Next Article in Journal
Establishment of Transboundary Partnerships in an International Climate Adaptation Project
Previous Article in Journal
Are Internally Displaced People (IDPs) Safe? A Geospatial Analysis of Climate Vulnerability for IDP Communities in Tacloban, Philippines
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Review

Climate Constitutionalisation in Europe—After KlimaSeniorinnen and the ICJ’s Advisory Opinion

University of Amsterdam, Nieuwe Achtergracht 166, 1018 WV Amsterdam, The Netherlands
Climate 2025, 13(9), 186; https://doi.org/10.3390/cli13090186
Submission received: 13 August 2025 / Revised: 25 August 2025 / Accepted: 27 August 2025 / Published: 11 September 2025
(This article belongs to the Section Policy, Governance, and Social Equity)

Abstract

Several European courts have vested mitigation obligations with a hierarchically higher legal rank than ordinary state action. They construe these obligations from human rights in combination with international commitments and climate science. This phenomenon is here called ‘climate constitutionalisation’. In addition, we see an increasing escalation of climate cases to the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) and we now have the advisory opinion of the International Court of Justice (ICJ). Climate constitutionalisation in Europe is an incremental process of replication and reiteration. It can only be understood by studying the developing body of national case law in the context European and international law. Studying general emission reduction cases against states in Europe, this paper traces how non-enforceable legal norms, political commitments, and climate science are used to interpret binding and enforceable human rights norms. It reflects on the present and future consequences of the ECtHR’s decision in KlimaSeniorinnen and ICJ’s Advisory Opinion on climate obligations. The paper argues that Europe’s multilayered legal and judicial landscape strengthens climate constitutionalisation and herewith deepens the fault line between the judiciary and the elected institutions. Europe’s openness towards international law facilitates this process. The paper then offers tentative normative justifications for this process.

1. Introduction

Judges in Europe (denoting the geographical area where national law, European Union law, and the ECHR are applicable partially overlapping) have repeatedly relied on international political and legal commitments in combination with climate science in order to give substance to human rights norms. As a result, they have established climate mitigation obligations that enjoy a hierarchically higher legal rank than state climate action, be it legislative or executive. This process is here called ‘climate constitutionalisation’.
Climate constitutionalisation through general emission reduction cases against states is more strongly visible in Europe than elsewhere (by way of comparison: [1] on Asia and [2] on the Americas). This is the case for three reasons: first, Europe is a geographical area with a comparatively high number of climate cases in this category [3] [4] (p. 29–30) [5]; second, a considerable share of these cases has been successful [4] (p 29–30) [6,7,8,9,10,11,12,13,14,15,16]; and third, Europe’s multilayered landscape of national law, European Union law, and the European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR), with a comparatively open attitude towards international law facilitates this process. This process may—to denote its distinctiveness—be called ‘European climate constitutionalisation’.
This paper traces multilevel climate constitutionalisation and its countertendencies in Europe. It unearths how climate litigation vests international commitments and climate science with de facto constitutional effects capable of imposing lawfulness requirements on states. A framework of norms that is—at least at times—able to constrain state actions logically makes a claim to be prevailing, i.e., higher-ranking than ordinary state action. This justifies speaking of ‘constitutionalisation’.
It focusses on strategic climate litigation (SCL) in Europe brought against states and aiming for general emission reduction (mitigation) [17,18]—also called ‘systemic cases’ [19] and ‘framework cases’ [20]. For simplicity, the abbreviation SCL is here used for this type of cases. SCL so defined is distinct from climate-related litigation predominantly driven by the interests of the litigating party (not strategic), against companies (not states), pertaining to specific sectors or implementation measures (not general), or aiming for adaptation measures or damages (not mitigation).
The paper examines SCL in European jurisdictions that all meet in law and practice (more or less) the requirements of liberal democracies, human rights, the rule of law, and separation of powers. The geographical focus allows engaging with Europe’s multilayered legal and judicial landscape. In this landscape, three layers of law interact and interlock: first, regional human rights protection under the ECHR; second, EU law regulating a broad range of climate-relevant policies and offering rights protection under the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights (CFR); and, third, national law regulating an infinite number of issues, implementing EU law, and offering in most jurisdictions (constitutional) human rights protection [21]. Because of its primacy and direct effect, EU law enjoys an elevated level of effectiveness in the national legal orders of the Member States, as compared to international law [22] (pp. 1–14). At the same time, the EU, including through the CFR, is committed to consistent interpretation with the ECHR and international law in general [21,22] (p. 189). This is a constellation, in which the ECHR, international law, and EU law can deploy great relevance in national litigation.
This paper shows that the process of creating norms capable of restraining states’ (in)action takes place incrementally, non-linear, and triggers countertendencies. The paper also highlights that this process benefits from a high potential for replication because of overlapping legal norms that bind all European states. These norms are EU law, the ECHR and international law, as well as political and legal commitments made by all European states. The universal nature of climate science also supports this process. The paper concludes that the actual and future constitutionalising consequences of the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR)’s ruling in KlimaSeniorinnen and the International Court of Justice (ICJ)’s Advisory Opinion can hardly be overestimated within Europe [16,23,24].
It adopts a qualitative approach, combining legal doctrinal analysis with constitutional contextual reflections. It is based on an examination of nineteen SCL cases in the public database on Global Climate Change Litigation that have been decided in at least one instance on 30 April 2025, ranging from Urgenda in 2015 to the Finnish Climate Case II in 2025 [25], [6,7,8,9,10,11,12,13,14,15,16] (successful), [26,27,28,29,30,31,32,33,34,35,36,37] (unsuccessful). Urgenda (NL) [6,7,8], Neubauer (DE) [10], Klimaatzaak (BE) [13,14], KlimaSeniorinnen (ECtHR) [16] and the ICJ’s Advisory Opinion [24] are identified as landmark cases for constitutionalisation and discussed in greater detail, while the other cases are mentioned in support of specific arguments, either in the main text or in the footnotes.
First, this paper gives a nuanced account of climate constitutionalisation in Europe (descriptive contribution). Second, it argues that the interaction between the different legal layers within Europe are particularly suitable to advance climate constitutionalisation (analytical contribution). Third, it reflects on whether, in light of well-documented wide-spread failures of states to take adequate climate mitigation measures [38,39,40], climate constitutionalisation gives us some ambivalent hope that judges may meaningfully contribute to climate decision-making in liberal democracies (normative contribution).
Section 2 explains how this paper uses the term constitutionalisation, emphasising its incremental nature and countertendencies. Section 3 identifies the central relevance of human rights, international legal norms and political commitments, and climate science in climate constitutionalisation in Europe. Section 4 turns to the ECtHR’s landmark case of KlimaSeniorinnen and the ICJ’s Advisory Opinion as additional legal layers reinforcing this process. Section 5 reflects on replicability of arguments and outcomes, as well as countertendencies. Section 6 offers justifications for climate constitutionalisation. Section 7 concludes.

2. Constitutionalisation

2.1. Prevailing Legal Yardsticks

The literature departs from different, partially overlapping understandings of ‘constitutionalism’ and ‘constitutionalisation’ [41,42,43]. This paper uses the term constitutionalisation for two reasons: because it focusses on the process rather than the outcome, and because its first contribution is descriptive and analytical followed by more limited normative reflections. Constitutionalisation denotes here the ‘process by which political actors become regulated’ through ordering by means of legally binding and prevailing norms [42] (p. 16). It is ‘the attempt to subject [via judicial review] all governmental action within a designated field to the structures, processes, principles, and values of a “constitution” [41] (p. 47).’ Literature on ‘environmental constitutionalism’ engages with codified and judicial norms, as well as structural or procedural principles responding to environmental issues [44,45] [46] (p. 187). This paper focusses more narrowly on judicial norms and climate mitigation. ‘Climate constitutionalisation’ here refers to a process of establishing and consolidating prevailing mitigation norms through judicial interpretation that limit the lawful scope for state action—compare [43] (broader (not limited to mitigation or litigation) and narrower (focused on the development of international law)).
This insulation of the objective of climate mitigation from ordinary politics comes with similar challenges as other constitutionalisation, namely that it may appear ‘essentially antidemocratic’ as it does not rely on majoritarian decision-making and could therefore be seen as ‘remov[ing] certain decisions from the democratic process’ [47] (p. 196). It hence needs to be justified on other than majoritarian grounds. Sam Bookman instructively distinguishes three ways in which judges justify prevailing legal yardsticks that set boundaries on majoritarian decisions of democratically elected institutions: liberal-conservative, technocratic, and transformative justifications [44]. The liberal-conservative justification emphasises that ‘environmental matters fall within existing conceptions and traditions of mainstream constitutional theory’ [44] (introduction). The technocratic justification argues that ‘environmental governance requires a high degree of expertise, which is beyond the capacity of electoral majorities’ [44]. The transformative justification purports that ‘environmental crises require fundamental changes in interrelated social, political, and economic systems, and constitutions can embody the necessary legal and aspirational framework for such transformation’ [44]. The three arguments are not mutually exclusive. Throughout this paper, I highlight how courts use these justifications in SCL.

2.2. Incrementalism, Entrenchment, and Countertendencies

The incremental nature and relevance of legal constitutionalisation becomes apparent in Duncan Kennedy’s general remark about one of the ‘more powerful conventions of the legal argument’, namely, that ‘arguments proceed, both within a given case and over a series of cases, from the more general choices to the more particular, arguing and then re-arguing, rather than debating the merits of a point on the continuum versus all the other points on the continuum’ [48] (p. 101). Few legal scholars dispute that legal reasoning is a process of choosing between alternatives. The stakes differ depending on whether one goes down one path or the other. The quote highlights that the process of interpreting and creating norms is prone to unfold in a path-dependent way. This highlights the relevance not only of the outcome of the individual case but also of developing a vocabulary, i.e., a stock of legal concepts. This vocabulary becomes comprehensible beyond the individual case, frames the argumentation of litigants and judges, and may be replicated in future cases.
Interpretations by higher instance, regional and international courts, as well as references to constitutional norms have a particularly authoritative value and entrenching effect in this process of carving out paths for legal arguments [49] (p. 5), [50]. These interpretations create norms, which are taken as a point of reference in the judicial processes in lower or national courts. Judges can distinguish their own case from these norms, but they cannot substantively change or simply ignore them. Emphasising the coherent (‘path-dependent’) development of law based on the entrenching effect of higher or regional courts’ decisions draws on a ‘liberal-conservative’ justification. This justification goes to the heart of traditional judicial reasoning, which usually claims coherence with pre-existing legal norms and in this way draws legitimacy from the legal order as a whole [51].
However, courts do not only advance but also restrict constitutionalisation. They do so by limiting the scope of higher ranking domestic norms or depriving (international or regional) norms of their effect within the domestic legal order [52]. These are countertendencies of constitutionalisation, often justified by deference to elected institutions or ongoing democratic decision-making. It is a defining characteristic of the judiciary that it may only act when litigants file a case; however, when this is the case judges must say what the law is [53] (Chapter 3), [54,55]. While they may decline jurisdiction, doing so also contributes to the understanding of the law. It determines what the law does or does not govern. This explains how litigation necessarily develops the law. Also, unsuccessful cases may for example contribute to strengthening the understanding that the climate crisis is a justiciable human rights matter. Importantly, all cases contribute to a better understanding of the legal opportunity structures and guide litigants in future cases [56] (p. 13), [57].
So far in Europe, most judges have accepted justiciability of climate issues, so countertendencies are largely limited to specific arguments—by contrast [58]. However, these arguments also raise the spectre of a scenario in which judges see themselves structurally unable to exercise jurisdiction. This is a scenario in which the polity cannot uphold its constitutional promise even when legally binding norms are violated.

3. Countering Governance Failures with Human Rights, International Law, and Science

The governance failures to adequately address the climate crisis are widespread and well-documented [38,39,40]. However, one cannot discuss SCL without mentioning that it emerges in reaction to these governance failures. Often, SCL aims to demonstrate how these governance failures violate human rights [59].

3.1. Human Rights

Imposing limits to (in-)actions of democratically elected institutions based on human rights draws on a liberal-conservative justification. Entrusting the judiciary with this enabling and controlling function presupposes a considerable faith in the functioning of state institutions. Europe’s commitment to overlapping and cross-referential national and European human rights instruments is rooted in a shared—albeit increasingly challenged—commitment to liberal democracy. This commitment links democracy inextricably with the rule of law. In this environment, recourse to regional human rights norms enjoys exceptional potential for replicability and entrenchment.
Urgenda, the first ever successful case of SCL, was originally based on the unwritten duty of care under Dutch tort law, in combination with Articles 2 (right to life) and 8 (right to private and family life) ECHR [1,60]. In second and third instance [7,8], the courts based the unwritten duty of care directly on Articles 2 and 8 ECHR. All three instances obliged the state to reduce the overall emissions from its territory by the substantive minimum of 25% in 2020. Neither of these human rights provisions directly refers to the climate and Urgenda pioneered by interpreting them to entail a prevailing mitigation obligation. Human rights as legal grounds constitutionalised the issue and strengthened potential for replication. The Procurator General even directly explained his reasoning ‘[f]or the benefit of non-Dutch readers’ [61] (para 1.35). Both the ECtHR and the ICJ have since confirmed that the climate crisis is a human rights matter, with the ECtHR holding Article 8 ECHR (family life) applicable and the ICJ even finding a right to a healthy environment (see below).
The plaintiffs in the Belgian Klimaatzaak took Urgenda in the first instance as their blueprint and based their claim on civil liability in Article 1382 of the Belgian Civil Code in combination with Articles 2 and 8 ECHR [13,14]. In the first and second instance, the courts established both civil liability and a violation of the plaintiffs’ Convention rights. Klimaatzaak extensively referenced and literally cited, besides Urgenda, also the German Federal Constitutional Court’s (GFCC) Neubauer decision [14] (para 234). It is currently pending in final recourse before the Court of Cassation. Both Urgenda and Klimaatzaak concerned the rights of all citizens, rather than only rights of individual plaintiffs.
By contrast, an example of an individualised rights claim is the GFCC’s decision in Neubauer. This case reached the court under the constitutional complaint procedure and, in line with the requirements of that procedure, it dealt with the (alleged) violation of the constitutional rights of 45 individual persons from Germany, Bangladesh, and Nepal, while the complaints of two associations were dismissed as inapplicable. However, by relying among other things on a state objective in Article 20a German Constitution to protect the environment, the GFCC established a general future-oriented, intergenerational duty of care [10] (para 144 et seq). In other words, even within this individualized procedural setting, the Court took a community perspective, including the perspective of future generations.
A rights-based approach as opposed to other legal grounds formally gives equal emphasis to the rights of all humans, including underrepresented and disadvantaged individuals [62,63]. The climate crisis exacerbates inequalities not only between countries but also within countries, and affects very differently persons of different race, gender, and class [64] (pp. 15–34), [65], [66] (Chapter 6), [67]. In this light, human rights are one way of empowering each person rather than a heterogenous collective. However, besides being ill-suited to protect nature for its own sake, human rights usually require demonstrating an individualized violation. Individuals regularly find it difficult to satisfy the procedural requirements of having, for example, to demonstrate ‘victim status’ [16] (paras 478–488 and 507–520) or ‘individual and direct concern’ [68] (paras 33 et seq) [69] (paras 76–77) [70,71]. These legal requirements are characterized by the distinctiveness of the litigants’ harm. This stands in stark contrast to the fact that the climate crisis ‘threatens the world’s entire population’ [61]. Moreover, the strategic aspect of SCL is usually aimed at protecting a collective. This also stands in tension with the individualist human rights framing. Whether such collective claims are possible (as in Urgenda and Klimaatzaak) or whether only individuals can bring cases in their own right (Neubauer) depends on the standing requirements in the specific jurisdiction. When courts interpret standing requirements broadly, they usually rely on a transformative justification by emphasising the exceptionality of the climate crisis [10,16,72].

3.2. International (Climate) Law

At the heart of states’ international obligations in relation to the climate crisis is the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change (UNFCCC). The UNFCCC pursues the objective to stabilize the greenhouse gas concentrations in the atmosphere. A central instrument is the 2015 Paris Agreement adopted at COP21. Nationally Determined Contributions (NDCs) form the basis for countries to achieve the temperature goal of the Paris Agreement [73] (synthesis of 166 NDCs of 193 parties). These are the norms that national courts have so far relied on to impose emission reduction obligations on states. However, the ICJ clarified in its Advisory Opinion of 23 July 2025 that the different sources of international law rather than contradicting each other, inform each other and should be read together [24] (para. 410). It referred not only to a large number of environmental treaties but also to customary international law and discarded any attempt to see climate-related treaties as lex specialis.
In many SCL cases, judges explain in much detail how defendant states ratified and participated in the UNFCCC [74]. They usually emphasise the clarity of the political positions adopted at consecutive COPs and widespread and repeated support expressed for them. Urgenda illustrates an approach that several courts took; The Dutch Supreme Court emphasised that the UNFCCC’s relevance in two respects: First, the Court relied on the UNFCCC’s legal principles to interpret Articles 2 and 8 ECHR, i.e., the principle of common but differentiated responsibilities and respective capabilities (CBDR-RC) in the recitals and Art 3(1) UNFCCC and the precautionary principle in Article 3(3) UNFCCC [8] (para 5.7.3). Second, the Court emphasised the political recognition of the scientific insights of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) in numerous COP decisions to justify the outcome of the case [8] (paras 7.2.2 and 7.2.3).
Urgenda is an illustrative example of climate constitutionalisation, where political and non-enforceable legal commitments contribute to establishing prevailing obligations when they give meaning to human rights obligations. The Supreme Court and, in even more detail, the Procurator General list the relevant stipulations of all past COPs [8] (paras 5–12), [61] (sections 1.2(xxvii), 1.7, 2.19, and 2.30). They explain that, as highest political organs of the UNFCCC, COPs do not produce binding norms. This implies that also non-binding commitments and norms may deploy legal effects in combination with binding norms. Similarly, the appeal decision in Klimaatzaak bolsters the relevance of international commitments for the legal assessment of state action, including to establish a substantive minimum threshold [14] (paras 8–68).
One factor that determines whether and how much courts rely directly on international political and legal commitments is whether and to what extent national legislation has transposed these commitments. If these commitments are transposed, courts can and do rely on the equivalent national legal obligations. In Neubauer, the GFCC also incidentally referred to the UNFCCC framework but did not (have to) rely on international commitments because the Federal Climate Change Act had incorporated the Paris temperature goal [10].
The stark contrast between international and national political and legal mitigation commitments made collectively and for the future (e.g., Paris Agreement and net zero pledges), on the one hand, and either the lack of or unambitious interim targets and inadequate implementation action is central to SCL. Litigants challenge public failures to adequately protect their rights in light of overwhelming representations and commitments of the same public authorities promising such protection. In SCL, states do not deny that they made these representations and commitments but routinely challenge their justiciability. SCL also exposes conflicts between the objectives states express in law and politics and the measures that they take in law and practice. Judges regularly point out how states fail to justify the latter in light of the former. When doing so, judges make a coherence argument (liberal-conservative justification). Regularly, this leads them to establish unlawfulness or even to impose positive duties. Some cases strongly contribute to the constitutionalisation of international commitments (Urgenda; Klimaatzaak, L’Affaire du Siècle and Grande Synthe I). In others, these commitments are not given prevalence but form part of the legal assessment (Neubauer). None of the examined cases denies their (persuasive) relevance.

3.3. Normative Effects of Science

Any and all of the international political and legal commitments of the defendant states can only be concretised into mitigation obligations by reference to climate science. The IPCC reports capture the global state of the climate crisis. They constitute the baseline of argument in SCL, often complemented with country-specific studies. Because of their exceptional inclusiveness and political support, IPCC reports are routinely considered ‘best available science’ within the meaning of Articles 4(1), 7(5) and 14(1) of the Paris Agreement by national courts, and now also explicitly the ICJ [24] (para 278), critical [75]. By now, they enjoy particular normative authority also because of this judicial acknowledgement of their legal relevance. The summaries for policymakers are endorsed line-by-line and the reports are more globally endorsed by states, both by unanimity. On the one hand, this bolsters their democratic support; on the other, it leads to the exclusion of controversial points and gravitates towards the lowest common denominator. Litigants rightly pointed out that the IPCC reports are therefore substantively fairly ‘conservative’ [14] (para 17).
Urgenda, Klimaatzaak, and L’Affaire du Siècle, for example, drew in their reasoning on different IPCC reports. Neubauer relied on the assessments of national scientific advisory bodies, which are based on IPCC reports [10] (paras 28, 36, 216–47), [76]. KlimaSeniorinnen again heavily relied on the IPCC for establishing the ‘facts concerning climate change’ [16] (paras 64–120) and the effects of climate change for the enjoyment of Convention rights in its assessment of Articles 2 and 8 ECHR [16] (paras 431–33). For its assessment of the adequacy of Swiss climate actions, however, it relied on expert submissions of the parties [16] (paras 558). In all of these cases, science forms an essential element in establishing the justification and substance of prevailing mitigation obligations. The strong engagement with expertise evokes the technocratic justification, namely that, in the climate crisis, expert knowledge needs to be placed beyond the reach of political majority decisions [44].
However, reliance on IPCC reports does not in all cases result in close (or even correct) engagement with the substantive scientific information. IPCC reports simply set out models of different scenarios with different likelihoods (pathways). They do not cast a normative judgment on desirability or adequacy in light of the gravity of impacts or legal and political commitments. The Court of Appeal in Klimaatzaak, for example, made the normative choice to combine in its assessment the most conservative variables that it found in the IPCC reports, i.e., those that are ‘least constraining for the state’ [14] (para 21). From this basis, it construed an absolute minimum. This approach holds the danger that this absolute minimum is vested with the normative judicial endorsement of legal adequateness and justifiability [77] (p. 4810). To be more specific, the Court took as a starting point a probability of one out of two/50% to keep global warming to 1.5 °C. This is different from the Dutch Supreme Court in Urgenda and the GFCC in Neubauer, but also notably KlimaSeniorinnen, which all assumed that outcome should be ‘likely’, two out of three or 67%. It then settled for the lowest level of ambition by accepting the lower end of 55% (rather than 65%) reduction by 2030. Overall, this led in Klimaatzaak to an absolute minimum that seems difficult to justify. The Swiss Federal Court in KlimaSeniorinnen even held that the Paris Agreement ‘assumed that there was still time to avert the global temperature rise to keep it [well below 2 °C or even 1.5 °C (sic!)]’ [29] (para 5.3). This is a misconception of what climate science tells us needs to be done to stay below that goal.
What likelihood of an outcome is legally required is a normative question, not a scientific one. The Court of Appeal in Klimaatzaak is hence wrong when stating that ‘best available science confirms that a 50–scenario is not unreasonable’ [14] (para 195). Scientific bodies set out pathways with the one in two likelihood of reaching 1.5 °C and sketch how they are feasible and cost effective. They do not make any assessment of normative reasonableness or desirability. Accepting the lowest end of possible reduction percentages is a normative choice which a court must justify by reference to normative considerations grounded in law. Similar issues are raised by grandfathering, overshoot, and negative emissions, which are inherent in all climate models but the degree of their use needs to be normatively justified. In other words, certain obligations, including the absolute minimum reduction obligations, cannot be normatively substantiated by arguing that they are reasonable in light of science. They must be justified in light of political and legal commitments, principles of international law, and constitutional obligations. By foregrounding science as the single justification, the court marginalised the value-based disagreements that exist about what we should do to avoid which climate impacts and human rights violations.
Without detailed and reliable science, prevailing legal norms could not be interpreted to entail specific obligations to reduce emission by a substantive minimum (as Urgenda and Klimaatzaak). Similarly, procedural duties with substantive yardsticks as in Neubauer and KlimaSeniorinnen (ECtHR) require states to quantify and justify their actions in relation to best available science.

4. Climate Constitutionalisation in Europe

Climate constitutionalisation in Europe is an incremental but also at times erratic non-linear process carried by expressions of legal authority. Courts from different jurisdictions that do not stand in any hierarchical relationship to each other participate in this process. All cases examined in this paper build on each other by referring at least to one prior SCL case (with the exception of Urgenda as the first). Many other cases in Europe also refer to the herein discussed cases, e.g., [9,15].

4.1. Replicability

In 2019, Urgenda established in final instance that the climate crisis is a matter of human rights under the ECHR. In the past 5 years, Urgenda has been widely cited by other courts, within but also beyond Europe [78,79,80]. What we see in the examined case law is a high level of replicability. Human rights arguments are proposed and developed. International legal and political commitments of the defendant states are relied on to argue that they repeatedly acknowledged and hence knew about the magnitude and urgency of the climate crisis. Climate science is the factual basis to concretise what human rights and international commitments require in terms of emission reductions. All three aspects are prone to exceptional replicability. All European states are Contracting Parties to the ECHR and participate in international climate governance. The heating of the climate concerns each and every person on the planet; it can scientifically directly be linked to a global carbon budget that represents the cumulative emissions on earth. By reliance on each other’s decisions, judges add external authority to all three ways of justifying constitutionalisation: Liberal-conservative arguments based on coherence are bolstered by reference to interpretations of human rights applicable in all European jurisdiction, such as the ECHR. Technocratic or transformative arguments are supported by reference to rulings of other, potentially higher, courts explaining the urgency or the exceptionalism of the crisis.
The replicability of arguments and findings traced in this paper also reaches beyond general emission reduction cases against states. For example, an increasing number of climate cases against companies relies in their reasoning on arguments and findings that were developed in SCL. In the Netherlands, Milieudefensie v. Royal Dutch Shell is a case in point [81]. It was built on the success of Urgenda, relying on liberal-conservative and transformative arguments. In Germany, Neubauer is widely cited in follow up cases, including cases against public authorities and companies [82,83,84,85,86,87]. Because of the GFCC’s strong hierarchical position in the German legal order its decisions carry exceptional weight for coherence arguments (liberal-conservative). Follow-up cases in Germany routinely apply and further develop arguments from the Neubauer decision [88]. An example is the ‘budget approach’, characterized by its focus on the equality implications of future human rights restrictions caused by mitigation measures that are necessary to stay within Germany’s fair share of the shrinking global carbon budget. This point draws inter alia on a technological justification.
Replicability drives climate constitutionalisation, which in turn empowers the judiciary. Reference to other SCL rulings bolsters a court’s claim to legitimacy. References to international commitments, science, and cases from other jurisdictions highlight the global nature of the climate crisis and the grievances it causes. They also emphasise judicial decisions as one entry point where the international dimension of the climate crises enters into the domestic deliberation about mitigation obligations. Fairness in the context of the global carbon budget can only be argued in relation to others, including those outside one’s own jurisdiction. Ultimately, a claim to fairness in this respect must stand the test of whether it should at least on principle be reasonably acceptable to those outside one’s own jurisdiction. Because of widespread cross-jurisdictional references, one may expect that national courts are aware how their reasoning resonates beyond the boundaries of their jurisdiction. They likely also consider whether their position could be perceived as acceptable if it were generalised and replicated in other jurisdictions.

4.2. Countertendencies in a Multilayered Judicial Context

Countertendencies are also part of climate constitutionalisation. Unsuccessful SCL cases come with low expectations of what they may contribute to climate constitutionalisation and are overall more likely to push back on one of the three examined issues. Examples of unsuccessful cases with countertendencies can be found in Nature and Youth, Plan B, Klimatická žaloba (Supreme Administrative Court, 2023) and the national Swiss case of KlimaSeniorinnen, as well as Greenpeace v Spain I & II, A Sud (IT), the Swedish case Aurora and the Finnish climate cases [26,27,28,29,30,31,32,33,34,35].
Swiss courts in the national case of KlimaSeniorinnen took the stark and—in Europe—exceptional position that the issue was not justiciable. In Nature and Youth, environmental groups claimed that Norway violated the constitution by issuing oil and gas licenses for deep-sea extraction in the Barents Sea [26,89], and that they should take into account (foreseeable) extraterritorial emissions resulting from burning the extracted fossil fuels. The claim was rejected in all three instances. The Norwegian Supreme Court concluded that Articles 2 and 8 ECHR were not violated. It stated that ‘the net effect of the combustion emissions is complicated and controversial’ [26] (para 234) and that ‘[t]he authorities’ policy was that’ GHG emissions were reduced ‘by other means than stopping future petroleum production’ [26] (para 243). Accepting complexity and undefined other means as reasons for executive discretion goes against the trend of requiring concrete justification from public authorities. Nonetheless, the court confirmed that the right to a healthy and natural environment is ‘not merely a declaration of principle, but a provision with a certain legal content’ [26] (para 144). Under certain circumstances, this right may directly be invoked in court.
Another illustrative example of a countertendency is Plan B in the UK. In this case, the plaintiffs alleged that the national climate policy violated the ECHR/Human Rights Act 1998 by not complying with the Paris Agreement. The courts rejected this claim because of the ‘insuperable problem’ that the evolving regulatory framework reflects a judgment of the legislature that needs to be respected ‘unless it is manifestly without reasonable foundation’ [27] (para 48–50 and 77). In the UK, while the ECHR and the ECtHR’ case law are not directly legally binding under national law, these norms enjoy great relevance before UK courts. In Plan B, the Court of Appeal rejected the application for permission to appeal based on the Human Rights Act, arguing that ‘[t]he fundamental difficulty which the Claimants face is that there is no authority from the [ECtHR] on which they can rely’ [27] (para 5). Plan B also considered and distinguished both Urgenda and the Irish Climate case [27] (para 55–56).
In Klimatická žaloba (Supreme Administrative Court, 2nd instance), Greenpeace v Spain, and A Sud (IT, 1st instance), courts relied on EU law to deny justiciability of national climate targets [90]. They emphasised the competences of the EU, the ongoing processes of allocating emissions within the EU, and the potential political damage of ruling on the legality of the national contribution to EU-wide emission reductions. Indirectly, they denied that their respective states had autonomous obligations under international law that may require them to go further than what EU law requires them to do.
National courts are the primary judicial actors to apply human rights. Some have rejected or limited the relevance of human rights claims in relation to the climate crisis. However, (the potential threat of) bringing cases to Strasbourg puts pressure on national institutions, including national courts. It urges them to consider the ECtHR’s position, including on the here discussed aspects of scope and applicability of human rights in relation to the climate crisis, the relevance of international law principles to quantify domestic fair share carbon budgets, and science. The next section illustrates the particular opportunities within the multilayered legal and judicial landscape in Europe. The setting does not only allow for replication but also for deliberation and co-creation. Both national courts and the ECtHR are aware of each other’s contributions to that deliberative process. It is a space where political and legal actors with overlapping powers that do not stand in a judicial hierarchy to each other negotiate their authority and deliberate how the climate crisis should be addressed [91].
For the moment, however, the ECJ does not participate in this process. The climate cases demanding greater general emission reductions from the EU were rejected by the EU courts in two instances [68,69,70,71,92]. To allow SCL cases against the EU, the ECJ would have to change its strict interpretation of the standing requirements in cases brought by individuals. The ECtHR’s decision in KlimaSeniorinnen, discussed in the next section, puts pressure on the ECJ in that respect [93].

5. Multilayered Constitutionalisation

European climate constitutionalisation is driven by the multilayered legal landscape of Europe, which is characterized by a distinct interlocking between different layers of law, namely the ECHR, EU law, and national law, and to a lesser degree international law [21,22]. This offers a fertile ground for mutual referencing, reliance and replication, which allows decisions of the ECtHR and the Advisory Opinion of the ICJ—at least in principle—to carry great weight in national litigation.

5.1. The European Court of Human Rights: KlimaSeniorinnen and Beyond

All states in Europe are Contracting Parties to the ECHR. This highlights the relevance of the interpretation given to the ECHR in Urgenda, Klimaatzaak and, of course, KlimaSeniorinnen. When Convention rights are concretised by the ECtHR, this entrenches an interpretation beyond the reach of national courts and makes legal change more difficult [50]. National courts will have to either give effect to the ECtHR’s interpretation or distinguish it. They cannot simply ignore it. At the same time, the Strasbourg judges’ knowledge of national SCL may be assumed to have played a role in KlimaSeniorinnen. They explicitly agreed with the GFCC in Neubauer [16] (para. 571). Urgenda was mentioned several times in the relevant materials but not in the Court’s reasoning [16] (164, 245–246 and 260–261). This all speaks to the particular replicability of the rights-based argument in the multilayered judicial landscape. In this multilayered landscape, human rights provisions, while they differ in some respects, largely converge [21].
While the ECHR is binding on 46 Contracting Parties, the status and practical relevance of the ECHR in the national legal order differs among the Contracting Parties [94]. Besides their legal effects, ECtHR rulings enjoy across jurisdictions great persuasive authority for all future SCL in Europe. By way of illustration, one can contrast Germany as a very dualist legal order and the Netherlands following a (moderate) monist tradition [95]. The GFCC ruled that the ECHR has the same status as ordinary laws taking effect within the framework of the German Constitution [96,97]. As other international treaties that are binding on Germany, the ECHR hence ranks below the Constitution. Ordinary courts must first observe the Constitution as interpreted by the GFCC. Before the GFCC, the ECHR (only) serves as an ‘interpretation aid’ in determining the contents of the Constitution [94]. This also explains why the ECHR was not given any attention in the Neubauer case. In the Netherlands, by contrast, individuals can, pursuant to Article 94 of the Dutch Constitution, rely upon provisions of international treaties that are binding on everyone, even if they are incompatible with the national constitution. The ECHR and decisions of the ECtHR can be directly invoked before national courts. The ECtHR de facto functions as the highest human rights court since the Dutch Supreme Court does not have the power of constitutional review. This strong position of the ECHR in the Netherlands is illustrated by Urgenda.
However, the precise effects of international articulations of rights norms are not easy to pin down. As has been observed eloquently: Such articulation ‘has reshaped domestic dialogues in law, politics, academia, public consciousness, civil society and the press. […] While reliable quantitative measurement is probably impossible, by strengthening domestic rights institutions, international human rights law has brought incalculable, indirect benefits for rights protection’ [98] (p. 121). These benefits rest on a complex combination of binding adjudicatory powers of the ECtHR and the principle of subsidiarity and the margin of appreciation [99] (pp. 705 and 722). The former establishes a prevailing duty to comply with Convention rights. The latter, by contrast, gives state institutions, including national courts, a degree of independence to interpret and give effect to this duty in a ‘deliberative engagement’. Ultimately, however, the Convention demands that state institutions make a claim of compliance [49] (pp. 7–8).
In KlimaSeniorinnen, the Grand Chamber of the ECtHR interpreted Article 8 ECHR to entail a positive duty to quantify a fair share carbon budget. It did so after Swiss courts in two instances had rejected claims alleging an omission of the Swiss Government to adopt a regulatory framework of adequate climate policies [16,29]. The ECtHR’s decision in KlimaSeniorinnen establishes a procedural duty (to quantify a budget) with a substantive yardstick (in light of fairness principles). Because of the composition and institutional role of the Grand Chamber, rulings of the Grand Chamber enjoy particular authority and ensure a higher level of coherence than other decisions of the ECtHR [100] (Rule 24 and 72).
The ECtHR’s ruling in KlimaSeniorinnen drives climate constitutionalisation on all three above-discussed aspects. It recognised, first, that the climate crisis is a human rights issue that can be litigated under the Convention and imposes a positive obligation on states. Second, this obligation to quantify a fair share carbon budget has to be discharged in line with fairness principles of international law. Third, the Court recognised the science that allows quantifying a carbon budget in line with a two out of three/67% likelihood to stay under 1.5 °C.
With regard to the first and the second, the ECtHR did not numerically quantify Switzerland’s budget or establish the precise methodology for quantification. It did not set out a minimum emission reduction obligation either. However, it confirmed that fairness principles of international law must be taken into account for states to discharge their duty to quantify their share of the carbon budget [16] (para. 571). The Court carefully avoided to take a position on intricate methodological controversies and allowed states a wide margin of appreciation on methods. At the same time, it made clear that the Contracting Parties had to offer ‘effective protection’ [16] (para 519) of Convention rights. In order to do so, they must work out and explain what their ‘fair share’ carbon budget is, i.e., how should the global carbon budget be divided into national shares in light of fairness principles. Fair share is a concept central to all general emission reduction cases and the relevance of the Strasbourg Court’s reasoning and findings on this point can hardly be overestimated for current and future SCL cases in Europe.
The ECtHR has cast the ball back to the domestic institutions of the Contracting Parties. These must now draw up explicit fair share carbon budgets, set up regulatory frameworks to stay within these budgets and, by doing so, decide how to reconcile numerous short-term and long-term interests. The Court emphasises that this process involves all three branches of government, i.e., not only the executive and the legislature but also national courts [16] (paras 449 and 550). The latter demonstrates respect for vertical separation of powers, i.e., the more limited role of the ECtHR as a regional court offering subsidiary protection in combination with a greater role for the national judiciary in the domestic democratic process. As explained above, all domestic institutions must deliberatively engage with KlimaSeniorinnen and make a claim of compliance with the obligations to quantify a fair share carbon budget and adopt an effective regulatory framework.
The ECtHR also gave standing rights to the association KlimaSeniorinnen. This is another specific aspect that cast the ball back to national courts and that has already and will continue to have a tremendous impact on SCL before national courts and potentially also the ECJ. Before the ECtHR, the association could represent the interests of affected individuals under Article 8 ECHR, including ‘without a specific authority to act’ [16] (paras 498–503; quote at 476). This broadening of standing before the Strasbourg Court is determinative for pending and future SCL. Judges when interpreting national standing requirements of associations take note of KlimaSeniorinnen [33,101]. National courts have all reasons to avoid being ticked on their fingers in follow up cases in Strasbourg [102]. However, in the same way, KlimaSeniorinnen also puts pressure on the ECJ to adjudicate mitigation cases relating to the EU itself rather than waiting for national courts and Strasbourg to tell it what constitutes a rights violation [93].
Furthermore, in KlimaSeniorinnen, the ECtHR directly quoted the paragraph on lack of authoritative case law in Plan B and did what it was invited to do: clarify the relevance of the Paris Agreement for the interpretation of the Convention [16] (para 268). This should have great influence on the interpretation of Convention rights in the UK in the future. Finally, KlimaSeniorinnen may potentially reign in countertendencies in the pending case of Max Mullner v Austria [103]. In this case, the ECtHR is for the first time asked to consider the Convention-compliance of an EU Member State that does not have a separate national emission reduction target. Austria derives its target directly from the EU target. Therefore, the Court may likely have to engage with the issue of whether Member States can discharge their obligations by pointing at EU law and the EU decision-making process, as the Czech Supreme Court held [90]. By extension, this may lead the ECtHR to examine the EU target in light of the Convention obligation to quantify one’s fair share carbon budget (KlimaSeniorinnen).

5.2. The Advisory Opinion on of the International Court of Justice

The ICJ’s groundbreaking and unanimous advisory opinion on obligations of states in respect of climate change is likely to give SCL and other climate litigation around the world a new momentum. This includes SCL in Europe. The ICJ is the highest authority interpreting states’ obligations under international law. National and regional courts must relate their interpretation of what national and regional norms mean in light of international law to the ICJ’s interpretation.
Advisory Opinions are given in an unusual procedural setting. In this setting the courts do not rule on the rights and obligations of specific parties in an individualized dispute but responds to questions in a more abstract and generalized fashion [24,104,105]. This may also explain why, besides the important and specific reflection on the harmfulness of producing, licensing, and subsidizing fossil fuels, the ICJ did not outline detailed state obligations or remedies [24] (para 94 (scope of AO) and 427 (attribution)).
The ICJ took the strong and unambiguous position that the right to a clean and healthy environment is a precondition for the enjoyment of other human rights [24] (paras 389 and 393). It explained in detail how the climate crisis is a human rights issue [24] (paras 372–86). While some of the separate opinions take the position that the ICJ could have gone further in outlining the scope and status of the right to a clean and healthy environment [106] (para 9), [107] (para 27–46), the Advisory Opinion leaves no doubt about its fundamental importance and arguably goes further on this particularly point than the ECtHR’s ruling in KlimaSeniorinnen, Urgenda, and Neubauer, none of which specifically establishes an autonomous right to a clean and healthy environment but derives the right to protection from the climate crisis from other human rights.
The ICJ also expressly found support for its reasoning in the decisions of regional and national courts [24] (para 385). As regards the relevance of international law and policy, the Court traced and confirmed the political and legal consensus on 1.5 °C as the long-term temperature goal (while acknowledging that this level of warming already causes significant harms) [24] (paras 224 and 189). It also established that international environmental treaties and customary international law and the international climate regime ‘inform each other’ [24] (paras 404 and 309–315). Finally, it confirmed the relevance of international fairness principles to establishing what states are obliged to do in terms of climate mitigation [24] (paras 240 and 247). As regards science, the ICJ made clear that ‘[t]he determination of “significant harm to the climate system and other parts of the environment” must take into account the best available science. which is to be found in the reports of the IPCC [24] (para 278 emphasis added). A core climate obligation of states is to ‘prepare, communicate and maintain successive and progressive NDCs’ that are capable of achieving 1.5 °C [24] (para 457 (3)(A)(f)). The assessment of whether cumulative mitigation efforts are capable of achieving the long-term temperature goal must necessarily rely on science to establish the link between human emissions and global warming [24] (para 72).
The ICJ’s Advisory Opinion authoritatively clarifies extensive international obligations in respect of climate change. Already before the delivery of the advisory opinion, these international obligations have, as we saw above, regularly informed the judicial reasoning of national and regional courts in Europe. They construed what domestic and regional human rights require from states by reference to these obligations. With the ICJ unambiguously linking climate obligations to core international human rights instruments, national and regional courts are in a very difficult position to explain why corresponding national and regional human rights should be interpreted less stringently. Moreover, the position that Member States of the EU do not have autonomous climate mitigation obligations under international law that may go further than what EU law requires them to do became untenable after the ICJ’s advisory opinion.

6. Justifying Constitutionalisation

SCL asks courts to declare unlawful the defendant states’ failure to adequately mitigate the climate crisis and/or impose mitigation obligations on the defendant states. Two different types of outcomes in SCL may be distinguished: substantive obligations (Urgenda, Klimaatzaak) and procedural obligations in light of substantive yardsticks (Neubauer, KlimaSeniorinnen). In both categories of outcomes, courts place the objective of mitigating the climate crisis beyond the reach of day-to-day state actions by the (directly or indirectly) elected, majoritarian institutions, i.e., Parliament and Government. In none of the examined cases, courts determined the means of how emissions should be reduced or even the methods based on which the domestic fair share should be quantified. Hence, the balancing of (short-term) interests relating to how we reduce emissions and the justification of what is fair are left to politics [16] (para 421). Hence, in the examined SCL cases, judges leave space to the political (majoritarian) institutions and civil society to deliberate how to mitigate the climate crisis. They only demand that they do so.
We have seen that judges offer at least three types of justifications in favour of constitutionalisation: liberal-conservative, technocratic, and transformative [44]. Scholars have also advanced justifications along these three lines in favour of SCL. They emphasise, for example, how litigation reinforces representation within existing structures [108], the need for science-based decision-making [109], and that the climate crisis, because of its exceptionality, requires an urgent break with existing practices [110].
The strongest justification flows from the realisation expressed by the ICJ, namely that a healthy environment is a prerequisite for the enjoyment of many other human rights. In addition, it is also a prerequisite for democracy itself [70]. If states do not deliver on the most basic goods in the social contract this puts social peace and the functioning of the polity in danger. In Neubauer, the GFCC convincingly pointed out that if more stringent mitigation actions are not taken now this leads in the future (after 2030) to unreasonable restrictions of freedoms, including collective political freedoms [10] (para 246). In a state of climate emergency, i.e., carbon lockdowns, democratic choices vanish.
In other words, judicial intervention and democratic decision-making cannot be juxtaposed. They form part of the interinstitutional exchanges that characterise decision-making processes in European democracies. Declining jurisdiction, denying standing, and ultimately making human rights irrelevant in the climate crisis is neither innocent nor neutral for democracy. In light of increasing impacts, state paralysis reasonably raises doubt whether our democracies are up for this fundamental challenge [111,112,113]. Considering alternatives of judicial engagement with SCL in light of governmental failures quickly leads us to transformative justifications. While courts in SCL have so far engaged with transformative reasons only to a limited extent, growing impacts, closing windows of opportunities, and dwindling carbon budgets are likely to make this line of reasoning become more prevalent in future cases.
Another strong justification is tied together with the nature of the climate crisis as a truly global collective action problem that necessarily requires international cooperation. Any such cooperation is only possible if states remain credible and trustworthy cooperation partners. In other words, cooperation can only work if states do domestically what they commit to internationally. This also becomes apparent in ICJ’s advisory opinion emphasising the duty to cooperate [24] (para 227). International or regional treaties set binding (quasi-contractual) norms between sovereign states that necessarily entrench what was agreed and by doing so, make cooperation possible [114]. Such treaties cannot be cast aside and hence constrain the politics of the day expressed within the elected institutions. Ensuring that these international norms are (at least to some degree) given effect forms part of being a credible and trustworthy cooperation partner. Whether this is done by the judiciary or by the elected institutions is not the primary concern. This also taps into the liberal-conservative reasoning of coherence in the legal order.
We can however see the fault lines deepening between the judiciary and the political institutions, not only in the national but also in the international context [115]. Courts from many jurisdictions, including the ICJ, bolster with their rulings and opinions the conditions for more litigation. They allow those whose human rights affected by the climate crisis to demand justification for inadequate climate actions. They also acknowledge that human rights do not only have a defensive function but also an enabling function—e.g., most clearly [10]. If a certain level of protection of (human) rights is not in practice ensured humans cannot be autonomous participants in the democratic process [116].
In relation to these fault lines, anyone criticising that judges are overreaching in SCL should consider the alternatives. Some of the ‘unsuccessful’ SCL cases demonstrate the inability of our constitutional democracies to deal with the existential threat of the climate crisis. If judges deny jurisdiction, while the other branches of government fail to take adequate action, our state institutions collectively prove incapable of addressing the climate crisis. If structurally citizens are left without any remedy against irreversible current and future human rights violations this amounts to an institutional, systemic failure of justice. Such a failure of justice cuts even deeper than the failure of states to take adequate action in the first place. Ultimately, as confirmed by the ICJ, all other human rights depend on the right to a clean and healthy environment.

7. Conclusions

SCL in Europe has incrementally, including with countertendencies, established prevailing mitigation norms drawing on human rights, international legal and political commitments, and science. This phenomenon can appropriately be described as European climate constitutionalisation. One aspect of constitutionalisation is that SCL is not mushrooming in many unrelated cases but builds a connected web of arguments and references. The multilayered legal landscape of Europe creates a particularly fertile landscape for constitutionalisation. Courts that do not stand in a hierarchical relationship to each other decide on interrelated or even largely the same issues from the perspective of different jurisdictions. They take binding decisions with respect to the same people and territory. They also refer to each other’s rulings and rely on each other’s authoritative interpretations.
In addition, SCL benefits for at least four reasons from exceptional replicability: First, the climate crisis is a truly global collective action problem caused by all and affecting the human rights of all (albeit both in very different ways). These human rights—albeit in slightly different ways—are recognised by all European states, not only under national law but also collectively by signing up to the ECHR and EU law. Second, SCL relies on political and legal commitments of states within the international climate governance framework with nearly universal membership. In addition, the ICJ recently connected these mitigation obligations with universally binding jus cogens, which is likely to be picked up in future SCL. Third, climate science is universal in that it traces and explains a global phenomenon. The underlying causal relationships, and resulting impacts, of the climate crisis, even if its impacts affect different regions very differently, are universal. All and every action on the planet is factually connected to these processes. Fourth, so far, none of the defendant states has taken climate action anywhere close to their fair share. This fair share is defined as what adequately mitigating the climate crisis collectively would demand from them in light of fairness principles. Each and every European state is a potential defendant in SCL. These exceptional characteristics of SCL have allowed it to produce in a relatively short timeframe prevailing norms that constrain state action.
Within Europe, a recent leap in climate constitutionalisation is the ECtHR’s ruling in KlimaSeniorinnen. The Court’s reading that the climate crisis as a human rights issue under the Convention powerfully reenforces the position of those domestic courts that see a role for law and courts in this crisis. All ECHR signatories may reasonably expect to be taken to the Strasbourg Court if they remain below the level of climate action demanded by the ECtHR in KlimaSeniorinnen. Future decisions in the currently pending cases offer further opportunities to push back on countertendencies. In addition, the ICJ’s advisory opinion significantly contributes to the constitutionalising processes in domestic courts. It confirmed—in line with KlimaSeniorinnen—what adequate climate action is. National emission reductions expressed in NDCs must comply with international fairness principles and, importantly, be cumulatively capable of keeping global warming below 1.5 °C. It is now for domestic courts to give teeth to the obligations outlined by the ECtHR and the ICJ. Litigants will surely ask them to do so.
The number of new and pending SCL cases in Europe remains at a high level [4]. For politicians, SCL may feel like being stuck in a repeat game with increasing stakes and decreasing chances. With the adoption of more and more net zero targets, SCL may over time shift from pushing states to adopt emission reduction targets to push them to adopt the necessary plans and concrete mitigation (and adaptation) measures and pay compensation for failing to do so. New litigation strategies emerge and rely on the insights in the discussed cases on what works and what does not. Some cases are bound to contribute to further climate constitutionalisation. If the elected branches continue to fail to agree and adopt adequate climate actions the fault line between them and the judiciary is going to deepen.
Whatever judges do in SCL, their decisions contribute to the development of norms. They also speak to the meaning of law and the role of the judiciary in addressing the climate crisis. Unsuccessful cases also contribute to constitutionalisation, including by escalating the issues to the ECtHR. The emerging norms constitute the framework in relation to which public but also private actors develop their understanding of what actions are lawful or justified [117] (p. 855). This effect goes beyond the courtroom. Not only because of growing climate impacts but also because of the rising level of climate constitutionalisation, the political and legal salience of climate mitigation (and adaptation) as a human rights issue is likely to further increase. We may expect further interventions by numerous interested and affected parties, including through litigation.
Climate constitutionalisation can also be normatively justified. In light of the wide-spread and well-documented failures of European states to reduce emissions adequately, it remains an ambivalent hope. The repeated signposts and redlines drawn by national and international judges cannot easily be ignored by state institutions. The judiciary’s task to protect the coherence of the legal order lies at the heart of SCL. Political actors time and again confirm in law and politics that the urgency and magnitude of the climate crisis but they do not manage to take the necessary actions in the short-term. They rather aggravate the problem further by pushing these actions into the future. SCL decisions aim to re-establish coherence between diverging legal norms, including the fundamental background norms that protect us from systematic human rights violation. They are important points of reference in the ongoing deliberation of what to do about the exceptional challenge of the climate crisis. Some courts have the constitutional task to ensure that all state institutions live up to their constitutional duties. Arguably, all state institutions must protect the existence and functioning of the polity. This entails averting the ‘existential risks’ of the climate crisis [16] (para 421). Judicial review has an important place in the democratic process of demanding and providing justification. The underlying relations of demanding and giving justification are complex. The litigants in SCL are the prime actors demanding justification from the defendant states. However, international law and politics play an important role in the legal reasoning and extend these relations beyond the specific judicial processes and beyond the involved parties, including to other states and third country nationals.
Importantly, constitutionalisation, while it may remove certain aspects from the political debate, does not mark an end point of these processes. It does not definitely settle emission reduction obligations of states. The ICJ’s Advisory Opinion is the latest example of a principled judicial position that leaves room for the unfolding of politics to crystalize precise state obligations. Examples from domestic courts to support this point are Urgenda and Neubauer. After Urgenda, the political debate in the Netherlands continues [118]. A second SCL case, launched by Greenpeace, together with and on behalf of citizens of Bonaire, was admitted to Dutch courts in September 2024 [101]. The hearing is scheduled for October 2025. In Germany, Neubauer established a constitutional commitment to remain within the national fair share of the global carbon budget. This is the point of reference for all follow-up litigation and the work of the expert bodies advising the German government under the federal climate change act [119]. Several follow up cases challenged inadequate implementation of the federal climate change act and its 2024 amendment [88,120]. In Switzerland, the implementation of the ECtHR’s decision in KlimaSeniorinnen is negotiated in the Council of Ministers [16 (para 657),121]. In Belgium, Wallonia decided not to appeal Klimaatzaak, while Belgium and Flanders appealed to Court of Cassation. In other words, climate constitutionalisation continues to unfold, accompanied by ongoing interactions between elected representatives, the judiciary, and the public on how to address the climate crisis. Climate constitutionalisation sets boundaries but does not bring these debates to an even temporary conclusion.

Funding

This research was funded by the European Research Council as part of the LitDem project [101125511].

Conflicts of Interest

The author declares no conflict of interest.

References

  1. Chaisse, J. Systematic Rivalries and Multilevel Governance in Asia: A Constitutional Perspective. In Constitutionalism and Transnational Governance Failures; Petersmann, E.-U., Steinbach, A., Eds.; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 2024. [Google Scholar]
  2. Daly, E.; Tigre, M.A.; Urzola, N. Common but Differentiated Constitutionalisms—Does “Environmental Constitutionalism” Offer Realistic Policy Options for Improving UN Environmental Law and Governance? US and Latin American Perspectives. In Constitutionalism and Transnational Governance Failures; Petersmann, E.-U., Steinbach, A., Eds.; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 2024. [Google Scholar]
  3. Higham, C.; Setzer, J.; Bradeen, E. Challenging Government Responses to Climate Change Through Framework Litigation; Grantham Research Institute on Climate Change and the Environment and Centre for Climate Change Economics and Policy: London, UK, 2022; Available online: https://www.lse.ac.uk/granthaminstitute/wp-content/uploads/2022/09/Challenging-government-responses-to-climate-change-through-framework-litigation-final.pdf (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  4. Setzer, J.; Higham, C. Global Trends in Climate Change Litigation: 2025 Snapshot; Policy report, LSE 2025; Research Institute on Climate Change and the Environment: London, UK, 2025. [Google Scholar]
  5. Sabin Center’s Climate Litigation Database on Global Litigation. Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case-category/other/ (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  6. Rechtbank Den Haag [Court of First Instances The Hague], 24 June 2015, AB 2015/336 (Urgenda, First Instance). Rechtbank Den Haag, C/09/456689/HA ZA 13-1396 (English Translation). Available online: https://uitspraken.rechtspraak.nl/details?id=ECLI:NL:RBDHA:2015:7196 (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  7. Hof Den Haag [Court of Appeals The Hague], 9 October 2018, JB 2019/10 (Urgenda, Court of Appeal). Available online: http://deeplink.rechtspraak.nl/uitspraak?id=ECLI:NL:GHDHA:2018:2610 (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  8. State of the Netherlands v Stichting Urgenda [2019] ECLI:NL:HR:2019:2007 (Urgenda, Supreme Court). Available online: http://deeplink.rechtspraak.nl/uitspraak?id=ECLI:NL:HR:2019:2007 (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  9. Supreme Court of Ireland. Friends of the Irish Environment v. Ireland, Appeal No. 205/19. Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/friends-of-the-irish-environment-v-ireland/ (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  10. German Federal Constitutional Court [Bundesverfassungsgericht] Neubauer and Others v Germany [2021] 1 BvR 2656/18, 1 BvR 96/20, 1 BvR 78/20, 1 BvR 288/20, 1 BvR 96/20, 1 BvR 78/20 (Neubauer). Available online: https://www.bundesverfassungsgericht.de/SharedDocs/Entscheidungen/EN/2021/03/rs20210324_1bvr265618en.html (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  11. Administrative Court of Paris [Tribunal Administratif de Paris] L’Affaire du Siècle, Nos. 1904967, 1904968, 1904972, 1904976/4–1 (Oct. 14, 2021). Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/wp-content/uploads/non-us-case-documents/2021/20210203_NA_decision.pdf (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  12. Council of State [Conseil d’État]. Commune de Grande-Synthe v. France, Case No. 467982. Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/commune-de-grande-synthe-v-france/ (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  13. Court of First Instance VZW Klimaatzaak v Kingdom of Belgium & Others [2021] 2015/4585/A. Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/vzw-klimaatzaak-v-kingdom-of-belgium-et-al/ (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  14. Court of Appeals Brussels [Cour d’Appel Bruxelles] (2nd ch.), 30 November 2023, J.L.M.B. 24/045 (Belgium) (Klimaatzaak, Court of Appeal). Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/vzw-klimaatzaak-v-kingdom-of-belgium-et-al/ (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  15. Court of Appeal (England and Wales). R (Friends of the Earth Ltd.) v. Secretary of State for Business, Energy and Industrial Strategy, Claim Nos. CO/125/2022, CO/163/2022, CO/199/2022 (Net Zero Strategy). Available online: https://www.judiciary.uk/wp-content/uploads/2022/07/FoE-v-BEIS-judgment-180722.pdf (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  16. European Court of Human Rights, KlimaSeniorinnen Schweiz et al. v Switzerland, no. 53600/20, ruling of 9 April 2024. Available online: https://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng?i=001-233206 (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  17. Peel, J.; Osofsky, H.M. Climate Change Litigation. Annu. Rev. Law Soc. Sci. 2020, 16, 21–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  18. Wewerinke-Singh, M.; Mead, S. The Cambridge Handbook on Climate Litigation. 2025. Available online: https://www.cambridge.org/core/books/cambridge-handbook-on-climate-litigation/4970332A24405A651D2E68821E24C558 (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  19. Maxwell, L.; Mead, S.; van Berkel, D. Standards for adjudicating the next generation of Urgenda-style climate cases. J. Hum. Rights Environ. 2022, 13, 35–63. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  20. Setzer, J.; Higham, C. Global Trends in Climate Change Litigation: 2022 Snapshot. Policy Report, LSE 2022. Available online: https://www.lse.ac.uk/granthaminstitute/wp-content/uploads/2022/08/Global-trends-in-climate-change-litigation-2022-snapshot.pdf (accessed on 20 August 2025).
  21. Eckes, C. Mutual Trust and the Future of Fundamental Rights Protection in the EU’s Compound Legal Order. In Human Rights in Transition; Bhuta, N., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2024. [Google Scholar]
  22. Eckes, C. EU Powers Under External Pressure; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2019. [Google Scholar]
  23. Savaresi, A. Verein KlimaSeniorinnen Schweiz and Others v Switzerland: Making climate change litigation history. Rev. Eur. Comp. Int. Environ. Law 2025, 34, 279–287. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  24. International Court of Justice (ICJ). Obligations of States in Respect of Climate Change; Advisory Opinion of 23 July 2025 (ICJ, AO); ICJ: The Hague, The Netherlands, 2025. [Google Scholar]
  25. Sabin Center for Climate Change Law. Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-climate-change-litigation/ (accessed on 20 August 2025).
  26. Norwegian Supreme Court, Nature and Youth Norway and Others v Norway [2020] HR-2020-24720P (Nature and Youth). Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/greenpeace-nordic-assn-v-ministry-of-petroleum-and-energy-ecthr/ (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  27. High Court of Justice (Administrative Court). Plan B Earth v. Prime Minister, Case No. CO/1587/2021 (Plan B). Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/plan-b-earth-and-others-v-prime-minister/ (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  28. Supreme Administrative Court of the Czech Republic. Klimatická Žaloba ČR and Others v. the Czech Republic; Case No. 9 As 116/2022–166. Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/klimaticka-zaloba-cr-v-czech-republic/ (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  29. Swiss Federal Court [Bundesgericht] KlimaSeniorinnen Schweiz et al. v Federal Department of the Environment, Transport, Energy and Communications [2020] 1C_37/2019. Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/union-of-swiss-senior-women-for-climate-protection-v-swiss-federal-parliament/ (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  30. Supreme Court of Spain, Greenpeace v. Spain, ECLI:ES:TS:2023:3556 (Greenpeace v. Spain I). Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/greenpeace-v-spain/ (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  31. Supreme Court of Spain, Greenpeace v. Spain, ECLI:ES:TS:2023:3556 (Greenpeace v. Spain II). Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/greenpeace-v-spain/ (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  32. Civil Court of Macerata, Italy, A Sud v. Italy, Case No. 39415. Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/a-sud-et-al-v-italy (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  33. Nacka District Court, Aurora and Others v. Sweden, Case No. 7177-23. Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/anton-foley-and-others-v-sweden-aurora-case/ (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  34. Supreme Administrative Court of Finland [Korkein hallinto-oikeus]. KHO:2023:62; ECLI:FI:KHO:2023:62 (Finnish Climate Case I). Available online: https://www.kho.fi/en/index/decisions/summariesofselectedprecedentsinenglish_0/eclifikho202362.html (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  35. Supreme Administrative Court of Finland [Korkein hallinto-oikeus]. KHO:2025:2; ECLI:FI:KHO:2025:2 (Finnish Climate Case II). Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/wp-content/uploads/non-us-case-documents/2025/20250117_83751_decision.pdf (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  36. European Court of Human Rights, Carème v. France, Application No. 7189/21. Available online: https://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng/?i=001-233174 (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  37. European Court of Human Rights, Duarte Agostinho, Application No. 39371/20. Available online: https://hudoc.echr.coe.int/?i=001-233261 (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  38. UNEP. Emissions Gap Report 2023: Broken Record—Temperatures Hit New Highs, Yet World Fails to Cut Emissions (Again). EGR2023.pdf. Available online: https://unep.org (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  39. Climate Action Tracker. Analysis for 2022. Available online: https://climateactiontracker.org (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  40. UNEP. Emissions Gap Report 2022. Available online: https://www.unep.org/resources/emissions-gap-report-2022 (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  41. Dobner, P.; Loughlin, M. The Twilight of Constitutionalism? Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
  42. O’Donoghue, A. Constitutionalism in Global Constitutionalisation; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
  43. Niehaus, M. Global Climate Constitutionalism “from Below” the Role of Climate Change Litigation for International Climate Lawmaking; Springer: Wiesbaden, Germany, 2023. [Google Scholar]
  44. Bookman, S. Demystifying Environmental Constitutionalism. Environ. Law 2024, 54, 1–77. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  45. May, J.; Daly, E. Global Environmental Constitutionalism; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
  46. Kotzé, L. The Conceptual Contours of Environmental Constitutionalism. Widener L. Rev. 2015, 21, 187. [Google Scholar]
  47. Holmes, S. Precommitment and Paradox of Democracy. In Constitutionalism and Democracy; Elster, J., Slagstad, R., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1988. [Google Scholar]
  48. Kennedy, D. A Semiotics of Legal Argument. Syracuse Law Rev. 1991, 42, 75–116. [Google Scholar]
  49. Harel, A. The Tension between the National and ECHR Human Rights Adjudication: A Normative Account. Hum. Rights Law Rev. 2024, 24, ngad033. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  50. Barber, N. Why entrench? Int. J. Const. Law 2016, 14, 325–350. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  51. Eckes, C. A Timid Defence of Legal Formalism. In The Politics of European Legal Research; Bartl, M., Lawrence, J., Eds.; Edward Elgar Publishing Ltd.: Cheltenham, UK, 2022; pp. 192–207. [Google Scholar]
  52. Supreme Court of the United States. Medellín v. Texas; 552 U.S. 491 (2008); Supreme Court of the United States: Washington, DC, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
  53. Kavanagh, A. The Collaborative Constitution; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2023. [Google Scholar]
  54. Art. 13 Dutch Law of General Provisions {Wet Algemene Bepalingen] Neergelegde Verbod van Rechtsweigering [Prohibition to Deny Justice]. Available online: https://wetten.overheid.nl/BWBR0001833/2012-01-01 (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  55. Supreme Court of the United States. Marbury v Madison; [1803] 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137 (1803); Supreme Court of the United States: Washington, DC, USA, 1803. [Google Scholar]
  56. Verheyen, R.; Endres, A. Wir Alle Haben ein Recht auf Zukunft: Eine Ermutigung|Klimaschutz ist Menschenrecht—Ein Weckruf von Deutschlands Bekanntester; dtv Verlagsgesellschaft mbH & Co. KG: München, Germany, 2023. [Google Scholar]
  57. Eckes, C. Governance failures in court: How litigation constitutionalises norms on climate change mitigation. In Constitutionalism and Transnational Governance Failures; Petersmann, E.-U., Steinbach, A., Eds.; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 2024. [Google Scholar]
  58. Juliana v US, at: Juliana v. United States—Climate Change Litigation. Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/case/juliana-v-united-states/ (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  59. Rodríguez-Garavito, C. Human Rights: The Global South’s Route to Climate Litigation. Am. J. Int. Law 2020, 114, 40–44. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  60. Mak, C. Giving voice: A public sphere theory of European private law adjudication. Eur. Law Open 2023, 2, 697–723. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  61. Conclusion of Procurator General in State of the Netherlands (Ministry of Economic Affairs and Climate Policy) v Stichting Urgenda [2019], ECLI:NL:PHR:2019:887. Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/urgenda-foundation-v-kingdom-of-the-netherlands/ (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  62. Amnesty International. After UN Climate Action Summit, Urgent Action Needed by All States to Avoid Human Rights Violations on Massive Scale. Public Statement, Index Number IOR 40/1239/2019, Amnesty International 2019. Available online: http://www.amnesty.org/en/documents/ior40/1239/2019/en/ (accessed on 20 August 2025).
  63. UNEP (UN Environment Programme). Climate Change and Human Rights. Report, UNEP 2015. Available online: http://www.unep.org/resources/report/climate-change-and-human-rights (accessed on 20 August 2025).
  64. Taconet, N.; Méjean, A.; Guivarch, C. Influence of climate change impacts and mitigation costs on inequality between countries. Clim. Change 2020, 160, 15–34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  65. Cevik, S.; Jalles, J.T. For Whom the Bell Tolls: Climate Change and Income Inequality. IMF Work. Pap. 2022, 2022, 27. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  66. Lindvall, D. Climate Change and the Endurance of Democracy; Taylor & Francis: Abingdon, UK, 2024. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  67. World Inequality Lab. Climate Inequality Report 2023, Fair Taxes for a Sustainable Future in the Global South. Available online: https://wid.world/news-article/climate-inequality-report-2023-fair-taxes-for-a-sustainable-future-in-the-global-south/ (accessed on 20 August 2025).
  68. General Court, Case T-330/18 Carvalho and Others v EP and Council EU:T:2019:324. Available online: https://curia.europa.eu/juris/document/document.jsf?text=&docid=214164&pageIndex=0&doclang=en&mode=lst&dir=&occ=first&part=1&cid=4401175 (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  69. European Court of Justice, Case C-565/19 Carvalho v EP and Council EU:C:2021:252. Available online: https://curia.europa.eu/juris/document/document.jsf?text=&docid=239294&pageIndex=0&doclang=en&mode=req&dir=&occ=first&part=1&cid=4398435 (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  70. General Court, Case T 141/19 Peter Sabo v EP and Council ECLI:EU:T:2020:179. Available online: https://curia.europa.eu/juris/document/document.jsf?text=&docid=226323&pageIndex=0&doclang=en&mode=lst&dir=&occ=first&part=1&cid=4401175 (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  71. European Court of Justice, Case C-297/20 P Sabo and Others v EP and Council ECLI:EU:C:2021:24. Available online: https://curia.europa.eu/juris/document/document.jsf?text=&docid=236737&pageIndex=0&doclang=EN&mode=lst&dir=&occ=first&part=1&cid=4401175 (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  72. Eckes, C. “It’s the democracy, stupid!” in defence of KlimaSeniorinnen. ERA Forum. 2025, 25, 451–470. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  73. UNFCCC. Nationally Determined Contributions Under the Paris Agreement; FCCC/PA/CMA/2022/4; Synthesis Report; UNFCC: Bonn, Germany, 2022; Available online: https://unfccc.int/ndc-synthesis-report-2022 (accessed on 20 August 2025).
  74. Savaresi, A. Climate Change Litigation: The Role of International Law. Camb. Int. Law J. 2024, 13, 286–299. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  75. Kanitkar, T.; Mythri, A.; Jayaraman, T. Equity assessment of global mitigation pathways in the IPCC Sixth Assessment Report. Clim. Policy 2024, 24, 1129–1148. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  76. German Advisory Council on the Environment (Sachverständigenrat fur Umweltfragen—SRU). Available online: https://www.umweltrat.de/EN/home/home_node.html (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  77. Pont, Y.R.D.; Meinshausen, M. Warming assessment of the bottom-up Paris Agreement emissions pledges. Nat. Commun. 2018, 9, 4810. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  78. Thomson v. Minister for Climate Change Issues, High Court of New Zealand Wellington Registry (2017). Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/thomson-v-minister-for-climate-change-issues/ (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  79. Mathur v. Ontario, Superior Court of Justice of Ontario (2020); Lawyers for Climate Action NZ Incorporated v The Climate Change Commission, High Court of New Zealand (2022). Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/mathur-et-al-v-her-majesty-the-queen-in-right-of-ontario/ (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  80. Daniel Billy et al. v. Australia, UN Human Rights Committee (2022). Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/petition-of-torres-strait-islanders-to-the-united-nations-human-rights-committee-alleging-violations-stemming-from-australias-inaction-on-climate-change/ (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  81. Milieudefensie et al. v. Royal Dutch Shell. Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/milieudefensie-et-al-v-royal-dutch-shell-plc/ (accessed on 20 August 2025).
  82. Higher Regional Administrative Court [Oberverwaltungsgericht], Deutsche Umwelthilfe v Germany (building sector) OVG 11 A 11/22, decision of 30 November 2023. Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/wp-content/uploads/non-us-case-documents/2024/20240201_19185_decision.pdf (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  83. Higher Regional Administrative Court [Oberverwaltungsgericht], Deutsche Umwelthilfe v Germany (transport sector) OVG 11 A 27/22, decision of 30 November 2023. Available online: https://www.duh.de/fileadmin/user_upload/download/Projektinformation/Klimaschutz/Klimaklagen/2024_02_02_beA_OVG_Urteil_geschw%C3%A4rzt.pdf (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  84. Regional Court [Landgericht], Barbara Metz et al. (Deutsche Umwelthilfe) v. Wintershall Dea AG. Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/barbara-metz-et-al-v-wintershall-dea (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  85. Regional Court [Landgericht], Kaiser et al. (Greenpeace) v. Volkswagen AG. Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/kaiser-et-al-v-volkswagen (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  86. Regional Court Munich I [Landgericht], Deutsche Umwelthilfe v. Bayerische Motoren Werke AG (BMW). Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/deutsche-umwelthilfe-duh-v-b (accessed on 20 August 2025).
  87. Regional Court [Landgericht], Barbara Metz et al. (Deutsche Umwelthilfe) v. Mercedes-Benz AG, 17 O 789/21, decision of 21 June 2022. Available online: https://climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/deutsche-umwelthilfe-duh-v-mercedes-benz-ag/ (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  88. Constitutional Complaint by Greenpeace and Germanwatch. Available online: https://www.greenpeace.de/publikationen/Verfassungsbeschwerde_final_0.pdf (accessed on 20 August 2025).
  89. Minnerop, P.; Rostgaard, I. In Search of a Fair Share: Article 112 Norwegian Constitution, International Law, and an Emerging Inter-Jurisdictional Judicial Discourse in Climate Litigation. Fordham Int. Law J. 2021, 44, 847–920. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  90. Eckes, C. Strategic Climate Litigation before National Courts: Can European Union Law be used as a Shield? Ger. Law J. 2025, 25, 1022–1042. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  91. Lafont, C. Democracy Without Shortcuts: A Participatory Conception of Deliberative Democracy; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2019. [Google Scholar]
  92. Winter, G. Plaumann withering: Standing before the EU General Court underway from distinctive to substantial concern. Eur. J. Leg. Stud. 2023, 15, 85–123. [Google Scholar]
  93. Eckes, C. KlimaSeniorinnen Requires the EU to Set a 2040 Target of at Least 90% Reduction Domestically. European Law Blog, 2025. Available online: https://www.europeanlawblog.eu/pub/okmpmqpy/release/1 (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  94. Eckes, C. EU accession to the ECHR: Between autonomy and adaption. Mod. Law Rev. 2023, 76, 254–285. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  95. Dutch Supreme Court [Hoge Raad] Nyugat [1959], 6 March 1959, NJ 1962. Available online: https://www.hogeraad.nl/ (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  96. German Federal Constitutional Court [Bundesverfassungsgericht], Decision of 14 Oct. 2004, 2 BvR 1481/04—(Görgülü; ECHR decision). Available online: https://www.bundesverfassungsgericht.de/SharedDocs/Entscheidungen/EN/2004/10/rs20041014_2bvr148104en.html (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  97. German Federal Constitutional Court [Bundesverfassungsgericht], Decision of 4 May 2011, 2 BvR 2365/09; 2 BvR 740/10; 2 BvR 2333/08; 2 BvR 1152/10; 2 BvR 571/10—(Preventive Detention). Available online: https://www.bundesverfassungsgericht.de/SharedDocs/Entscheidungen/EN/2011/05/rs20110504_2bvr236509en.html (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  98. Cassel, D. Does International Human Rights Law Make a Difference. Chic. J. Int. Law 2001, 2, 121–135. Available online: https://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1122&context=cjil (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  99. Letsas, G. Two Concepts of the Margin of Appreciation. Oxf. J. Leg. Stud. 2006, 26, 705–732. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  100. ECtHR. Rules of the Court; edition of 23 June 2023. Available online: https://www.echr.coe.int/documents/d/echr/rules_court_eng (accessed on 20 August 2025).
  101. Greenpeace Netherlands v Netherlands (Bonaire case) ECLI:NL:RBDHA:2024:14834. Available online: https://uitspraken.rechtspraak.nl/details?id=ECLI:NL:RBDHA:2024:14834 (accessed on 20 August 2025).
  102. Eckes, C.; Kammeringer, C.; Coenders, A. Democratie en vertegenwoordiging van het algemeen belang. Ned. Juristenblad 2025. [Google Scholar]
  103. European Court of Human Rights. Mullner v. Austria App no. 18859/21 (ECtHR, 1 July 2024). Available online: https://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng?i=001-235058 (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  104. Advisory Opinion of the International Tribunal of the Law of the Sea (ITLOS) of 21 May 2024. Available online: https://itlos.org/fileadmin/itlos/documents/cases/31/Advisory_Opinion/C31_Adv_Op_21.05.2024_corr.pdf (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  105. Eckes, C. Judicial Control of the European Union and the Member States Trade and Investment Relations. In The Dynamics of Separation of Powers in the European Union; Eckes, C., Leino-Sandberg, P., Ghavanini, A., Eds.; Bloomsbury Publishing: London, UK, 2024. [Google Scholar]
  106. International Court of Justice (ICJ). Separate opinions of Judge Charlesworth. Advisory Opinion of 23 July 2025. Available online: https://www.icj-cij.org/sites/default/files/case-related/187/187-20250723-adv-01-08-en.pdf (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  107. International Court of Justice (ICJ). Separate opinions of Judge Aurescu. Advisory Opinion of 23 July 2025. Available online: https://www.icj-cij.org/sites/default/files/case-related/187/187-20250723-adv-01-11-en.pdf (accessed on 25 August 2025).
  108. Kuh, K. The Legitimacy of Judicial Climate Engagement. Ecol. Law Q. 2019, 46, 731–764. [Google Scholar]
  109. Sulyok, K. Science and Judicial Reasoning; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2020. [Google Scholar]
  110. Dover, S. Sustainability: Demands on Policy. J. Public Policy 1997, 16, 303–318. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  111. Fiorino, D. Can Democracy Handle Climate Change? John Wiley & Sons: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 2018.
  112. Brennan, J. Against Democracy; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
  113. Shearman, D.; Smith, J.W. The Climate Change Challenge and the Failure of Democracy; Bloomsbury Publishing USA: New York, NY, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
  114. Benvenisti, E.; Harel, A. Embracing the Tension Between National and International Human Rights Law: The Case for Discordant Parity. Int. J. Const. Law 2017, 15, 36. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  115. Hirschl, R. The Judicialization of Politics. In The Oxford Handbook of Political Science; Goodin, R., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2011; p. 256. [Google Scholar]
  116. Habermas, J. Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy; MIT Press: Cambridge, UK, 1996; p. 84. [Google Scholar]
  117. Sartori, G. Constitutionalism: A Preliminary Discussion. Am. Political Sci. Rev. 2013, 56, 853. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  118. Dutch Parliament, Parliamentary Question and Answers of the Cabinet Relating to KlimaSeniorinnen. Available online: https://www.tweedekamer.nl/kamerstukken/kamervragen/detail?id=2024Z12035&did=2024D34379 (accessed on 20 August 2025).
  119. Expertenrat für Klimafragen. German Council of Experts on Climate Change. Available online: https://expertenrat-klima.de/en/publikationen/ (accessed on 20 August 2025).
  120. Solarenergie-Fördervereins Deutschland e.V. (SFV) and Bund für Umwelt und Naturschutz Deutschland e.V. (BUND), background paper. Available online: https://www.bund.net/fileadmin/user_upload_bund/publikationen/klimawandel/klimaschutz-menschenrecht-klima-verfassungsbeschwerde-bund-sfv.pdf (accessed on 20 August 2025).
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Eckes, C. Climate Constitutionalisation in Europe—After KlimaSeniorinnen and the ICJ’s Advisory Opinion. Climate 2025, 13, 186. https://doi.org/10.3390/cli13090186

AMA Style

Eckes C. Climate Constitutionalisation in Europe—After KlimaSeniorinnen and the ICJ’s Advisory Opinion. Climate. 2025; 13(9):186. https://doi.org/10.3390/cli13090186

Chicago/Turabian Style

Eckes, Christina. 2025. "Climate Constitutionalisation in Europe—After KlimaSeniorinnen and the ICJ’s Advisory Opinion" Climate 13, no. 9: 186. https://doi.org/10.3390/cli13090186

APA Style

Eckes, C. (2025). Climate Constitutionalisation in Europe—After KlimaSeniorinnen and the ICJ’s Advisory Opinion. Climate, 13(9), 186. https://doi.org/10.3390/cli13090186

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop