpretation; in Section 3, a cognitivist-constructionist alternative is offered, and Section 4 concludes.

2. The Nature of Doubler-Uppers

2.1. A Preliminary Constructional View of Doubler-Uppers

Within constructionist analyses (e.g., Audring 2019; Booij 2016, 2017, 2019; Booij and Masini 2015; Goldberg 2006, 2019; Hilpert 2015, 2019a, 2019b; Hoffmann 2022; Mansfield 2021), the construction type is considered to be significant, and words, but not morphemes, are considered to be the smallest constructions in terms of complexity in construction morphology (Booij 2013, p. 256), while morphemes are recognised as constructions in construction grammar (Goldberg 2006, p. 5). At least the following construction types of a word in terms of complexity with distinct properties have been recognized, “where ‘M’ is a morpheme, “[_]w” is a constituent that meets wordhood criteria, and ‘+’ indicates one or more iterations of an element type.
[M+]w = (Minimal) Word
[[M+]w -M+]w = (Recursive) Word
[[M+]w [M+]w+]p = Phrase”
In view of these considerations, the bases of double-uppers are either recursive words or phrases further participating as recursive words in derivational processes by combining with morphemes. Irrespective of their recognition as words or multi-word semantically unified expressions, they participate in at least one morphological schema in the sense of Booij (2013), which is associated with the semantics of the ‘agent of the activity named by the unified concept of the base’.
Another set of properties of construction types captures the nature of the internal constituents in terms of fixedness and substantive specificity or variability, where a constructional idiom or an abstract schema is recognised as one in which at least one constituent is phonetically specified, e.g., “<[x]Vi er]Nj Languages 09 00091 i001 [Agent of SEMi]j>” (Booij 2016, p. 425). Even if we recognise the preservation of the mapping with the semantic part, for doubler-uppers, we need to adequately model the formal part that will encode the agent (or other extended) reading(s), either despite the double appearance of the suffix or supported by it.
In other words, doubler-uppers are not typical compounds for at least the following two considerations: (i) they are considered to arise either through reduplication or affixation (by no means coterminous or easily reconcilable processes in the derivational ecosystem of English); and (ii) their bases are not typical compounds (variability in ordering, which leads to internal interruptability, which individually and conjoinedly undermine wordhood). They cannot be considered as affixed phrasal compounds either, since, in phrasal compounding, any affixation would be at the outer rightmost border. The doubling of the affix seems not to be semantically motivated, i.e., they are not typical affixal products. Reduplication in English seems to be naturally associated with compounding (Benczes 2012), not with affixation, and is considered “not a major means of creating lexemes in English, but […] perhaps the most unusual one” (Crystal 2003, p. 130).
From a construction-analytical perspective, issues are raised relating to their identification as alternating schemas inherited from a single mother schema, as constructional idioms (with double -er substantively specified) or constructional templates.3 They could be identified as constructional templates in Hoffmann’s sense (2022, p. 14), but only if they are assumed to be recursively derived, and not if they are marked simultaneously (see the interpretation of great-great-grandfather in Hoffmann (2022, p. 14)), so they do not fit the criteria for a constructional template either. The term template in relation to affixal elements also raises other associations—a pattern of ordering without a hierarchical structure (Mithun 2016, pp. 149–50) and fixed slots for particular meanings. Any which way an analyst looks doubler-uppers seems to be the odd man out.

2.2. What Has Been Established about Doubler-Uppers

Both multi-word verbs and -er deverbal nominalisations in English have been extensively studied from various perspectives (e.g., Baeskow 2015; Bolinger 1971; Heyvaert 2010; Lieber 2004, 2016; Lieber and Andreou 2018; Ryder 1999, 2000). Their mutual products have not been commensurately studied, with a few full-length studies exclusively dedicated to the problems these pose for numerous widely shared assumptions (see Cappelle 2010; Chapman 2008; Denison 2008; Lensch 2018, 2022; McIntyre 2004; Walker 2009) about word formation.
The synchrony and diachrony of doubler-upper nouns reported in the literature can be generalised into the following:
  • General: They are still considered to be marked—either colloquial (Blevins 2006), humorous (Bauer et al. 2013), jokingly nonstandard (Quirk et al. 1985, p. 1539), extravagant (Lensch 2022), “popular, grotesque“ (Wentworth 1936), clumsy (Bauer 1983), intentional errors (Cappelle 2010), or “fairly natural kind of ‘error’” (McIntyre 2004). Supposedly, they are more widely spread in American English (including the written medium, see Lensch 2022), but certain types (roller-upper, washer-upper, roper-inner, and stopper-inner) are attested only in BNC, not in COCA (Bauer et al. 2013, p. 218).
  • Diachronic perspective
    (i)
    Chapman (2008) speculates on their historical development, suggesting that the picker-upper pattern may be a transitional stage on the way from picker-up to pick-upper.
    (ii)
    They are a borderline phenomenon, lying “on the chronological or conceptual borders of lexicalization or grammaticalization” (Ryder 2000, p. 292). The suffix -er itself is on the way to full grammaticalization, acquiring a clitic-like character in its ability to attach to “non-lexicalized phrases”4 (Ryder 2000, p. 292). Multiword verbs do not belong to the latter group as they are fully lexicalised, but they seem to occupy a middle ground in the path to grammaticalization between the prototypical deverbal -er nominalising suffix and the clitic-like, anaphoric-function-performing suffix -er.
    (iii)
    They are a transient fashion (Mencken 1945).
  • Synchronic perspective
    (i)
    They are a morphological phenomenon (which has to be recognised as a deviant one in the sense of Hathout and Namer (2014)). According to Lensch (2022, p. 76), they violate at least four principles of English morphology: the Righthand Head Rule, the monosuffix constraint, Aronoff’s (1976) Unitary Base Hypothesis, and the avoidance of formally (near-) identical and (near-) adjacent (non-coordinate) grammatical elements or structures. In her view, they are realised by affix reduplication, which is not characteristic of the ecosystem of English word formation (unlike the recognised role of reduplication in rhyming compounds of all types (Benczes 2012; Rastall 2004));
    (ii)
    They are a phonological phenomenon, or at least a phonologically motivated phenomenon—according to Walker (2009), they arise for euphonic causes; in the view of Denison (2008), they are rhythmic phenomena, associated with the specific rhythmic pattern of phrasal verbs. Doubler-uppers, in his view, are “a new rhythmic template, one in which the relative weights of verb stem and particle are respected as well as the need to have -er as final element of an agent noun (which is both a rhythmic and a formal matter)” (Denison 2008, pp. 212–13).
    (iii)
    They participate in a tripartite competition among patterns: V + P-er, V-er + P, and V-er + P-er, and the criteria for discriminating which one is chosen for a particular nominalisation remain obscure (Chapman 2008).
    (iv)
    They violate two principles or strong tendencies in English morphology: (1) the -er suffix has a tendency to attach to verbal bases, and (2) English derivational morphology is normally placed at the right-hand margin of the base (Chapman 2008, p. 279; Cappelle 2010, p. 360). We can add to this the general principle of the right-headedness of compounds in English.
    (v)
    They allow multiple -er attachments at the right outside boundary, e.g., washer-upperer, thus violating Bauer’s contention that “in English no suffix can be added to a base that already ends in the same suffix” (Bauer 1983, p. 92).
To these points, it might be relevant to add that doubler-uppers do not easily or conveniently fit into any of the four types of multiple exponence (ME) identified by Harris (2017). They look like Type 2, the alternating one “typically involving featurally identical non-adjacent affixes”, which is optional “or it may alternate with a simpler form, or it may be inconsistent within a paradigm” (Harris 2017, p. 54). Even though doubler-uppers conform to the formal side of Type 2 and are also lexically governed, they contradict the meaning side of Type 2 ME, since it “is probably always inflectional, including marking of number, case, possessives in the noun, and agreement markers in the verb” (ibid.), while -er doubling on multi-word verbs in English, at least for the time being, predominantly serves naming functions of agent, instrument, stimulus, entity, and event readings (though not place or inhabitant readings, otherwise characteristic of the suffix -er).
Even the recognition of the ubiquity of -er suffixation on all kinds of linear elements, including non-lexicalised phrases, as in in-the-parker, up-and-comer, and blue-chipper (Ryder 1999, p. 292) (where its function is interpreted as an anaphoric marker with generalised substantivizing meaning akin to one), does not solve or directly relate to the doubling issue. On the contrary, it makes it even more special in view of the fact that -er at the rightmost border progressively widens the scope of bases that easily tolerate it. Besides not solving the doubling issue, this invites the recognition of an internal border within an MWE, which, for certain purposes, is a unified linearisation (onomasiologically speaking, MWVs constitute a single naming unit), but for other purposes, displays an internal boundary, e.g., pronominal direct object movement with phrasal verbs (e.g., fix the house up vs. fix up the house and fixer upper with at least two possible readings—agent and entity).

2.3. Why Doubler-Uppers Are Not the Product of Reduplication

As early as the 1930s (Wentworth 1936), doubler-uppers were recognised as affixed compound nouns, which does not run contrary to the principles of English word formation, as many compounds in the language are of the complex type (see e.g., Bauer 2017; Hilpert 2015; Dirven and Verspoor 2004, etc.), i.e., both the processes of compounding and affixation are involved in their constitution—e.g., good-looking, blue-eyed, and hand-carved, etc. From this perspective, doubler-uppers deviate in terms of two-fold marking with the same affix. For Lensch (2018, p. 163), the explanation lies in the fact that “doubler-upper nouns constitute an additional systematic pattern to the classes of reduplicatives in English”. However, doubler-uppers cannot straightforwardly be explained as products of reduplication. They are far removed from both canonical and prototypical reduplication within “the unclear phenomenology of reduplication” (Stolz 2018, p. 201) cross-linguistically. Haugen (2015), in acknowledging the legitimacy of affixes as reduplicants under the Morphological Doubling Theory of reduplication (Inkelas and Zoll 2005), emphasises that “the question of whether or not affixes can be legitimate targets for reduplication” (Haugen 2015, p. 12) remains open, as well as the issues of which affixes can be reduplicants and why these specific affixes.
A reduplicative interpretation of doubler-uppers violates Hurch’s definition of reduplication as a morphological procedure “by which the inflectional and/or derivational formatives used to signal a specific category are directly derivable from the phonological/prosodic structure of the uninflected or underived simplex form” (Hurch 2005, p. 1). Furthermore, Lensch (2018, p. 160) claims that repetition “triggers a change in expressive or interpersonal meaning”, while, as a morphological procedure, reduplication “is accompanied by changes in descriptive meaning”. It also creates bracketing problems and presupposes an intermediary stage in the derivational process. If we are to assume that doubler-uppers result from the morphological procedure of reduplication, we need to assume one of the single-affixed alternatives as the base for reduplication and, thus, acknowledge at least two stages involved in the derivation of these complex nominals—affixation (for the single affix marking), followed by reduplication, e.g., ask out > asker out > asker outer. Again, the doubling remains an unjustified addition, since the target semantics is already present in the single-affixed form, while Booij (2010, p. 39) contends that “the doubled structure conveys a meaning that is not reducible to the meaning of its constituents” (Booij 2010, p. 39). The fact that doubler-uppers are competitors in a tripartite competition suggests that their meaning is reducible to that of any of the intermediary bases (see asker out above).
Lensch (2022, p. 96) explains this away as extravagance and creativity on the part of speakers and emphasises that the double marking has exclusively expressive functions and does not affect the descriptive meaning of the derived noun. In view of the principle of economy and the type frequency of doubler-uppers or the fact that “attestations of this template have become too numerous” (Lensch 2022, p. 90) and their passing “the threshold […] to the written medium” (Lensch 2022, p. 90), such an explanation falls thin. Furthermore, according to Denison (2008, p. 215) “[d]ouble -er does not seem explicable as emphatic reinforcement, as some kinds of linguistic doubling certainly are”. Even if we adopt the definition of discontinuous reduplication, “where other morphological material may appear between the reduplicant and the base” (Velupillai 2012, p. 101), which, according to Mattiola and Masini (2022, p. 274), is both non-canonical and non-prototypical, we still have not solved the issue with the functional justification and meaning-encoding problem of double -er marking. Adopting Good’s (2016) definition of template, Lensch (2022, p. 76) avoids ‘the reduplication as a morphological procedure’ issue by identifying doubler-uppers as templates, since “templates are more flexible than schemas in the Construction Grammar sense”. A reduplicative interpretation dissociates the three alternative nominalising patterns of particle verbs and precludes the possibility of a unified analysis capturing the properties of all competing alternatives and showcasing the common core. It runs counter to the ideas of constructionism and violates both inheritance relations (from a common, more abstract schema to more substantively specified variants) and sister relations (the complex relations between equally substantively specified schemas at the same level of abstraction). It leads to the conclusion that the single marking of the -er affix (no matter where exactly it is positioned—internally on the verb, or externally on the particle) results from a different process, i.e., affixation, while double marking results from reduplication. Reduplication, as a morphological procedure, requires the presence of the reduplicant in the base, which, as explained above for doubler-uppers, means that a vacuous element is added that is an exact phonological copy of an element from the source, but without any morpho-semantic contribution, which is questionable in view of at least two principles—the economy principle and the cognitivist principle that “all structures in language, ranging from morphemes, to words to syntactic patterns, are considered as inherently meaningful” (Lemmens 2015, p. 90).

3. Doubler-Uppers as Sister Allostructions

In other words, doubler-uppers remain a unique type of complex -er nominal, defined by Ryder (1999, p. 292) as “a noun with the nominalizing -er suffix whose base consists of more than one free morpheme”. They exemplify ““deviant word formation”, that is Word Formation (WF) departing from the canonical one-to-one correspondence between form and meaning, and thus moving away from morpho-semantic transparency” (Hathout and Namer 2014, p. 177). This deviance runs contrary to their optimality, paradoxically also defined in terms of the best morphophonological fit.
In Hathout and Namer’s classification of deviant morphology, doubler-uppers are simultaneously an instance of “derivational over-marking” and of “lexical over-marking”. From the point of view of derivational canonicity, the double (or in some cases multiple) marking of -er displays a mismatch between meaning and form correspondence in reference to the local base-derivative relations, while the fact that they participate in a tripartite competition between patterns with the same semantics makes them lexically deviant.
A fitting model to analyse the phenomenon is to conceive a family of constructions or sister-schemas that share a common core but display individual specificities. This may avoid the issue with the exact identification of the morphological process or procedure (reduplication, affixation, and compounding, etc.) of their constitution on the one hand, and on the other, emphasise the affinity among the three alternative patterns for nominalising particle verbs in English. To avoid looking at those as epiphenomenal patterns arising from different processes or involving individual schematic representations, an allostructional analysis is offered, with a focus on the complementary analytical utility of recognising both a shared mother schema and a series of sister schemas, which better illustrates the nature of the constructicon as a highly dynamic and exclusively relational network, matched by the dynamics of the flexicon in the mind.

3.1. Data

For both rhetorical and analytical purposes, this section starts with a long quotation from the crowd-sourced online Urban Dictionary (1999–2024). This may raise a few brows, but “UD captures what most traditional English dictionaries fall short of: recording ephemeral quotidian spoken language and representing popular views of meaning” (Cotter and Damaso 2007, p. i). In addition, Chapman (2008) expressed a desideratum for looking into corpora with a greater representation of colloquialisms for establishing a firmer grasp on doubler-uppers. The elaborate doubler-upper example in (1) demonstrates a complex naming unit with an embedded particle verb nominalisation:
(1)
Story interruptor one-upper adder-toer (UD) (2010)—21 positive votes—1 negative vote
A person that interrupts you mid-story. But then not only interrupts your story, they feel the need to one-up your story with an even better story of their own. And to top it off, they not only interrupt you in the first place, one-up you with their story, they then feel the need to add to your original story they interrupted.
I was in class the other day talking about how my dad went to Haiti to help the earthquake victims, and before I could even finish Frank interrupted me and said his dad not only flew to Haiti to help the victims, but that he also donated a million dollars to the relief act. He went on to say that his dad told him my dad was down there but wasn’t actually doing anything to help. That fucking Frank is such a story interruptor one-upper adder-toer!
Example (1) is an excellent exemplar to showcase that there is no identifiable linguistic factor that can determine the choice of agentive particle verb nominalisation in English (except genre specifications and degree of formality). It illustrates the convictions of cognitive and functional linguists “that virtually everything in language is motivated […] even if very little is strictly predictable” (Langacker 2008, p. 14; emphasis in the original). Both the verb and the preposition are affixed in adder-toer, contra Denison’s (2008, p. 224) claim “for a strong tendency of those particles/prepositions that occur more typically in phrasal verbs to be more typical of the picker-upper pattern and those that are more typical of prepositional verbs to be typical of the picker-up pattern.” It appears in the adjacency of another nominalisation of a (converted) particle verb, in which only the particle is affixed. The example is provided by a single speaker, which may be taken to suggest that entrenchment (for an elaboration of the role and nature of entrenchment in the dynamic language model adopted here, see Schmid (2020)) is item-specific or that disparate factors influence the positioning and number of affixes in MWVs’ (agentive) nominalisations. Both nominalisations have strictly agentive readings in the immediate context and participate in a single naming unit; neither denotes a purposeful or rather a habitual doer of an activity, which runs counter to Lensch’s (2018, p. 178) claim of “a tendency for doubler-upper nouns to denote volitional agents or instruments that are used purposefully and not by accident or chance” and have divergent marking, with one of the constituents with a single (particle-attached) -er affix and the other with double affixation.
This is not a typical example and is not used here to argue for the extravagant nature of doubler-uppers, just to alert the reader to the impossibility of predicting which of the three -er marking alternatives will be used for a particular particle verb (agentive) nominalisation. Each of them forms a different pocket of productivity in the local network of -er nominalisations, with the understanding that X-er Y-er is the most colloquial, even though “it just feels right” (Whitman 2010).
The data presented in Table 1 below were extracted from the NOW (2023) and GloWbE (2023) corpora and UD, with a view of their potential for conducting, in the future, an analysis across varieties, registers, and genres. The data sources were chosen based on the possibility for more colloquial data to be collected across genres and varieties (although, at this stage, the differences among varieties and genres have not been analysed). GloWbE encompasses different varieties of English and amounts to 1.9 billion words. The NOW corpus, the largest corpus at 18.6 billion words, was chosen for its contemporaneity and the data it represents—web-based newspapers and magazines—while UD was chosen because it is crowdsourced and corresponds to Chapman’s (2008) advice for more colloquial data. UD was manually searched for each of the target forms. The corpora were searched with the string *-*Y-er, where Y is one of the particles for the respective particle verbs, following the approach employed by Hilpert (2015), and then manually cleaned. The hits option was set to 500 hits for each of the searched strings. Only type counts are presented and they are not capitalised on further in the analysis, neither in terms of frequency, nor in terms of genre and register specification, due to the objective and scope of the current research. The extracted types have an illustrative purpose here, with their in-depth analysis a natural next step. All the extracted types are provided in Appendix A, where the six tables (Table A1, Table A2, Table A3, Table A4, Table A5 and Table A6) contain the data from the three sources, arranged per affixed particle: -upper (Table A1), -downer (Table A2), -inner (Table A3), -outer (Table A4), -awayer (Table A5), and -offerer (Table A6). They were qualitatively, not quantitatively, explored in search of any conspicuous factor that may suggest any constraints for double -er marking on particle verbs. (For quantitative data on doubler-uppers, see Chapman (2008) and Lensch (2022), even though two considerations should be taken into account: the data in Chapman are outdated at present and those in Lensch (2022) are genre-specific.) The factors considered are: interference from homonymous full words (offer, upper, downer, outer, and inner vs. *awayer), on the hypothesis formulated by Denison that avoidance of homonymous comparative adjectival forms will facilitate doubling; support for symmetrical coercion via antonymy (up vs. down; in vs. out), on the hypothesis that it is likely that the antonymic association might strengthen the production of symmetrical nominalisations on antonymous particles; and figurativity of meaning, adverb particle vs. preposition as constituents of MWVs, and transitivity of the particle verb base.
Assuming the web is a corpus (Gatto 2014; Kilgarriff and Grefenstette 2003), we can use certain examples found by specific searches as evidence against the euphony-rhythmic explanation or motivation for the marking of the -er in particle verbs, since, as attested below, it can be attached to any element with unconstrained flexibility and can be further repeated multiple times, which undermines the rhythmic argument, e.g., as in the examples (2–6) below:
(2)
(3)
(4)
Light-turner-offer-onerer (https://morph.surrey.ac.uk/index.php/author/tim/ accessed on 13 November 2023),
(5)
Headache-bringer-oner(er) (https://morph.surrey.ac.uk/index.php/author/tim/ accessed on 14 November 2023)
(6)
Singing comer-outer (https://www.queerty.com/andrew-cristi-singing-comer-outer-20100408 accessed on 16 November 2023).

3.2. Analysis

3.2.1. The Analytical Model

Considering that constructionism resolves many significant points of difference between MWEs and word formationally created complex lexical items, modelling multiple -er affixations on MWEs from a cognitive-constructionist perspective seems like an Occam’s razor approach. Agentive -er marking on particle verbs occupies a special place in the constructicon of English, and its flexibility ensues from the mere nature of constructions, understood as “emergent clusters of lossy memory traces that are aligned within our high- (hyper!) dimensional conceptual space on the basis of shared form, function, and contextual dimensions” (Goldberg 2019, p. 7).
The constructionist strand employed combines findings, methodological decisions, and presentation formats from construction grammar—Goldberg (2019), Hoffmann (2022)—and construction morphology—Audring (2019) and Booij (2016, 2019). The cognitivist stance embraces “the methodology of analytic thought, which includes the systematic manipulation of ideas, abstraction, comparison, and reasoning, and which is itself introspective in character” (Talmy 2007, p. xi). Support for the latter comes also from psychodynamic interpretations of the mental lexicon within psycholinguistic approaches to complex words. Libben (2021, p. 1) argues strongly against the view of the mental lexicon as “a static repository of representations with fixed structural properties”, ensuing from the generally accepted, underlying metaphor that the mental lexicon is a dictionary. The scholar offers an alternative hypothesis, construing the mental lexicon as a flexicon, a dynamic and highly interconnected system of actions. Within the flexicon, each word is a set of activities that we perform. These are organised via the principles of morphological transcendence and lexical superstates. A lexical superstate lacks a fixed structure and is a hub “of alternative morphological structures […] as potential realization” (Libben 2021, p. 1). It is not an unfounded conjecture to claim that the flexicon is the psycholinguistic (or mental) counterpart of the dynamic, output-based system of the constructicon. Analytically, the flexicon is the bridge between cognitive and constructionist views on complex words and can be used to convincingly model the dynamics of alternative -er affixation patterns on MWVs.

3.2.2. Speakers’ Self-Reflections

One methodological technique in cognitive analysis is the assessment of the “accessibility” of language phenomena to the second level of consciousness (Talmy 2018, p. 219) of speakers. In this respect, the metacognitive salience of doubler-uppers is high, as can be concluded from various people attending to it offline in Talmy’s (2018, p. 222) sense, e.g., Whitman (2010), Zimmer (2015), Zwicky (2013), and Feist (2019). Spontaneous linguistic reflections on salient language phenomena tap into an individual’s language consciousness. The concurring consensus among several individuals in journal columns and blogs is that, doubler-uppers, though unevenly considered to be acceptable (especially in formal written genres), just sound right.
One issue discussed in popular texts on doubler-uppers is worth commenting on—the effect of double agentive affix marking on the attachment of inflectional markers such as the plural -s. Feist (2019) comments on the positioning of inflectional material on nominalisations of phrasal verbs and recognises two possibilities: internal inflection on the verbal element (e.g., passers-by or the washers-up) or external inflection (e.g., washer-ups), with the second sounding awkward and rarely being used. But if the agentive marker appears on both constituents, then there seems to be no choice, and plurality tends to be marked externally, which suggests that doubly marked nominalisation is perceived as a non-divisible single unit. This only comes to strengthen Cappelle’s (2010, p. 335) verdict that “doubling the -er may be the most felicitous option when deriving nouns from phrasal verbs”.

3.2.3. An Allostructional Family View

As argued for in Section 2.3, doubler-uppers are not extravagant reduplications, rather, they are optimal affixal variants in a competition between a single verb-based attached affix, single particle-attached affix, and double affixation on both the verb base and particle within the MWV. The answer to the question of why double marking seems to be the optimal variant, in my opinion, is because it strikes the perfect balance between unity and complexity and provides the most semantically fitting solution to expressly mark a fully unified and substantivized form. The variant of single outer affixation reduces the complexity of the base and results in clashes with homophonous single lexical items like inner, outer, downer, and upper, which supports the idea that homonymy with independent words (be them comparative adjectival forms or nouns) functions as a bootstrapping mechanism for affix doubling. Single verbal part affixation disrupts the conceptual unity of the whole, although it satisfies the headedness condition as the locus for various morphological processes. The double -er marking iconically emphasises both the complexity and the unity of the base: the sameness of the affix mirrors the unity, while the doubling isomorphically via diagrammatic iconicity highlights the complexity. Recognising doubler-uppers as the result of affixation with affix doubling, not of reduplication, more naturally accommodates the polysemy that is starting to arise with some of these nominalisations, a phenomenon characteristic of the suffix -er in the ecosystem of English nominalisations, as expounded by Lieber (2016), and points to the unity in variable -er suffixation on MWVs.
Doubler-uppers form a local family of allostructions, together with the positionally differentiated single marking within the extended family of -er nominalisations and the wider network of nominalisations in English in general. Figure 1 presents the allostructional sister relations and the secondary mother schema with which they are related and which serves as the hub that establishes network relations with other kinds of relatives within the extended -er family.
The allostructional family is a local “hierarchy of actions” in Libben’s (2021, p. 2) sense and may be conceived of as a volatile superstate of -er nominalisations of any particle verb. When committed to the nominalisation of an MWV, a speaker will most probably choose, on different occasions, one or another of the available options. The mother schema (on top in Figure 1) may be identified with the notion of nominalisation (agentive in the local hub presented in the figure), while the leftmost block presents the single particle-attached affixation, as in one-upper, the middle one—the single verb-base-attached affix option, as in looker-on, and the rightmost one—double affixation, as in goer-awayer. The local hub is a small portion of a much wider and more complex network of -er suffixation possibilities in the English language, which will vary in terms of semantic relation (the various readings associated with this suffix) and in terms of the nature of the [[x] [y]] option, as, in many cases, there will be only an [x] (single base variable), as in teacher, or other elements may be added [[[x] [y] [z] -er], as in in-the-parker and up-and-comer), etc.
This allostructional family is available to speakers to choose from in any instance of particle verb nominalisation, and the analysis of the data (the types found in the three sources and the ones from the web as corpus) did not reveal any single factor as a candidate for an absolute or even strong constraint on the choice of double -er marking.
Denison (2008, p. 2014) hypothesised that -er doubling tries to avoid homonymy with a comparative form of an adjective (upper, inner, outer, and rounder), but the data analysed do not bear directly on such a hypothesis. First, downer is not a comparative form of an adjective, but a noun, inner, outer, offer, and upper are also nouns, and more importantly, as independent words, upper and downer have meanings fully compatible with the meaning of some nominalised particle verbs with a stimulus reading, e.g., picker-upper, bringer-upper, and calmer-downer. The existence of homonymous full words may be considered as a strengthening factor in -upper constructions (as they are the most numerous in all sources) and even suggest a compounding origin story. It is probably not by chance that OED (Oxford English Dictionary 2023) identifies -upper as “a combing form (i.e., a compound constituent), forming rhyming compounds based on phrasal verbs with up adv. with the agent noun corresponding to the verb as the first element, as fixer-upper n., maker-upper n., picker-upper n., etc”. Downer, inner, offer, and outer also exist as independent lexemes (admittedly, offer stands apart as the most homonymous, i.e., no semantic association can be established between the noun offer and the nominalised -off constituent), but none of them compare to -upper in terms of types of doubler-upper nominalisations (although nominalised -out boasts significantly more instances than any of the other analysed particles, with the exception of -upper). This should come as no surprise, since Dixon ([1991] 2005, p. 346) states that “up, out and off—these are in fact the most commonly occurring prepositions in phrasal verbs. Others are down, in and on, which are the next most common prepositional components”. This means that it is not homonymy with a comparative adjectival form that is the leading factor, but the productivity of the respective particles for constituting different types of particle verbs. The role of homonymy for doubler-uppers can be interpreted as one among multiple motivations for the constructions, rather than a dedicated homonymy-resolution strategy. In other words, neither a strengthening nor a constraining effect can be postulated across the board in relation to homonymy. The most frequent prepositions in particle verbs logically display the greatest number of types of doubler-upper nominalisations.
In both antonymous pairs up vs. down and in vs. out, any expectation of mutual coercion remains unsupported. Upper and downer nominalisations show as stark a contrast in terms of types as inner and outer do. Symmetry supported by particle antonymy does not seem to be an influential factor, especially considering that awayer construction types are not remarkably fewer than -inner ones.
Both breaker-upper (reported to have an idiomatic, i.e., figurative meaning), and goer-awayer (identified as a compositionally constructed particle verb with spatial meaning) exist (among numerous other types), which implies that figurativity in the semantic composition of the particle verb does not seem to be a facilitating or an adversely interfering factor determining the choice of suffixation alternative.
The distinction between prepositions and adverbs in the constituency of particle verbs also does not seem to have an immediate effect on the choice or not of double -er marking. Maker-outer is derived from a verb and an adverb particle and has figurative meaning in the sense from which the nominalisation is derived, while adder-toer is derived from a verb–preposition combination and is not characterised by idiomaticity or figurativity, and putter-upper-wither includes triple affixing (on each constituent of the MWV) and is figurative in meaning. It can be cautiously concluded that the number and status of the non-verb constituent(s) in a particle verb do not constrain or determine the possibility of double or multiple -er marking (depending on the nature of the base).
Transitivity also does not appear be an operationally constraining factor for doubler-uppers. Double -er marking attaches equally easily to both transitive and intransitive particle verbs: filler-outertr, eater-outerintr; (gut) sucker-innertr, sleeper-innerintr.; ticker-offertr., shower-offerintr.; disher-uppertr., messer-upperintr.; taker-downertr., sitter-downerintr.; and giver-awayertr., runner-awayerintr., despite the existence of well-established verb-attached single suffix alternative nominalisations. Go out and go away are intransitive MWVs (unlike the transitive go for) and both goer out and goer away exist as alternatives to doubler-uppers. Blow up is a transitive MWV and both blower-up and blower-upper are actualised alternatives. The predominance of nominalisations from transitive MWVs, as can be evidenced in Table 2 below, is exclusively dependent on the semantics of the combination of the verb base and particle in the MWV and does not seem to be correlated with a specific allostructional choice, which suggests that the said choice is not sensitive to transitivity.
It may also be mentioned that there is a tendency for recursive expansion of the MWEs via the incorporation of objects in certain nominalisations, such as football-snatcher-awayer, cab-runner-awayer, spoon-putter-outer, trash-taker-outer, and problem-hasher-outer, etc., which confirms the unified status of doubler-upper particle verb nominalisations as word elements, which is also supported by the tendency for hyphenation in their spelling.
It might be stipulated that there are two further motivating factors for doubling the suffix -er. One of them is the existence of a comparative correlative construction, which purely digrammatically might support doubling. The second is the plausibility in certain doubler-upper types (especially with -upper and -downer) of a compounding derivational interpretation. Even though Lensch (2018, p. 159, footnote 2) insists “that -er simultaneously attaches to verb and particle/preposition in the case of doubler-upper nouns” and that they do not represent “a case of compounding in which a nominalized verb combines with a nominalized particle/preposition”, it is not improbable that the latter might have been an initial motivating factor. These two-fold affixed nominalisations might have started as affixed verbs compounded with upper or downer, and from there, analogy has strengthened the case of doubling the marker across other particle verbs. It has long been recognised that there is a tendency for “[a] bipartite marker […] to replace an isofunctional marker consisting of only one of the two elements, i.e., the complex marker replaces the simple marker […]; my translation—SRA)” (Anderson 2015, p. 278, quoting one of Kuryłowicz’s laws of analogy). This plausible motivation story, not a diachronic origin story, is in keeping with the ideas of lexical relatedness and multiple motivations for lexical items via multiple existing schemas (Booij and Audring 2018).
Specific quantitative information in relation to any of the factors mentioned above would make the claims in this qualitative analysis sufficiently more robust and is the naturally occurring subsequent stage of this work in progress. The same applies to the patterns of polysemanticisation of the doubler-upper construction—agentive, patient, entity, and eventive readings (although the place and inhabitant readings typical of the suffix -er are definitely lacking in any of the analysed types) to add to the study of this polyfunctional suffix in English that can attach to “verbs and nouns, but also to adjectives, prepositions, verb-particle constructions (sometimes with an “extra” -er) with the particle preceding or following the verb and if following the verb, preceding or following the -er suffix, and a variety of phrases, including various kinds of noun phrases, prepositional phrases, adverb phrases, conjoined phrases, verb phrases and a handful of less easily categorized constructions” (Ryder 2000, p. 293).

4. Conclusions

Doubler-upper nominalisations appear to be deviant, both lexically and derivationally, and, at the same time, optimal in maintaining a balance between complexity and unity, which, in many cases, may also be supported by optimal rhythmic considerations. If we subscribe to the postulation that “[t]he form of a derivative is optimal if it is the best one morphophonologically” (Hathout and Namer 2014, p. 186), then we need to redefine ‘morphophonologically’ in terms of naturalness and semantic fitness. These paradoxical claims may both be separately and conjointly true, if we recognise the dynamicity of language as a complex, emergent, adaptive system. Such kinds of paradoxes and phenomena, akin to the flexibility of nominalisations of particle verbs in English, are captured by Libben’s (2021) interpretation of the lexicon as a flexicon comprising words which are themselves dynamic actions, where two principles operate to maximise naming possibilities and storage capabilities—morphological transcendence and superstates.
Double (or multiple) -er marking (where marking is intended to collapse any commitment to process associations—compounding, affixation, reduplication, or a mixture of these) on particle verbs in English results from the suffix -er developing lexical superstates via morphological transcendence, without leading to fixed morphological structures as Libben (2021) claims, since words are actions, not static representations stored in the mind. The notion of the flexicon captures both onomasiological and semasiological perspectives in word processing. In the speaker’s view, a superstate realisation is epiphenomenally shaped when searching for a way to encode a target meaning in a specific communicative situation, while the specific realisation in context triggers relations to a superstate in comprehension and models the relations between item-specific and schema-general knowledge. This dynamicity and flexibility can be analytically captured by applying an allostructional approach with a balanced “division of labour between sister links and mother schemas” (Audring 2019, p. 293).
The still-questionable status of doubler-uppers as ‘emancipated’ colloquialisms within a tripartite competition of free speaker’s choice points towards a very complicated relationship between entrenchment (the individual speaker’s perspective) and conventionalisation (the communal status and distribution of types and tokens of such constructions), which are interrelated via feedback loops into usualisation frequencies (see Schmid (2020) for elaborate analyses of these dimensions of dynamic language). The use of doubler-uppers has been claimed to be on the rise diachronically (Chapman 2008, pp. 272, 276, 280) and in terms of permeation in written genres, more specifically British and American newspapers, as claimed by Lensch (2022, p. 83), but considering that very little is predictable in language (Langacker 2008), not much can be said about their immanent conventionalisation.

Funding

This study was financed by the European Union-NextGenerationEU, through the National Recovery and Resilience Plan of the Republic of Bulgaria, SUMMIT project BG-RRP-2.004-0008-C01.

Institutional Review Board Statement

Not applicable.

Informed Consent Statement

Not applicable.

Data Availability Statement

Data available on request: [email protected].

Conflicts of Interest

The author declares no conflict of interest.

Appendix A

Lists of the raw data retrieved from the NOW corpus, GloWbE, and UD per particle.
Table A1. -upper.
Table A1. -upper.
NOWGloWbEUD
162 unique types out of 188 overall count
115 types36 types37 types
8 types coincide across the three data sources; 11 types coincide between NOW and UD; 7 types coincide between NOW and GloWbE
backer-upperbar-propper-upperadder-upper
ball-picker-upperboomer-upperbackseat washer-upper
beater-upperbreaker-upperbeater-upper
blower-upperbuilder-upperblower upper
breaker uppercheerer-upperborder-upper
brusher-uppercleaner-upperchecker-upper-onner
builder-upperdoer-uppercheerer-upper
butter-upperdryer-uppercleaner-upper
caller-upperfiller-uppercracker-upper
catcher-upperfixer-upperdaisy pusher-upper
chatter-upperidea-thinker-upperdoer-upper
cheerer-upperjumper-upperfixer-upper
chief-washer-upperknocker-upperflipper-upper
cleaner-upperletter-maker-upperfucker-upper
cocker-upperliner-upperhanger-upper
cover-uppermaker-upperholder-upper
cracker-uppermasher-upperhooker-upper
curler-uppermind-maker-upperkicker-upper
disher-uppermixer-upperknocker-upper
doer-uppermopper-uppermaker-upper
dog-stink-cleaner-uppernumber-maker-uppermesser-upper
doggy-poo-picker-upperpicker-uppermixer upper
drawer-upperpuke-mopper-uppernecker-upper
dreamer-upperpuker-picker-upperpicker-upper
dresser-upperputter-upperringer-upper
feeler-upperquicker-picker-upperrunner-upper
filler-upperramper-upperscrewer-upper
fixer-upperrounder-uppershutter-upper
follier-uppersinger-uppersneaker-upper
follower-uppersnapper-uppertaper-upper
fresher-upperstander-upperthicker-picker-upper
fronter-upperstarter-uppertrader-upper
fucker-upperstitcher-uppertrash-picker-upper
gammon-winder-upperwaker-uppertrumpster pucker-upper
giver-upperwarmer-upperupper topper flopper stopper
hanger-upperwasher-upperwaker-upper
hangover-fixer-upper word maker-upper
holder-upper
holderer-upper
kid-picker-upper
knocker-upper
lifter-upper
litter-picker-upper
looker-upper
loosener-upper
maker-upper
masher-upper
mega-fixer-upper
messer-upper
mixer-upper
non-cleaner-upper
non-fixer-upper
non-messer-upper
non-stuff-maker-upper
old-house-fixer-upper
opener-upper
owner-upper
padfixer-upper
pants-puller-upper
paster-upper
pepper-upper
perker-upper
picker-upper
pooper-upper
price-pusher-upper
pumper-upper
puncher-upper
pusher-upper
quicker-picker-upper
ripper-upper
roller-upper
saliva-sucker-upper
scooper-upper
scraper-upper
sender-upper
setter-upper
shaker-upper
shower-upper
shutter-upper
smasher-upper
snapper-upper
soaker-upper
sock-picker-upper
sopper-upper
splitter-upper
starter-upper
sticker-upper
stirrer-upper
street-cleaner-upper
sucker-upper
sweeper-upper
switcher-upper
table-cleaner-upper
teamer-upper
tearer-upper
tidier-upper
time-taker-upper
topper-upper
toucher-upper
trader-upper
trash-picker-upper
tree-cleaner-upper
tree-putter-upper
tripper-upper
trouser-holder-upper
urban-trader-upper
user-upper
waker-upper
warmer-upper
washer-upper
weigher-upper
whipper-upper
whooper-upper
winder-upper
word-maker-upper
Table A2. -downer.
Table A2. -downer.
NOWGloWbEUD
20 unique types out of 22 overall count
13 types3 types6 types
2 types coincide in NOW and GloWbE
calmer-downercalmer-downerfixer-downer
closer-downerfaller-downerhanger-downers
cutter-downertearer-downerone-upper downer
gawker-shutter-downer oner-downer
knocker-downer poster taker downer
pusher-downer shooter downer
putter-downer
sitter-downer
slower-downer
taker-downer
tearer-downer
wolfer-downer
writer-downer
Table A3. -inner.
Table A3. -inner.
NOWGloWebUD
21 unique types out of 25 overall count
8 types9 types8 types
2 types coincide across the three data sources; 2 types coincide between NOW and GloWbE
breaker-innercutter-innerbacker-inner
cutter-innerfiller-innerbutter-inner
daily checker-innerfitter-innercaller-inner
filler-innerheader-innercaver-inner
keeper-innerlocker-innerfiller-inner
putter-innerputter-innerrubber-inner
sleeper-innershover-innersleeper-inner
tucker-innersleeper-innerspinner-inner
sucker-inner
Table A4. -outer.
Table A4. -outer.
NOWGloWbEUD
76 unique types out of 88 overall count
50 types21 types17 types
2 types coincide across the three data sources; 2 types coincide between GloWbE and UD; 2 types coincide between NOW and UD; and 6 types coincide between NOW and GloWbE
acter-outerbanger-outerasker outer
bin-putter-outercaller-outerbacker-outer
blotter-outerchurner-outerbanger-outer
blower-outerdiner-outerblacker-outer
blurter-outerfreaker-outereater outerer
booger-pointer-outerhair-puller-outereXer-outer
bummer-outerhelper-outerfader-outer
caller-outerhole-pointer-outerfreaker outer
candle-putter-outerkicker outerhappiness sucker-outer
churner-outerneck-sticker-outerleaver-outer
closer-outerpointer-outermaker-outer
disher-outerproblem-hasher-outerplane-checker outer
eater-outerpuller-outerpuller-outer
filler-outerputter-outerroot beer giver-outer
finder-outersacker-outertrash taker-outer
flamer-outerseller-outerworker-outer
getter-outersitter-outerzoomer-outer
giver-outerstopper-outer
goer-outertaker-outer
hander-outerwhipper outer
hanger-outerworker-outer
helper-outer
lasher-outer
opter-outer
pointer-outer
pourer-outer
puller-outer
putter-outer
puzzler-outer
reader-outer
ripper-outer
roller-outer
ruler-outer
runner-outer
seeker-outer
sitter-outer
sniffer-outer
snuffer-outer
sorter-outer
spoon-putter-outer
stomper-outer
striker-outer
taker-outer
thinker-outer
trash-taker-outer
trier-outer
walker-outer
wiper-outer
worker-outer
zoner-outer
Table A5. –awayer.
Table A5. –awayer.
NOWGloWbEUD
9 unique types out of 9 overall
3 types1 type5 types
No coincidence of types across the data sources
football-snatcher-awayerpadder awayerrunner-awayer
giver-awayer hair-goer-awayer
thrower-awayer keeper-awayer
cab runner awayer
pusher-awayer
Table A6.offer.
Table A6.offer.
NOWGloWbEUD
12 unique types out of 14 overall
9 types2 types3 types
2 types coincide between GloWbE and UD
blower-offerpisser-offerpisser-offerer
payer-offersetter offershower-offer
pusher-offer cutter-offer
ripper-offer
suit taker-offer
sicker-peeler-offer
switcher-offer
taker-offer
ticker-offer
Examples A1. Examples of combinations quoted as impossible in (Dixon [1991] 2005, pp. 345–46).

Notes

1
Chapman (2008, p. 267) identifies four participants in this competition: “we have four patterns of nominalizations (by-stander, picker-up, picker-upper, pick-uppper) and three subcategories of multi-word verbs that serve as inputs” but the first one is considered no longer productive (Cappelle 2010; Denison 2008).
2
Particle verb is chosen over phrasal verb for two reasons: (i) to neutralise the distinction between preposition and particle and (ii) to remain agnostic in relation to idiomaticity since by definition phrasal verb implies “some degree of idiomaticity in the assembly of the verb plus preposition (cry over something), or verb plus separable particle (run up the flag, run the flag up), verb plus inseparable particle (run up a debt), or the double assembly of verb plus particle and preposition (face up to problems)” (Dirven 2001, p. 39), since idiomaticity does not affect the choice of -er doubling or not and neither does the preposition—adverbial particle distinction, and examples such as putter upper wither also exist.
3
It should be noted that when Lensch (2022) identifies doubler-uppers as templates, she uses the term template in Good’s (2016, p. 7) sense as “[a]n analytical device used to characterize the linear realization of a linguistic constituent whose linear stipulations are unexpected from the point of view of a given linguist’s approach to linguistic analysis”. Hoffmann’s (2022, p. 14) template is a special type of construction, which results from constructions’ unification and is fully expected as a mental construct within the construction.
4
In all fairness, Ryder (2000, p. 292) offers a host of arguments for the newly acquired clitic-like features of the suffix -er in its diachronic development: increasing frequency, widening of meaning, its use for “the primarily grammatical function of anaphora” (Ryder 2000, p. 292).

References

  1. Anderson, Stephen. 2015. Morphological change. In Routledge Handbook of Historical Linguistics. Edited by Claire Bowern and Bethwyn Evans. New York: Routledge, pp. 264–86. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  2. Aronoff, Mark. 1976. Word Formation in Generative Grammar. Cambridge: The MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  3. Audring, Jenny. 2019. Mothers or sisters? The encoding of morphological knowledge. Word Structure 12: 274–96. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  4. Baeskow, Heike. 2015. Rules, patterns and schemata in word-formation. In Word-Formation. An International Handbook of the Languages of Europe. iBooks. Edited by Peter O. Müller, Ingeborg Ohnheiser, Susan Olsen and Franz Rainer. Berlin and Boston: De Gruyter Mouton, vol. 2, pp. 32–184. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  5. Bauer, Laurie. 1983. English Word-Formation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  6. Bauer, Laurie. 2017. Compounds and Compounding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  7. Bauer, Laurie, Rochelle Lieber, and Ingo Plag. 2013. The Oxford Reference Guide to English Morphology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  8. Benczes, Réka. 2012. Just a load of hibber-gibber? Making sense of English rhyming compounds. Australian Journal of Linguistics 32: 299–326. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  9. Blevins, James. 2006. Word-based morphology. Journal of Linguistics 42: 531–73. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  10. Bolinger, Dwight. 1971. The Phrasal Verb in English. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
  11. Booij, Geert. 2010. Construction Morphology. Oxford: Oxfrod University Press. [Google Scholar]
  12. Booij, Geert. 2013. Morphology in construction grammar. In The Oxford Handbook of Construction Grammar. Edited by Thomas Hoffmann and Graeme Trousdale. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 255–73. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  13. Booij, Geert. 2016. Construction morphology. In The Cambridge Handbook of Morphology. Edited by Andrew Hippisley and Greg Stump. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 424–48. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  14. Booij, Geert. 2017. The construction of words. In The Cambridge Handbook of Cognitive Linguistics, Kindle edition. Edited by Barbara Dancygier. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 396–433. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  15. Booij, Geert. 2019. The role of schemas in construction morphology. Word Structure 12: 385–95. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  16. Booij, Geert, and Francesca Masini. 2015. The role of second order schemas in the construction of complex words. In Semantics of Complex Words. Edited by Laurie Bauer, Livia Körtvélyessi and Pavol Štekauer. Berlin: Springer, pp. 47–66. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  17. Booij, Geert, and Jenny Audring. 2018. Partial motivation, multiple motivation: The role of output schemas in morphology. In The Construction of Words. Edited by Geert Booij. Berlin: Springer, pp. 59–80. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  18. Cappelle, Bert. 2010. Doubler-upper nouns: A challenge for usage-based models of language? In Cognitive Perspectives on Word Formation. Edited by Alexander Onysko and Sascha Michel. Berlin and New York: Mouton de Gruyter, pp. 335–74. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  19. Chapman, Don. 2008. Fixer-uppers and passers-by: Nominalization of verb-particle constructions. In Studies in the History of the English Language IV: Empirical and Analytical Advances in the Study of English Language Change. Edited by Susan M. Fitzmaurice and Donka Minkova. Berlin and New York: Mouton de Gruyter, pp. 265–99. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  20. Cotter, Coleen, and John Damaso. 2007. Online dictionaries as emerging archives of contemporary usage and collaborative lexicography. In Queen Mary Occasional Papers Advancing Linguistics (OPALS). London: OPALS. [Google Scholar]
  21. Crystal, David. 2003. The Cambridge Encyclopedia of the English Language, 2nd ed. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  22. Denison, David. 2008. Patterns and productivity. In Studies in the History of the English Language IV: Empirical and Analytical Advances in the Study of English Language Change. Edited by Susan M. Fitzmaurice and Donka Minkova. Berlin and New York: Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, pp. 207–30. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  23. Dirven, René. 2001. The metaphoric in recent cognitive approaches to English phrasal verbs. metaphorik.de 1: 39–54. [Google Scholar]
  24. Dirven, René, and Marjolijn Verspoor. 2004. Cognitive Exploration of Language and Linguistics. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  25. Dixon, Robert M. W. 2005. A Semantic Approach to English Grammar, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. First published 1991. [Google Scholar]
  26. Feist, Tim. 2019. The headache-bringer-oner(er) of the English agentive suffix. Available online: https://morph.surrey.ac.uk/index.php/2019/01/16/the-headache-bringer-onerer-of-the-english-agentive-suffix/ (accessed on 9 December 2023).
  27. Gatto, Maristella. 2014. The Web as Corpus. Theory and Practice. London: Bloomsbury. [Google Scholar]
  28. GloWbE. 2023. Available online: https://www.english-corpora.org/glowbe/ (accessed on 6 December 2023).
  29. Goldberg, Adele. 2006. Constructions at Work: The Nature of Generalization in Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  30. Goldberg, Adele. 2019. Explain Me This: Creativity, Competition, and the Partial Productivity of Constructions. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
  31. Good, Jeff. 2016. The Linguistic Typology of Templates. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  32. Harris, Alice. 2017. Multiple Exponence. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  33. Haspelmath, Martin. 2023. Defining the word. Word 69: 283–97. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  34. Hathout, Nabil, and Fiammetta Namer. 2014. Discrepancy between form and meaning in word formation: The case of over- and under-marking in French. In Morphology and Meaning. Selected Papers from the 15th International Morphology Meeting, Vienna, February 2012. Edited by Franz Rainer, Francesco Gardani, Hans Christian Luschützky and Wolfgang U. Dressler. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, pp. 177–90. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  35. Haugen, Jason D. 2015. Reduplication of affixes. In Workshop on Replicative Processes in Grammar. Leipzig: Universität Leipzig. Available online: https://home.uni-leipzig.de/muellerg/replication/haugen.pdf (accessed on 6 December 2023).
  36. Heyvaert, Liesbet. 2010. A cognitive-functional perspective on deverbal nominalization in English: Descriptive findings and theoretical ramifications. In The semantics of Nominalizations Across Languages and Frameworks. Edited by Monika Rathert and Artemis Alexiadou. Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton, pp. 51–81. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  37. Hilpert, Martin. 2015. From hand-carved to computer-based: Noun-participle compounding and the upward-strengthening hypothesis. Cognitive Linguistics 26: 113–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  38. Hilpert, Martin. 2019a. Construction Grammar and Its Application to English, 2nd ed. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Available online: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.3366/j.ctvsf1p6c (accessed on 15 November 2023).
  39. Hilpert, Martin. 2019b. Higher-order schemas in morphology: What they are, how they work, and where to find them. Word Structure 12: 261–73. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  40. Hoffmann, Thomas. 2022. Construction Grammar. The Structure of English. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  41. Hurch, Bernhard, ed. 2005. Studies on Reduplication [Empirical Approaches to Language Typology 28]. Berlin and New York: De Gruyter Mouton. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  42. Inkelas, Sharon, and Cheryl Zoll. 2005. Reduplication: Doubling in Morphology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  43. Kilgarriff, Adam, and Gregory Grefenstette. 2003. Web as corpus. Computational Linguistics 29: 333–48. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  44. Kotowski, Sven, and Ingo Plag. 2023. The semantics of derivational morphology: Introduction. In The Semantics of Derivational Morphology. Theory, Methods, Evidence. Edited by Sven Kotowski and Ingo Plag. Berlin and Boston: Walter de Gruyter, pp. 1–14. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  45. Langacker, Ronald. 2008. Cognitive Grammar. A Basic Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  46. Lemmens, Maarten. 2015. Cognitive semantics. In Routledge Handbook of Semantics. Edited by Nick Riemer. New York: Routledge, pp. 90–105. [Google Scholar]
  47. Lensch, Anke. 2018. Fixer-uppers. Reduplication in the derivation of phrasal verbs. In Exact Repetition in Grammar and Discourse. Edited by Rita Finkbeiner and Freywald Ulrike. Berlin and New York: Mouton de Gruyter, pp. 158–81. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  48. Lensch, Anke. 2022. Diggers-out, leaf clearer-uppers and stayer-onner-for-nowers: On creativity and extravagance in English -er nominalisations. In Extravagant Morphology. Studies in Rule-Bending, Pattern-Extending and Theory-Challenging Morphology. Edited by Matthias Eitelmann and Dagmar Haumann. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins, pp. 73–100. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  49. Libben, Gary. 2021. From lexicon to flexicon: The principles of morphological transcendence and lexical superstates in the characterization of words in the mind. Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence 4: 788430. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  50. Lieber, Rochelle. 2004. Morphology and Lexical Semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  51. Lieber, Rochelle. 2016. English Nouns: The Ecology of Nominalization. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  52. Lieber, Rochelle, and Marios Andreou. 2018. Aspect and modality in the interpretation of deverbal -er nominals in English. Morphology 28: 187–217. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  53. Mansfield, John. 2021. The word as a unit of internal predictability. Linguistics 59: 1427–72. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  54. Masini, Francesca. 2019. Multi-word expressions and morphology. In Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Linguistics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  55. Mattiola, Simone, and Francesca Masini. 2022. Discontinuous reduplication: A typological sketch. STUF 75: 271–316. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  56. McIntyre, Andrew. 2004. Sum: English affix reduplication. The Linguist List 15: 1929. [Google Scholar]
  57. Mencken, Henri Louis. 1945. The American Language Supplement 1: The American Language: An Inquiry into the Development of English in the United States. New York: Alfred A. Knopf. [Google Scholar]
  58. Mithun, Marianne. 2016. Affix ordering: Motivation and interpretation. In The Cambridge Handbook of Morphology. Edited by Andrew Hippisley and Greg Stump. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 149–85. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  59. NOW. 2023. Available online: https://www.english-corpora.org/now/ (accessed on 5 December 2023).
  60. Oxford English Dictionary. 2023. Available online: https://www.oed.com/?tl=true (accessed on 9 December 2023).
  61. Quirk, Randolph, Sydney Greenbaum, Geoffrey Leech, and Jan Svartvik. 1985. A Comprehensive Grammar of the English Language. London: Pearson Longman. [Google Scholar]
  62. Rastall, Paul. 2004. Playful English: Kinds of reduplication. English Today 80: 38–41. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  63. Ryder, Mary Ellen. 1999. Bankers and blue-chippers: An account of -er formations in Present-day English. English Language and Linguistics 3: 269–97. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  64. Ryder, Mary Ellen. 2000. Complex -er nominals: Where grammaticalization and lexicalization meet? In Between Grammar and Lexicon. Edited by Ellen Contini-Morava and Yishai Tobin. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins, pp. 291–332. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  65. Schmid, Hans-Jörg. 2020. The Dynamics of the Linguistic System Usage, Conventionalization, and Entrenchment. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  66. Schulte im Walde, Sabine, and Eva Smolka, eds. 2020. Constituents in multiword expressions: What is their role, and why do we care? In The Role of Constituents in Multiword Expressions: An Interdisciplinary, Cross-Lingual Perspective. Berlin: Language Science Press, pp. iii–xix. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  67. Stolz, Thomas. 2018. (Non-)Canonical reduplication. In Non-Prototypical Reduplication. Edited by Aina Urdze. Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton, pp. 201–77. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  68. Talmy, Leonard. 2007. Forward. In Methods in Cognitive Linguistics. Edited by Monica Gonzalez-Marquez, Irene Mittelberg, Seana Coulson and Michael J. Spivey. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins, pp. xi–xxi. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  69. Talmy, Leonard. 2018. Ten Lectures on Cognitive Semantics. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
  70. Urban Dictionary. 1999–2024. Available online: https://www.urbandictionary.com/ (accessed on 9 December 2023).
  71. Velupillai, Viveka. 2012. An Introduction to Linguistic Typology. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  72. Walker, James. 2009. Double -er suffixation in English: Morphological, phonological and sociolinguistic reflections. Lexis—Journal in English Lexicology HS 1: 5–13. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  73. Wentworth, Harold. 1936. On adding the suffix of agency, -ER, to adverbs. American Speech 11: 369–70. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  74. Whitman, Neal. 2010. Picker uppers and putter upper withers. Available online: https://literalminded.wordpress.com/2010/03/02/picker-uppers-and-putter-upper-withers/ (accessed on 9 December 2023).
  75. Zimmer, Ben. 2015. More parents opt in to ‘opt out’. The Wallstreet Journal, April 24. Available online: https://www.wsj.com/articles/more-parents-opt-into-opt-out-1429893574(accessed on 3 December 2023).
  76. Zwicky, Arnold. 2013. Breaking up is hard to do. Available online: https://arnoldzwicky.org/2013/08/25/breaking-up-is-hard-to-do/ (accessed on 9 December 2023).
Figure 1. The -er particle verb nominalisation family.
Figure 1. The -er particle verb nominalisation family.
Languages 09 00091 g001
Table 1. Types of doubler-uppers with up, down, in, out, off, and away found in NOW, GloWbE, and UD.
Table 1. Types of doubler-uppers with up, down, in, out, off, and away found in NOW, GloWbE, and UD.
NOWGloWbEUDTypes
-upper1153637162
-downer133620
-innner89821
-outer50211776
-awayer3159
-offer92312
Table 2. Percentage of nominalisations from transitive and intransitive MWVs within the dataset.
Table 2. Percentage of nominalisations from transitive and intransitive MWVs within the dataset.
ParticlePercentage of Nominalisations from Transitive MWVsPercentage of Nominalisations from Intransitive MWVs
-up26.5%73.5%
-down20%80%
-in47.7%52.3%
-out26%74%
-away77.8%22.2%
-off83.3%16.7%
Total27.3%72.7%
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Bagasheva, A. An Upper Take on Doubler-Uppers. Languages 2024, 9, 91. https://doi.org/10.3390/languages9030091

AMA Style

Bagasheva A. An Upper Take on Doubler-Uppers. Languages. 2024; 9(3):91. https://doi.org/10.3390/languages9030091

Chicago/Turabian Style

Bagasheva, Alexandra. 2024. "An Upper Take on Doubler-Uppers" Languages 9, no. 3: 91. https://doi.org/10.3390/languages9030091

APA Style

Bagasheva, A. (2024). An Upper Take on Doubler-Uppers. Languages, 9(3), 91. https://doi.org/10.3390/languages9030091

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop