1. Introduction: Categories
At least until the 19th century, linguists showed little interest in or—perhaps more accurately—lacked the opportunity to become thoroughly acquainted with the structural differences of languages. As a result, the prevailing approach among grammarians has been to assume that notions such as ‘word’ as well as grammatical categories like ‘noun’, ‘verb’, ‘adjective’, ‘adverb’, and ‘preposition’—whose study goes back to antiquity—were cognitively grounded and thus universally applicable (
Haspelmath, 2014). However, with the increasing availability of data from non-Indo-European (IE) languages beginning in the 19th century, linguists began to observe that these languages often display markedly different organizational patterns and properties, including significant variation in the number and type of categories, word classes, or parts of speech. This led to growing scepticism about the classical teaching of nine parts of speech (pronoun, noun, verb, participle, adverb, article, preposition, conjunction, and interjection) and even raised doubts about the universality of the notion of ‘word’ itself, particularly with the rise of the concept of the ‘morpheme’. According to
Haspelmath (
2014), it, then, became increasingly common to argue that the analysis of non-IE languages should not be forced into the categories developed for IE languages, since descriptive categories “depend entirely on the inner form of each language” and, accordingly, each language should be described “in its own terms” (
Boas, 1911).
While early comparative linguists were primarily concerned with uncovering historical and genetic relationships among languages, structuralist linguistics—which emphasized the synchronic study of individual languages—gained prominence from the mid-20th century onwards. This approach led to the proposal of new language-specific categories and the recognition that certain categories may be unique to particular languages (
Sapir, 1921;
Bloomfield, 1933). However, this perspective clashed head-on with the new rising Chomskyan paradigm, which posited that grammatical categories—or at least their constituent features—are universal (
Chomsky, 1970;
Baker, 2003). As a result, linguists largely abandoned the earlier practice of identifying and justifying the most appropriate categories for describing individual languages. Instead, the focus shifted to revealing the fundamental principles governing language across all humanity, and lexical categories such as noun, verb, adjective, and preposition came to be assumed as universal. In the following decades, alternative classificatory frameworks received limited attention and, particularly with regard to categories, it was common to essentially reaffirm Chomsky’s position.
From the late 20th century on, however, a number of scholars (e.g.,
Croft, 1991,
2000,
2023;
Hengeveld, 1998;
Van Valin & LaPolla, 1997;
Dik, 1997;
Evans, 2000;
Baker, 2003;
Dixon, 2010;
Chung, 2012; among others) began to question the universality of these four major lexical categories, but a lack of consensus regarding the number of cross-linguistic categories became evident and proved difficult to resolve. This may, to some extent, be related to the difficulty in finding the right set of criteria to distinguish between word classes (
Crystal, 1967) or, more importantly, in establishing a definition enabling the universal identification of distinct word classes.
In an effort to address the limitations of strictly morphosyntactic criteria for defining lexical categories, various scholars have proposed semantically grounded characterizations of major word classes.
Givón (
1984) offers a semantic perspective, for example, by characterizing nouns and verbs in terms of time-stability. Nouns are thus said to represent experiences that remain stable over time, whereas verbs refer to rapidly changing states of affairs. He also acknowledges the prototypical nature of some members of a category, which are considered to be more central than others. Similarly, Langacker’s Cognitive Grammar (
Langacker, 1987a,
1987b,
2002,
2008,
2009) concurs that prototypical nouns and verbs denote physical objects and overt physical actions, respectively, but introduces the idea of higher-level schemas, which represent universal, schematic realizations that underlie all category members and are grounded in basic cognitive processes. Word classes are thus defined on two levels: a more general level showing universal semantic schemas where nouns and verbs are defined as linguistic expressions that designate a thing and a process, respectively, and a more specific level offering local instantiations that range from prototypical to non-prototypical members. For his part,
Croft (
1990,
2001,
2007) synthesizes semantic and pragmatic perspectives by proposing three semantic classes—objects, actions, and properties, which correspond to three pragmatic functions—reference, predication, and modification. These classes and functions are in turn aligned with the traditional categories of nouns, verbs, and adjectives, respectively, which serve as typological prototypes rather than fixed grammatical classes. Importantly, these prototypes describe only the core of each category, while their boundaries are defined by the grammar of individual languages. Finally,
Haspelmath (
2010) suggests that grammatical comparison must not begin with language-specific categories but rather with comparative concepts that are clearly distinct from descriptive categories. More specifically, an accurate analysis of word classes must take into account the semantic properties associated with the comparative concepts considered fundamental to communication, namely the capacity to refer and to predicate, and even to describe properties of entities. These functions appear to correspond to the traditionally used categories of noun, verb, and adjective, which, as
Haspelmath (
2012) argues, can be readily identified across languages and, as
Croft (
2000) points out, can be considered typological prototypes. In sum, these semantically oriented models offer a more flexible and cognitively grounded understanding of lexical categories, while acknowledging cross-linguistic variation in their grammatical instantiation.
In an attempt to sum up the situation, the evidence provided by the analysis of a wide range of languages from very diverse families reveals that there are hardly any languages that lack a definitive distinction between nouns and verbs (e.g.,
Schachter, 1985;
Sasse, 1993;
Davis et al., 2014;
Vogel & Comrie, 2000;
Haspelmath, 20011,
2023), although this distinction is not always as clear-cut as it is in IE languages
2. Adjectives also appear to be widely attested cross-linguistically, although they are less universally represented than verbs and nouns. Finally, as far as the other categories are concerned, for example prepositions, adverbs, pronouns, determiners, quantifiers, numerals, coordinators and subordinators, and particles, these tend to vary much more significantly from one language to another.
One of the language families in which the distinction between the categories of verb and noun is not as well-defined as might be expected is the Celtic family. In these languages, a hybrid category exists that is commonly referred to as the verbal noun, which, from the earliest attested stages of its historical development, appears to demonstrate that the boundary between verbal and nominal categories is far from clear-cut, despite the bias suggested by the name generally attributed to this category. As a result, the study and analysis of verbal nouns have consistently attracted considerable scholarly interest, so that now this work will focus on an investigation of this category in Scottish Gaelic from the perspective of intersective gradience.
The organization of this paper is as follows: after a brief account of the most relevant typological properties in Scottish Gaelic in
Section 2,
Section 3 introduces the notion of the verbal noun in Celtic linguistics and provides a summary of the way in which this category has traditionally been analysed with respect to its origin and nature as either a nominal or a verbal element.
Section 4 explains the concept of gradience in relation to word classes, parts of speech, or categories, and more specifically of intersective gradience, where an item exhibits characteristics of multiple word classes, thereby illustrating the intersection between categories.
Section 5 offers a comprehensive investigation of the distribution and functions of the verbal noun in Scottish Gaelic by examining a range of morphosyntactic and semantic properties across various contexts with the aim of determining whether the category of verbal nouns in Scottish Gaelic has more verbal or more nominal properties. A detailed discussion of the results derived from this analysis is provided in
Section 6, and, finally, a summary of the most relevant findings obtained in this research concludes this paper.
2. Typological Description of Scottish Gaelic
Scottish Gaelic is a language belonging to the Goidelic branch of Insular Celtic languages
3 and is mostly spoken in Scotland by about 69,000 speakers (
NRS, 2022), who exhibit a considerable degree of diatopical variation in their speech. In order to clarify the discussion concerning verbal nouns in this language, an introductory typological overview of some of its most relevant phonological and morphosyntactic features is included here. The most distinctive phonological feature of Celtic languages may be the existence of an elaborate system of initial mutations, which entail the alteration of the initial phoneme of words. More specifically for Scottish Gaelic, the most common type of mutation is lenition, which involves the softening of the initial consonant of a word—often marked orthographically by the insertion of an “h” in spelling (e.g.,
bòrd ‘table’ →
bhòrd)—in a variety of morphosyntactic contexts, such as after the vocative particle, the article in some cases, certain possessive pronouns, and specific prepositions, particles, adverbs, numerals, and adjectives, among others.
According to conventional morphological typology, Scottish Gaelic is considered a mildly synthetic, largely fusional, language, since, while it now has a relatively low morpheme-to-word ratio and a fairly regular morphology, in the past its verb forms have included a number of inflectional affixes expressing different grammatical meanings. Also, there are now instances of inflected, fused, or conjugated prepositions, which have historically developed from the contraction of a preposition with a personal pronoun (i.e., prepositional pronoun) or with a possessive (i.e., prepositional possessive):
(1) | Cha | chaidilinn | gu | math-san | taigh-tughaidh |
| neg | sleep.cond.dep.1sg4 | adv | good in.the.dat | house-thatched.dat |
| aca | rè | mo | shaor-làithean | samhraidh.5 |
| at.3pl | during | 1sg.poss | free-day.gen.pl | summer.gen |
| ‘I would not sleep well in their thatched house during my summer holidays.’6 |
Some of the words contained in this sentence reflect the previously synthetic nature of Scottish Gaelic. One example is the verbal dependent form
chaidilinn, which is composed of the verbal root
caidil7—this verb appeared in Old Irish
8 as
co-tlud, which is formed by a prepositional preverb meaning ‘with’ and a verbal root meaning ‘sleep’ (
Calder, 1923, p. 197)—and the suffix-
inn, which expresses the first person singular in conditional. The formation of verbal forms by adding pronominal suffixes to a verbal stem was common in Old Irish (
Thurneysen, 1946/1980, pp. 455–460), but this method gradually gave way to a more analytical procedure. Consequently, in Modern Scottish Gaelic, personal pronouns are expressed as independent forms, rather than by means of verbal endings.
9 Other morphological properties of Scottish Gaelic are: the distinction made between the masculine and feminine genders—a neuter gender once existed but has now disappeared, the existence of a four-way case distinction (nominative-accusative, dative, genitive, and vocative)
10, the presence of inflected, fused, or conjugated prepositions, the distinction between independent and dependent verb forms, the existence of an impersonal verb form, and the use of ablaut as a morphological device to mark grammatical distinctions in terms of number in nouns, tense in verbs, and degree in adjectives.
With respect to word order, Scottish Gaelic tends to have the tensed verb in clause-initial position—after preverbal particles indicating subordination, illocutionary force, and negation in dependent, interrogative, and negative sentences
11, although it is also possible to arrange a non-verbal constituent in a preverbal position for pragmatic purposes, as an epiphenomenon of information structure. As regards the parameter referred to as argument-type, Scottish Gaelic may be considered a lexical-argument language now, as the overt lexical nominal phrases are the true arguments of the predicate. It is, likewise, a dependent-marking language because all grammatical relations are coded in nominal phrases—which can be morphologically unmarked and which occur in the common case, or marked as dative or genitive, rather than within the verb. Scottish Gaelic is an instance of a right-branching language owing to the fact that it tends to place dependents after heads (i.e., it has prepositions, and the nouns are commonly followed by adjectives, although nominal objects may precede or follow their verbs depending on the type of construction). In terms of alignment, this language can be said to exhibit a nominative-accusative alignment, as, in the early stages of the language, the subjects of intransitive verbs were treated like the subjects of transitive verbs and were therefore distinguished from the objects of transitive verbs in basic clause constructions.
12 Finally, like the other Celtic languages, Scottish Gaelic makes use of two non-finite verbal forms, namely the verbal adjective and the verbal noun (or verb-noun). Regarding the first non-finite form, the verbal adjective, it suffices to note that it descends from the old past participle found in Old Irish. It was declined as an adjective and had verbal features, such as voice and, to a certain extent, tense (
Thurneysen, 1946/1980, pp. 441–443;
Russell, 1995, pp. 258–259), and is used today to express a passive meaning and perfect aspect in a specific passive-like construction:
(2) | Tha | an | leabhar | sgrìobhte | mu thràth. | | |
| be.pres | the | book | write.va | already | | |
| ‘The book is already written.’ | | |
The second form, the verbal noun, will be discussed in more detail in the following sections, as it constitutes the main focus of this study due to its ambiguous nature.
6. Discussion
An analysis of grammatical contexts involving verbal nouns in Scottish Gaelic shows a complex interplay of nominal and verbal characteristics, thereby justifying the continued debate surrounding their categorical classification. Further evidence would indicate that, while, in certain contexts, the verbal noun is either nominal or verbal, in other contexts this is less clear-cut, owing either to exceptions or because the context reflects properties of both categories. This therefore highlights the absence of a definitive boundary between them.
Thus, certain contexts allow for a straightforward identification of verbal nouns as either nominal or verbal. The clearest nominal contexts are those in which verbal nouns function as arguments of predicates (3–5), show distinctions in case (6–8), gender, and number (9–12), appear with determiners and numerals (13 & 14), require possessive pronouns instead of personal pronouns to express their arguments (26 & 27), and bear the genitive case when functioning as the complements of other nouns (21 & 22). Additional features reinforcing their nominal profile include the position of possessives (46) and PP complements (48), the formation of compound nouns (23 & 24), and their co-occurrence with the light verb dèan ‘do’ in periphrastic constructions (49 & 50).
Similarly, a number of contexts show the verbal nature of verbal nouns. These include their prototypical association with eventive semantics—such as actions, processes, and states (54 & 55), their morphological divergence from deverbal nouns, and their use as the non-finite complements of modal verbs and in impersonal constructions involving nominal or adjectival predicates (66 & 68). Other clear verbal properties are illustrated by the fact that verbal nouns also serve as the sole predicate in periphrastic aspectual constructions (69–73)—despite the lenition effects that possessives have on the verbal noun in this context—and passive constructions (75 & 76), and occur in control, raising, exceptional case marking (ECM), and causative constructions (77–80). Finally, other clearly verbal contexts include their behaviour in cleft constructions (81–84), the substitutability of verbal noun clauses with finite clauses (85–87), and their presence as a converb (96) in adverbial subordinate clauses.
On the other hand, a substantial number of contexts resist such a straightforward classification. For instance, regarding the morphology of the verbal noun, although it is evident that its root is clearly verbal, its inflection is unquestionably nominal. Verbal nouns may allow both adjectival and adverbial modification, which adds ambiguity (15 & 16 vs. 64 & 65). It is also unclear whether the positioning of the complements of verbal nouns can help determine whether these elements are more nominal or verbal in character, considering that their complements may either precede or follow the verbal noun in different constructions (63 vs. 18–20). Additionally, the case assigned to NP complements varies: while the genitive case is still often used in the expression of the progressive, prospective, and purposive aspect (18 & 20)—and this occurs usually when the object is definite, many constructions today favour the use of the basic or common case (63). Also, the co-occurrence of verbal nouns with relative clauses (30) is not frequently attested in contemporary usage. Moreover, the fact that verbal nouns are negated differently from finite verbs (31 & 32) does not necessarily indicate a nominal nature, as similar phenomena are observed cross-linguistically in non-finite clauses; hence, this does not appear to be sufficient grounds for precluding the interpretation of the verbal noun as retaining verbal properties in this context. Likewise, although prepositions typically select for nominal complements (42–44), it is plausible that in these cases the complement is the entire clause containing the verbal noun, rather than the verbal noun itself, which retains a predicative function. Furthermore, the lack of dependent/independent formal distinctions (36), a hallmark of finite verbs in Scottish Gaelic, should not automatically be taken as evidence of nominal status, as such distinctions could well be tied to tense (the imperative form does not show this distinction either). The absence of voice alternations (38) also need not imply nominal status; rather, it may reflect one particular language-specific strategy for expressing the passive voice in Scottish Gaelic, one that diverges significantly from the garden-variety passive construction observed, for example, in English. Additional areas of ambiguity include the use of reflexive pronouns with verbal nouns (41)—a phenomenon also attested with adverbs and adjectives—and the presence of obligatory and unambiguous arguments (28 & 29), a property not exclusive to verbs, as many nouns also generally have arguments with an unambiguous syntactic and semantic function. Finally, the distinction between prepositions and aspectual particles (90–93)—apart from a few well-established cases such as aig vs. ag/a’, ann, and even air in progressive, stative, and perfect constructions, respectively—is not always a reliable way of determining diagnostic purpose.
In summary, it seems clear that the behaviour of verbal nouns in Scottish Gaelic straddles the traditional divide between noun and verb and, rather than slipping neatly into a single category, verbal nouns have a dual nature that depends heavily on the grammatical contexts in which they appear.
While it is true that this type of confusion may be more prevalent in Celtic languages than in other branches of the IE family, due to the fact that Celtic languages possess only a single non-finite form—the verbal noun, leaving the verbal adjective aside, the difficulty in distinguishing between nominal and verbal properties in non-finite forms also occurs across other language families, as with the gerund in English (
Quirk et al., 1985, p. 1291;
Huddleston, 2002, pp. 1220–1222;
Aarts, 2007, pp. 142–144;
Malchukov, 2019;
Keizer, 2023, pp. 186–187). Indeed, in many languages, the same non-finite form may appear in different syntactic constructions, reflecting a distinctly lexical nature. This is the case with the Italian infinitive, which can function either as a subject or an object (e.g.,
Fumare fa male ‘Smoking is bad’) and can also serve as the sole lexical predicate in constructions involving modal verbs (e.g.,
Lui deve studiare oggi ‘He must study today’). It is also possible for two distinct non-finite forms to appear within the same syntactic context, such as the infinitive and the gerund in English when functioning as the subject or object of a sentence (e.g.,
I started to do/doing).
The root of this problem could be that, at least now, the distinction among non-finite forms is primarily based on their morphological characteristics (e.g., -ar/-er/-ir for infinitives, -ando/-endo for gerunds, -nte for present participles, and -ado/-ido for past participles in Spanish), rather than on the verbal, nominal, adjectival, or adverbial function they currently perform or may have performed in the past. Although it is not possible to trace the original morphology of verbal nouns further back than Proto-Indo-European, the solution to this categorial problem may be found through an analysis of the historical development of non-finite forms and the diachronic developments they have undergone up to the present day, not only within the Celtic languages but also across other languages, and more specifically, within those branches of the IE family most closely related to Celtic.
As has been widely acknowledged (
Shields, 1992;
Beekes, 1995;
Szemerényi, 1996;
Clackson, 2007), the reconstruction of the verbal system constitutes the most intricate aspect of PIE linguistics, owing both to its internal complexity and the considerable dialectal variation that distinguishes verbal morphology from other major categories. Notwithstanding this difficulty, there is a degree of scholarly consensus that the infinitives in PIE were formerly verbal nouns or action nominals. Nevertheless, it remains difficult to determine with certainty whether they were originally either nouns incorporated into the verbal system or were formed by attaching nominal morphology to a verbal root (
Zeuss, 1871;
Windisch, 1878;
Delbrück, 1893–1900;
Brugmann, 1886–1900/1897–1916;
Pedersen, 1909–1913;
Vendryes, 1910;
Lewis & Pedersen, 1931;
Disterheft, 1980,
1981). In addition, this protolanguage also made use of various participles—which may also have originated from a verbal root—that appear to have been adjectives assimilated into the verbal system, such as the present participle, the verbal adjective, which was semantically similar to a past participle, the gerundive, which was used to indicate need, obligation or possibility, and the absolutive (also referred to as a gerund but in a different sense), which had an adverbial function.
New forms gradually emerged from the ancient categories, acquiring non-personal verbal functions. Thus, subsequently, the infinitive constructions found in the classical IE languages appear to descend from fixed case forms of PIE verbal nouns (
Buck, 1933;
Hahn, 1966;
Rosén, 1981;
Beekes, 1995;
Sihler, 1995). For example, the Classical Latin and Ancient Greek infinitives are believed to have developed from PIE
s-stem verbal nouns marked for the locative or dative case. Similarly, the Latin gerund (as well as the supine, which was employed to express purpose or to complement adjectives) is thought to have originated from the same element, although it was used in all nominal cases, excluding the nominative, which remained the domain of the infinitive. Verbal adjectives such as the gerundive, which expressed necessity, obligation, or propriety regarding the execution of an action, and participles, which occurred in the active, middle, and passive voice, are also frequently used. However, unlike the infinitive and the gerund, these forms adopted an adjectival morphology (
Whitney, 1924;
Sihler, 1995).
45Over time, the extensive inventory of non-finite forms of Latin was reduced to three primary types in the subsequent Romance languages: two hybrid categories, namely the infinitive and the gerund, which combine nominal and verbal features, and one mainly adjectival (although also adverbial and verbal) form, namely the participle, which appears in two different forms: the present and past participle. In most Romance languages, the functions of the gerund and the present participle eventually merged, with one of the forms emerging as the prominent variant—it is mainly used to express the progressive aspect and adverbial subordination—and the other being relegated to highly sporadic uses—as is the case with the evolution of the old present participle in -ns/-nt (in the genitive)—as an adjective in many of these languages.
The Germanic languages developed the same three principal non-finite forms, also fusing the original gerund and present participle forms, thus introducing significant ambiguity in determining the syntactic and semantic function of each (
Ringe, 2006). For instance, although the infinitive commonly serves as the subject or object of a verb and as the complement of a preposition or noun, it is also widely used to express various aspectual distinctions, such as the prospective or predictive, and to function as the sole predicate in constructions involving modal verbs and impersonal clauses with adjectival or nominal predicates. A comparable ambiguity arises from the coalescence of the gerund and the present participle, now a single category that may serve a verbal role (as in the progressive aspect), an adjectival role (as a noun modifier), or an adverbial role (functioning as a converb in adverbial subordinate clauses) in many modern Germanic languages. The past participle presents a similar challenge, as it may act as a verb (in the perfect aspect or in passive constructions) or as an adjective (when modifying nouns).
Finally, the Celtic languages appear to have undergone fewer changes than other IE branches with regard to the evolution of non-finite verb forms, as they have retained the categories of the verbal noun and the verbal adjective
46.
In light of this diachronic explanation, it is reasonable to assume that the reduction and convergence of non-finite forms appears to be one reason to explain the confusion surrounding the identification of their lexical category. This issue is, of course, even more pronounced in the Celtic languages, where a single non-finite form like the verbal noun can serve a nominal, verbal, and even adjectival or adverbial function.
Another reason, which may account for the hybrid character of certain non-finite forms, is the presumed fuzzy nature of categories. If more information were available regarding the origin of verbal nouns prior to PIE, two different hypotheses could be reasonably proposed. Firstly, if verbal nouns derived from verbs, they might still be reinterpreted and reanalysed as nouns when their function is more closely aligned with a reference to actions or states, rather than with predication, that is the description of the event in which the participants are involved. Secondly, by contrast, if verbal nouns were originally nominal in nature, they could also be reinterpreted as verbs when their function is more closely associated with the depiction of specific events rather than with an explicit reference to the participants engaged in those events. In either case, this issue appears to invite a broader reflection on whether it is the verbal noun itself that should be regarded as a mixed or hybrid category, or whether such hybridity is more appropriately attributed to the fuzziness displayed by the categories of verb and noun when considered from a more diachronic perspective and even from a more conceptual standpoint.
With this in mind, the issue of categorization may not be fully resolved, but it can at least be simplified if, like
Croft (
1990,
2001,
2007), we consider that the two core pragmatic functions, reference and predication, are only prototypically aligned with the two major semantic classes, object and action—or, more accurately entity and event, and, consequently, with the two primary lexical categories, the noun and the verb
47. Thus, while the relationship between entity and reference, on the one hand, and between event and predication, on the other, seems to be grounded in basic cognitive processes, as objects typically serve as referents and actions or states are primarily conveyed through predicates in such a way that both reference and predication underpin propositional content, allowing utterances to express states, actions, or processes as well as the participants involved in them, it is entirely possible for an entity like ‘beer’ not to be referential (e.g., ‘He drinks beer’) and for an event like ‘smoke’ to be non-predicating (e.g., ‘To smoke is bad’). Even more commonly, each of the two lexical categories, noun and verb, may be capable of fulfilling either of the two pragmatic functions. For instance, a noun such as ‘dog’ can function referentially (e.g., ‘My dog is good’) or predicatively (e.g., ‘It is a dog’), and a verb such as ‘read’ can serve a predicative function (e.g., I read a book) or a referential function (e.g., ‘Reading is funny’).
This perspective may suggest that, at an early stage of language development
48, words emerged, independently of any fixed lexical category
49, as symbols—their sounds or letters signify only by cultural convention since the link between the sign and the signified could have been arbitrary—standing for both the entities and the events in which they are involved. Their subsequent classification into specific lexical categories would thus depend on the specific pragmatic function being expressed, which in turn necessitated a corresponding syntactic construction. In accordance with
Haspelmath (
2007)’s scepticism about the existence of pre-established grammatical categories and their purported semantic basis (
Haspelmath, 2023, p. 35), these source categories may then have originated not as fixed lexical classes, but rather as conceptual categories and, while in contemporary grammar each of these lexical categories tends to be associated with particular semantic properties and core pragmatic functions—namely noun with entity and reference and verb with event and predication, these correlations remain clearly distinct only in the most prototypical cases, which obviously do not include non-finite forms. This situation therefore appears to suggest that, in practice, the boundary between the categories of noun and verb is often blurred in non-finite forms, suggesting that the most defining feature of their interrelationship is their gradient nature and that the distinction is even less evident in languages with a more limited number of non-finite forms, as is the case with the Celtic languages. Thus, the gradience observed in Celtic verbal nouns may in fact be an epiphenomenon, reflecting a blurred boundary between two lexical categories, noun and verb, due to the difficulty in distinguishing between the functions of reference and predication in certain syntactic contexts. This gradience has been inherited, in a particularly salient way, by the hybrid category known as the verbal noun, and the fact that it typically appears in a single, morphologically undifferentiated form in Celtic languages further complicates the identification of its lexical status.
In light of the lack of early historical evidence, the only viable approach to understanding its lexical status and functional behaviour lies in examining and analysing it synchronically within the specific grammatical contexts in which it occurs. Regardless of whether their origin was verbal or nominal, it is evident that verbal nouns in the Celtic languages are employed across a significantly broader range of syntactic contexts than might be expected for either prototypical nouns or verbs, as they occur in environments where PIE and late IE would have used a genuine verbal noun, various types of participles, the absolutive or gerund, and the gerundive, each of which has different properties. Accordingly, the position of the verbal noun within the nominal-verbal continuum in the Celtic languages can be understood to vary across time and constructions
50. This assumption that this category may be construction-specific and even language-specific is therefore consistent with
Cristofaro’s (
2009) hypothesis that accounts for the cross-constructional and cross-linguistic diversity of individual categories and relations and is also aligned with a constructional view of categorization (
Croft (
2001);
Goldberg (
2006); among others). Accordingly, categories may be epiphenomenal, insofar as they depend on constructions, which are considered to be primitives, and word classes are defined by their distributional properties in different constructions.
On the one hand, it is important to bear in mind that that the properties of many contexts are currently in a state of flux, for example the grammaticalization of some prepositions as particles, the shift from possessives to personal pronouns, the case assigned to some NP objects, and the positioning of other NP objects, etc. This would suggest that the position occupied by these contexts within the continuum between clearly nominal and clearly verbal domains may not be fixed. Consequently, this could entail a reanalysis of the properties of the verbal noun in the future. In this light, the analysis of contexts involving verbal nouns in Scottish Gaelic may be better understood as part of an ongoing process of reanalysis, rather than as evidence of a completed categorial classification. Hence, the evolution of these constructions and the future categorization of verbal nouns remain subject to diachronic empirical investigation.
On the other hand, in the case of Modern Scottish Gaelic particularly, if these contexts were to be arranged along a continuum, contexts would be clearly nominal at one extreme and clearly verbal at the other. The former would include those contexts when the verbal noun functions as a subject or object, when it exhibits gender, number, and case distinctions, when it is modified by determiners and numerals, when it requires possessive pronouns instead of personal pronouns to express the arguments, and when it bears the genitive case as a complement to another noun. The latter would encompass contexts when the verbal noun unquestionably expresses an event, when it is different from a deverbal noun, and when it occurs in aspectual constructions or as a complement of modal verbs and adjectival or nominal predicates, etc. Accordingly, a differentiation between verbal nouns in their nominal and verbal uses in these contexts would seem logical.
However, it is arguably within the intermediate zone that the intersective gradience of the verbal noun becomes most evident. It is precisely in this middle ground that the analytical challenges are most pronounced, as this area involves hybrid contexts that oscillate between nominal and verbal syntactic behaviour. As a result, the verbal noun emerges as a flexible part of speech in such liminal cases and resists a clear-cut classification, as neither its morphological features nor its syntactic distribution provide definitive clues to its function or categorial status. Thus, this case of the convergence of nominal and verbal properties in these instances renders the verbal noun a genuinely hybrid category, as it includes contexts in which it is not possible to ascertain whether it functions as a noun or a verb. In summary, the current difficulty in determining whether the category traditionally referred to as the verbal noun in Celtic languages and predominantly exhibiting nominal or verbal properties may be attributed to the primordial categorial indeterminacy of words and, subsequently, to the inherent gradience of the categories from which it historically derives, primarily the noun and the verb, as well as the convergence of a wide range of both nominal and verbal functions into a single non-finite form. This illustrates the fact that verbal nouns are a graded, rather than a discrete, category whose categorical identification can only be achieved through the analysis of each specific grammatical context in which they appear, taking into account the fact that the properties of the construction may vary diachronically and across languages.
7. Conclusions
Non-finite constructions in Scottish Gaelic are intriguing because they use a specific non-finite verbal form traditionally referred to in Celtic linguistics as the verbal noun, which, as the term implies, has both verbal and nominal properties. Accordingly, the categorial status of verbal nouns in the Celtic languages—specifically, whether they are fundamentally nominal or verbal—has long been the subject of extensive debate within the field of Celtic linguistics.
The present study has sought to provide an analysis of the properties of the verbal noun in Modern Scottish Gaelic, adopting a functional-typological and multidimensional perspective. This approach emphasizes a holistic examination of this distinctive feature of Celtic languages, addressing the syntactic, semantic, and pragmatic dimensions of the constructions in which this hybrid category appears. It cannot be denied that the analysis of the contexts in which the verbal noun currently appears in Scottish Gaelic offered in this study reveals a rather ambiguous situation, insofar as it does not allow us to identify the lexical nature of this category in the language clearly, except in a few cases. This implies that, as with verbal nouns in other Celtic languages, it remains impossible to determine whether the verbal noun is nominal or verbal in nature. However, this should not be seen as a disappointment, nor should it be regarded as an impediment to gaining a deeper understanding of the language. Rather, it may be interpreted as a confirmation of an evident reality. Thus, it makes little sense to attempt to assign exclusively nominal or verbal properties to this category, as it has inherited its versatile character from the categorial indeterminacy of word classes and, subsequently, from the fuzzy nature of verbs and nouns, so its categorial properties depend on the specific grammatical context in which it occurs. Additionally, these properties may also be subject to diachronic variation and may differ across languages.
With the historical information on the Celtic languages available to us, and even their most distant ancestor, PIE, we can only hypothesize as to whether the verbal noun originally belonged to the nominal or the verbal system. Subsequently, and as with other non-finite verb forms across languages, it gradually came to be used in a wide range of constructions in which it could acquire properties typically associated with verbs, nouns, and even adjectives and adverbs. The issue, however, is that, while it is generally straightforward to correlate many types of non-finite forms with specific lexical categories, the participle is often equated with a verbal adjective and the converb with a verb of adverbial nature, for example, forms such as the infinitive and the gerund resist such correlation, as they frequently have both nominal and verbal uses. This is especially controversial in the Celtic languages, where a single non-finite form, namely the verbal noun, is used to cover a range of functions typically expressed through the infinitive and gerund, and even the present participle—as in the case of the progressive aspect or when it is used as a modifier of another noun or a main verb, and the past participle—as in the passive construction and perfect aspect—in other languages.
This complex behaviour shows that identifying the verbal or nominal character of this category is essentially unnecessary, as its status appears to depend on the construction in which it occurs. Rather, this study highlights the need for a nuanced, construction-based approach when examining the use of verbal nouns in Scottish Gaelic. Consequently, an analysis of their syntactic distribution might be more reasonable, since what may constitute nominal or verbal is usage rather than the verbal noun itself. An explicit and systematic distinction between the constructions in which the verbal noun participates and a description of its function in each of them are therefore necessary.
As a result of the analysis of the distribution of verbal nouns in Modern Scottish Gaelic offered in this study, it is evident that the verbal noun has gradually and unquestionably become a highly versatile syntactic constituent since it can now behave either like a noun or a verb in different grammatical environments. However, it has also become evident that a distinction between verbal nouns used either nominally or verbally can be drawn only in a limited number of contexts. The main challenge therefore lies in the fact that not all of the contexts in which the verbal noun appears allow for a clear identification of whether the verbal noun functions as a noun or as a verb. It is precisely in these contexts that the intersective gradience between these two categories—that is, the intersectionality between the properties of the nominal and verbal categories—becomes most apparent. The two categories of noun and verb have traditionally served to represent syntactically the correlation between the semantic classes of entity and event, and the pragmatic functions of reference and predication. However, due to the evident intersectionality between reference and predication in some grammatical contexts and to the convergence of non-finite forms into a single form in Scottish Gaelic, it is only possible to ascertain whether a verbal noun functions as a noun (converging on the class of nouns) or as a verb (converging on the class of verbs) in contexts where the categories of noun and verb clearly correlate with their corresponding semantic class and pragmatic function, but, apart from these prototypical instances, the inherent hybridity of the verbal noun becomes apparent in the other syntactic environments. This provides compelling evidence that, given that a clear-cut distinction between nominal and verbal characteristics is problematical, we should analyse constructions including verbal nouns as a continuum from clearly nominal contexts to clearly verbal contexts with intermediate contexts where the twofold character of the verbal noun is evident and, consequently reflects an instance of intersective gradience. In summary, it is in these intermediate contexts that this hybrid non-finite form reflects the intersection between the two word classes of noun and verb, making it possible to confirm that categories are inherently gradient in nature and that gradience is a pervasive phenomenon.