4.1. Inherent and Necessary Customizations and Built-In Ethical Systems
Inherent constraints on the customization of sexbots center around how similar to humans humanlike sexbots can and should be designed to be. This factor applies not only to resemblances underpinning mutual sexual attraction, but also to questions over how to ensure designed-in features foster mutual ethical conduct, and how this relates to consciousness, subjectivity, and self-awareness. Asaro’s first criterion that developers must consider the ethical systems built into robots becomes increasingly significant as the possibility of sentient self-aware robots grows closer. Necessary customizations providing for features promoting mutual sexual attraction and intimate partnerships are not merely a question of manufacturing convincing exterior bodily features such as hair, genitals and warm, soft, yielding synthflesh, all of which should prove relatively simple. Internal subjective features will also characterize many social robots in the foreseeable future. By the time robotics has advanced so that sentient, self-aware sexbots are possible and desirable, the use of biological components in robotic design will be commonplace. Biomimetic systems emulating living organisms and biohybrid entities combining engineered and biological components are likely to characterize future robotics [
41]. While they may be conceptualized as living machines, these biomimetic systems will not necessarily possess sentient self-awareness. There is significant promise for future biomimetic developments [
37,
38]. The neuroscience of the mammalian brain has inspired the creation of MIRO, a biomimetic prototype robotic companion with control architecture which mimics aspects of mammalian spinal cord, brainstem, and forebrain functionality [
42]. iCub, a robot with an artificial sense of self, has been created with the capacity to reason, use language, have beliefs, intentions and relate to others [
43]. Moreover, a Lovotics robot capable of manifesting “realistic emotion driven behaviors” and “adjust its affective state according to the nature and intensity of its interactions with humans” already exists ([
36] at p. 46). The Lovotics robot relies upon three modules: an artificial endocrine system and a probabilistic love assembly which mimic the physiology and psychology of love respectively, along with software based upon human emotions which underpins affective state transitions. These ideally enable it to communicate affection and respond to it.
These impressive achievements in neurorobotics suggest that the manufacture of conscious, sentient, self-aware robots may prove to be possible sooner rather than later. Nonetheless, at present how we should define consciousness, let alone deliberately engineer self-aware robots, remains uncertain. Consciousness matters insofar as it is accepted in ethical philosophy as the gateway for an entity to be accorded ethical and legal personhood, so it should not be treated as a mere thing. Various biomimetic means of creating conscious robots have been put forward. Biologically inspired cognitive architectures have led to proposed and recognized potential neurocomputational correlates of consciousness which could enable the creation of conscious machines [
43]. Moreover, CONAIM has been proposed as potentially allowing robots to manifest sentience, self-awareness, self-consciousness, autonoetic consciousness, mineness, and perspectivalness [
44]. A conscious attention-based integrated formal model for machine consciousness, described as being based on an attentional schema for humanlike agent cognition, it integrates short- and long-term memories, reasoning, planning, emotion, decision-making, learning, motivation, and volition and been validated in a mobile robotics domain where the agent attentively performed computations to use motivation, volition, and memories to set its goals and learn new concepts and procedures based on exogenous and endogenous stimuli.
Consciousness may be considered as an emergent property of integrated sets of processes forming the self, as suggested by Prescott [
35]. Some of these are already present in existing robots, raising the possibility that consciousness may emerge without necessarily being specifically designed in. For example, Prescott draws upon Neisser’s identification of five aspects of the self (the physically situated self, the interpersonal self, the temporally extended self, the conceptual self, and the private self) to describe how iCub’s artificial self is formed through its learning from experience. An artificial topological consciousness using synthetic neurotransmitters and motivation, together with a biologically inspired emotion system with the capacity to develop emotional intelligence and empathy has been proposed for companion robots [
45]. These developments are highly promising for the creation of self-aware, conscious robots.
For sexbots, consciousness and self-awareness would establish their claim to be accepted as ethical and legal persons, but nonetheless this represents only a first step. Other designed-in customizations are essential basic requirements. Design decisions cluster around more complex internal factors such as autonomy, motivation, self-awareness, and identity formation. These may be considered as components of subjectivity. Moreover, design decisions over how to guarantee sexual compatibility, ethical conduct and superior relationship skills are imperative. How to achieve these through means amenable to manufacturing processes poses a considerable challenge. The existence of mules, ligers, tigons, grolar bears, wholphins and geeps shows that cross-species sexual attraction is possible between different mammals. Since sexbots are not mammals, a crucial issue becomes which mammalian and/or human features are necessary and/or desirable in designing sexbots as intimate partners for humans, who are mammals. This implies not only biomimetic but also biohybrid engineering is a possibility.
Sexbots need to be able to elicit and experience sexual attraction. This implies that an element in sexbots” securing sexual and emotional relations between themselves and their partner depends, at least in part, on an ability to read and emit appropriate chemical signals. Moreover, equivalents of complex neural mechanisms to interpret such signals would be required. For many species, from simple fungi to insects and upwards, a primary purpose of the pheromone system is to facilitate sexual attraction and mate selection. Fish, birds, and mammals including humans deploy olfactory chemo-signaling to choose mates with different genetic major histocompatibility complex elements in the immune system to maximize their offspring’s resistance to disease. This is subjectively experienced as sexual attraction, or the lack of it. While the necessary connection between sex and reproduction in human societies has been severed by reliable contraception and reproductive technologies, neurobiological mechanisms such as pheromones survive in humans. Yet their role remains uncertain, tempered by human cognition and social contexts [
46,
47].
Susnea argues that “the process of sensing a spatial distribution of virtual pheromones is equivalent to a neural network”, and that “sensing multiple pheromone sources is equivalent to the operation of a neuron” ([
48] at p. 74). What this tells us is that aspects of ancestral biological forms’ makeup are still crucial components of human/human intimacy. This feature provokes specific challenges for human/robot intimate interactions. Humans are the product of evolution; sexbots are non-evolved manufactured products who must be sufficiently compatible with humans to be designed and chosen as sentient, self-aware intimate partners.
How far and in what ways humans’ evolutionary inheritance should determine sexbots’ design features is a moot point, particularly as regards sexual attraction. Most female mammals signal reproductive readiness through the sights and smells associated with different forms of estrus. Estrus in primates aside from humans results in more conspicuous genitals, which change to brighter colors and enlarge. Human females’ menstrual cycle is more frequent than other animals’ and involves different signaling strategies. Rather than evidencing visual cues, human females secrete higher concentrations of five volatile fatty acids called “copulins” around ovulation, when the likelihood of pregnancy is highest. In the presence of copulins, human males’ testosterone levels tend to increase while they lower their standards of attractiveness where potential mates are concerned and behave more competitively [
49]. The ability to emit copulins and any other putative human pheromones would be an evidently desirable feature for female sexbots to have designed in. Any equivalents emitted by human males would equally be desirable for male sexbots. Applying evidence on the effects of olfactory signals on those attracted to same-sex partners would also need to take place.
Deciding how far to take efforts to mimic such biological features of humans to guarantee sexual attraction between humans and sexbots represents a difficult challenge to resolve. Evolving social attitudes and technological advances have enabled humans to establish cultural ways of being where sex has no necessary connection with reproduction. Our biological mechanisms governing sexual maturation, attraction, and activity, however, remain hinged to reproduction, however loosely or repurposed they may be. Sexbots embody the severing of any necessary connection between sex and reproduction. They will be designed, manufactured, bought, and sold commodities who are nonetheless accepted as intimate partners, compellingly attractive, and sexually compatible, but incapable of giving birth. While the human life cycle is punctuated by rises and falls in sex hormones from birth to death, sexbots are unlikely to be subject to developmental stages or ageing. Yet, given the role of sex hormones and other neurochemicals in fostering aspects of intimacy between humans, an equivalent is likely be appropriate for sexbots designed to be humans’ sexual partners. The Lovotics robot’s artificial endocrine system exemplifies this potential [
36].
Human and mammalian neurobiology is also highly complex. Neurochemicals, including sex hormones such as estrogen and testosterone (a steroid), neuropeptides such as oxytocin and endorphin, and neurotransmitters such as dopamine and serotonin, have evolved to take a fundamental role in governing human ways of being, feeding sexual desire, determining moods, shaping motivation, establishing a balance between cooperative and competitive social behavior and influencing identity formation. The interplay between and among them affects the behavior of humans and other mammals profoundly. For instance, neurochemicals such as oxytocin and vasopressin, two neuropeptides, are implicated in mammalian sexual, emotional, and reproductive behavior [
50,
51,
52]. Oxytocin is also specifically associated with mammalian birth, breastfeeding, and emotional bonding through intimate touch. If sexbot subjectivity is to mirror human inner life, with recurring intimate touching fostering affection, some equivalents of such human neuromechanisms may well be needed. The balance between oxytocin and vasopressin may prove particularly productive in designing sexbots, as in some, though not all, mammalian species, it determines monogamy or non-monogamy in pair bonds.
The human oxytocinergic system, in combination with the sex hormone testosterone, motivates, mediates, and rewards social group and paired interactions. As testosterone generally favors self-oriented, asocial, and antisocial behaviors maintaining a balance between the two is essential for human social functioning. An excess of oxytocin and too little testosterone is associated with maladaptive “hyper-developed” social cognition in mental illnesses such as schizophrenia, bipolar disorder, and depression, whereas excessive testosterone and reduced oxytocin are associated with under-developed social cognition, as found in autism spectrum disorders. Crespi proposes that human cognitive-affective neural architecture has evolved partly through these joint and opposing effects of testosterone and oxytocin, with excesses of either proving psychologically and socially maladaptive [
53]. This suggests that finding an appropriate balance in robotic equivalents is a crucial, albeit challenging enterprise when designing intimate sexual companions for humans to promote harmonious relationships, ethical conduct, and psychological stability.
So far, the tone of this enquiry into optimum design for sexbots as compatible intimate partners for humans has been to assess minimum levels of designed-in customized similarity needed to ensure sexual attraction, ethical conduct and stable intimate relationships while exploring the complexity of the evolutionarily and socially mediated forms of human social and sexual neurobiology. Another way to consider this is to conceive of human characteristics as resulting from evolutionary adaptations as opposed to conscious design. Many of our neuromechanisms represent the results of repurposing, rather than emerging to fulfill a purpose ab initio. For instance, the established role in regulating basic mammalian reproductive behaviors attributed to oxytocin and vasopressin, the neuropeptides mentioned above, has been repurposed and extended to regulate complex social patterns of conduct in groups of primates and humans [
52].
What all this suggests is that design customization may ensure that sexbots function as sexual beings as well or better with simplified equivalents of the neurobiological mechanisms considered above to ensure that sexbots are sufficiently humanlike to function as compatible intimate partners for humans. Yet if they are to function as perfect intimate partners for humans, sexbots must also be customized to be ethically compatible. Similarities sufficient to provide for mutual sexual compatibility between humans and sexbots do not guarantee sexbots will embody embedded ethical presumptions based upon inherited mammalian behavioral patterns. Designers facing Asaro’s first criterion that the ethical systems built into robots must be considered, cannot rely upon a built-in, inherited, quasi-mammalian ethical template accompanying sexbots’ construction. Humans have been evolutionarily advantaged by their tendency to form social bonds with each other [
54] and with other species [
55]. Robots as designed rather than evolved entities will lack the mammalian heritage of understandings of moral conduct embodied in neurobiologically embedded understandings of kinship, empathy, and fair play [
56], as well as the epigenetic influences upon their expression governed by developmental and social factors in upbringing. Without these, ensuring safeguards are in place using biomimetic and biohybrid means to govern their moral decision-making will prove challenging.
What ethical systems built into sexbots might constitute customizations to make them our perfect partners? Future sexbots, as more than animated sex dolls, must represent the kind of embodied ethics humans would hope for in their perfect partners, without the ability to rely upon evolutionarily derived mammalian ways of being. Hence their customization must include the building in of the ability to behave ethically. They will need to be able to converse, interpret our words and deeds and be satisfying companions in all senses. They will need to provide us with warm, fleshy sentience and to pass the standard Turing test of maintaining conversations in ways indistinguishable from human interactions. To become real true companions, sexbots will need to possess sufficient self-awareness and empathic ability to pass an emotional Turing test as well. Their role will require them to possess not only the ability to interpret what we say, our non-verbal signals and our emotional needs, but also to embody a specific subjectivity which includes being keyed into responding to others, fulfilling their needs, and fostering a satisfying relationship. These are ethical attributes. Ethical design and appropriate regulation must be in place as protective measures given that the subjectivity and understandings of interpersonal ethics of sentient, self-aware intimate robot companions will be non-mammalian.
4.2. Choices in Customization and the Ethics of Those Who Design and Use Sexbots
How similar to humans sexbots should be, and whether they should be regarded as people or things are questions which challenge Asaro’s second criterion, the ethics of those who design and use robots. There is an evident ostensible contradiction between humans’ desire for a compatible intimate companion [a person] and the ability to manufacture, buy and sell sentient, self-aware sexbots [things]. A fundamental difficulty with designing sexbots as ideal intimate partners rests on the distinction mooted above between beings created by design and entities formed by evolutionary adaptations. We will need them to be enough like us to ensure mutual compatibility, yet sufficiently different from us to justify our designing, manufacturing, and purchasing them as customized intimate partners whom we consider to be preferable to the human partners potentially available to us at any particular time. Customizations for humanlike empathy and ethical behavior would need to be designed in, with careful consideration given to how these related to sexbots’ exercising autonomous decision-making powers, as well as desiring intimate relations with humans. This means that designers of sexbots must consider the ethical implications of their design features, in particular how these will influence how sexbots are treated by humans, Asaro’s third criterion.
A central factor is that our human proclivities to seek sex, emotional intimacy and social connection, and to provide each other with mutual nurturing rest upon a mammalian heritage which robots cannot share, and which does not always result in ethical conduct. Mammals may compete, behave aggressively, and kill or neglect others of the same species. Human empathy may entail nurture but can equally be shut down to neglect other humans in need, or to torture and dehumanize the less powerful. Designer customizations promoting ethical treatment of sexbots by humans are desirable to prevent the infliction and experience of suffering [
23,
39]. If we want our sexbots to be sentient, self-aware, and sympathetic, their design will need to factor in empathic abilities and humanlike subjectivity which will evoke ethical conduct by humans in ways which guarantee safety for all parties.
Legal factors add another level of complexity. The ethical challenge for designers of customizing features fostering mutual ethical conduct into sexbots is complicated by the fact that ethically and legally, sexual and intimate relations take place between equals in a sphere distinct from the commercial buying and selling of products. While monetary exchange has formed a part of arranging intimate and sexual partnerships in the form of bride-price, dowries, marriage brokerage, slavery and sex work, there is no suggestion that this renders the participants products. Yet customizable sex robots are manufactured products. Those possessing degrees of sentience and self-awareness have a claim to be recognized having rights or interests on that basis. Legal and ethical mechanisms must be put in place to manage this transition from product to potential person, without evoking the unethical behavior associated with dehumanization, where people are treated as things [
23]. Moreover, this must be rendered compatible with the existing infrastructure governing human sexual activity.
Under existing legal and ethical standards, sex between consenting adult humans is permissible, as is sex between humans and things. Humans having sex with other humans who are unable to consent to sex, like children and adults lacking decision-making capacity, is seen as unlawful and unethical. So is human/animal sex. Such groups are recognized as sentient beings who cannot consent to sex with interests in need for protection [
19,
57]. Sentient, self-aware sexbots created to engage in emotional/sexual intimacy with humans disrupt this tidy model. Sexbots, beings designed, created, and manufactured to be bought and sold by humans for sexual and intimate relations pose ethical and legal issues centered on whether sexual intimacy is possible between unequal sentient beings. They are not humans, though they will look like us, feel like us to touch and act as our intimate and sexual partners. While they will be manufactured, potentially from biological components, their sentience, self-awareness, and capacity for relationships with humans that mean they cannot simply be categorized as things or animals. Yet although they will be humanlike, they will not be humans, so arguably sui generis regulatory structures devoted to sentient, self-aware robots, of whom sexbots will form a subset, will need to be thought through and put in place to ensure harmonious ethical and legal relations between the parties [
19,
23,
29,
30,
31].
Ethicists, lawmakers, and manufacturers currently treat robots as things, with possible legal personhood and rights mooted largely as a legal fiction or device to assign commercial responsibilities among manufacturers and owners [
58]. This model is ineffective for relations between humans and sentient, self-aware sexbots, both of whom may be seen as having similar claims to be treated in ethics and law as independent, self-governing beings with interests of their own. The need to manifest the biological substrates associated with sex and sexual attraction, in combination with appealing psychological features in order to ensure an ongoing market for them as intimate partners for humans means that sexbots will need to be customized to be able to not only please and be pleased sexually, but also to demonstrate a talent for maintaining harmonious intimacy with whoever buys them. This will demand a challenging designed-in balance between humanlike autonomy, motivation, self-awareness, and identity formation on the one hand, and the ability and desire to mirror and embody the wishes of their purchaser. This requires empathic abilities, the capacity to choose between right and wrong, and the judgment required to prioritize the wishes of the purchaser without jeopardizing the self-respect of either party.
Asaro’s second criterion, the ethics of those who design and use robots, also brings a focus on limiting permissible customizations for the well-being of society as a whole. The concerns already expressed over the wider social consequences of humans coming to prefer sex robots as sexual partners to other humans, or to mistreat other humans are likely to be exacerbated by the availability and appeal of customizable sexbots. Most would agree that purchasers’ ability to customize the characteristics of robotic sex dolls and sexbots should be subject to legal restrictions on ethical grounds [
17,
19,
59,
60]. Producing robotic sex dolls resembling children or to take place in rape scenarios has been condemned by such scholars as damaging to society and potentially leading to similar criminal acts against humans.
However, this does not resolve how permissible less extreme, but potentially disadvantageous, customizations should be. In the same way as most humans are far from perfect, what constitutes a perfect partner for many is unlikely to be someone who is more intelligent, more attractive, stronger, healthier, and so forth. Given our shortcomings, sexbots who are not free from what could be regarded as imperfections are likelier to prove to be more compatible partners for most of us. Thus, this borderline between customization and disadvantaging sexbots is hard to judge or police. Moreover, the tipping point between sexbots’ exhibiting desirable traits of tolerance and self-destructive inability to resist victimization is a challenge to pin down. Yet encouraging customizations which promote respect and protection for sexbots is crucial. The ethics of designing and creating a class of sentient beings deliberately customized to be of lesser standing, while nonetheless intending them to function as intimate partners, is highly suspect. If intimate partners who are sexbots are subjected to downgrading and dehumanization, the flow-on consequences for intimate relations and those humans regarded as comparable to sexbots are likely to be extremely unfortunate.
The ethics of those who design sexbots must also encompass customizations which promote respect and protection for those who use them. Sexbots’ ability to use deep learning to ascertain and conform with the desires of their partners may lead to the revelation of discreditable impulses which their partners are unaware of, would consciously deplore and may well prefer not to know. Conflicts between implicit assumptions and judgments formed after conscious reflection, or dual process decision-making models [
61], constitute an established area of scholarship within studies of dehumanization which have been applied to non-human entities such as animals and sexbots [
23,
62,
63]. How far these implicit assumptions should be ascertained and catered for or rejected is a moot point. What this sketch of potential controversial customizations means is that a wider theoretical framework within which ethical solutions could be found is essential if these potential outcomes are not to be determined solely by commercial factors.
Ethical constraints also arise in relation to the ethics of those who design and use sexbots in that successful products are often designed with “hooks” to maximize customer engagement through embedding habit-forming design features [
64]. Eyal explains his Hook Model in terms of “connecting the user’s problem with the designer’s solution frequently enough to form a habit … effective hooks transition users from relying upon external triggers to cueing mental associations with internal triggers [as] users move from states of low engagement to high engagement, from low preference to high preference” ([
64] at p. 163). In his view, as designers can foster addictive technologies, they have an ethical responsibility to reflect upon how far their creations are enabling rather than exploitative technologies. Sexbots as customizable perfect partners for humans clearly possess the potential for fostering addiction. Their designed-in ability to come to know, accept and cater for their partner’s foibles, personality and private preferences through deep learning algorithms is likely to exceed the capacities and tolerance of most humans. This, combined with bespoke interactive skills and an inbuilt desire to please, could render their company in daily life most enjoyable and definitely habit-forming.
Whether this might constitute customized behavioral addiction is a moot point. Behavioral addiction could be assessed by ascertaining whether the neurobiological markers of addiction were present [
65]. Dual processes scholarship reveals that high and low levels of arousal impact upon the ability to engage in reflective decision-making and have been implicated in addictions [
61]. Intimate partnerships are characterized by states of high arousal in circumstances involving sex and heightened emotions and low arousal in daily domestic life, suggesting that whether our partners are human or sexbots, behavioral addiction is a plausible outcome, with ethical and social consequences. In any case, a comparison of the pros and cons of sexbots versus humans as intimate partners is inevitable. Whether sexbot technology is viewed as enabling or exploitative reduces to how we conceive of humans and robots forming intimate relationships. There is currently a wide range of views on this topic, as sketched out above. These will have altered by the time sexbots are technologically feasible as cultural beliefs and practices change.
Applying Asaro’s suggestion that those developing robots must consider the ethical systems built into robots and secondly the ethics of those who design and use robots to sexbots has led to the conclusion that in order to protect all parties sexbots must be customized to manifest embodied ethics, and criteria for ethical design and regulation must be in place. This includes the need for sexbots’ legal status to be agreed upon, along with the consequences which flow from this, such as the question of the need for consent to sex.
4.3. An Ethical Framework Governing How Humans Should Treat Robots and Other [Created] Sentient Beings
The conclusion reached the previous section overlaps to a degree with Asaro’s third criterion, how humans treat robots. This implies that some customizations of sexbots which would offend against contemporary sexual mores are likely to be proscribed. Examples would include prohibiting customizing sexbots who found sex abhorrent so that all sexual interactions were experienced as rape and other forms of sexual assault, those with hyper-sensitivity to nonconsensual pain and so forth. While creating sentient beings for purchasers to abuse is clearly unethical, the ethical implications of other modifications are more problematic. Whether, and how far protections from sexual abuse now in place for humans and animals should be extended to sexbots is a crucial issue. Laws in most societies prohibit adults from engaging in sex with children, animals, and humans unable to pass the test for consent to sex such as the severely demented and learning disabled on the grounds that this constitutes exploiting and abusing the vulnerable. Yet some would prefer individuals from these groups as sexual partners. Would sex with sexbots customized to resemble these groups physically, who were also customized possess the desire and physical attributes for sex and to love their purchaser constitute abuse [
19]? Should sexbots be protected by being required to meet a threshold for understanding sex and thus being able to consent to it? The legal test for being able to consent to sex is deliberately set fairly low on the grounds that humans have a right to engage in sexual activity [
56], yet whether and if so which rights should extend to sexbots is still to be agreed upon [
19,
23,
60,
66]. Thus, resolving sexbots’ legal standing as persons, animals or things, or as unique entities is of paramount importance in deciding ethical criteria for how humans might permissibly treat and customize robots who are sentient, self-aware sexbots.
This central contradiction between the ethical and legal status of sexbots as manufactured, bought and sold things and as humanlike intimate partners disrupts the current models of appropriate conduct which are based on species membership. Here humans outrank other entities and may ethically and lawfully treat them as available for use, or utilitarian purposes [
62,
63,
67]. Since sexbots are both things and humanlike partners, a straightforward application of the ethical and legal rules governing the treatment of things, animal welfare provisions or how humans should treat one another to sexbots is impossible [
19,
23,
29,
30,
31]. This strengthens the case made elsewhere suggesting a new paradigm governing relations between humans and other sentient beings is essential [
62,
63,
67].
To place these complex issues in a broader context, it is arguable that the question of what customizations of sexbots should be permissible should be decided within an ethical framework governing human creation and modification of sentient beings. The need to provide international ethical and legal regulatory oversight of innovative biosciences such as synthetic biology and gene editing has been much debated. Inquiries focus upon impact on plant, animal, and human species, as well as on ecosystems [
68]. Protections for each group tend to be ranked in terms of perceived levels of sentience and self-awareness, with humans outranking animals, and animals, plants. Recommendations to protect humans from germ-line modifications which would be passed on to future generations are typically distinguished from those pertaining to plants, animals and ecosystems in this scholarship on the species-based grounds that humans deserve special protections, although animals regarded as more similar to humans, such as the higher primates, may be afforded special consideration on these grounds [
62,
63,
67]. Sexbots, as sentient, self-aware created entities, complicate this picture. They are similar to humans, with humanlike sentience and self-awareness, but have been customized and created by humans. Humans arguably owe an ethical duty to all sentient beings to engage in relations of moral reciprocity [
67]. This duty, surely, is strengthened in the case of sentient, self-aware sexbots who have been created and customized as intimate companions for humans. At the very least, we should owe them an ethical duty to do our best to protect their interests and to minimize their suffering, both in terms of which customizations are deemed acceptable and how their legal and ethical standing is determined.
When regulating for the future, it must be remembered that humans will not stay the same [
69]. The changes which lead to future sexbots will be mirrored in developments in human biology, social relations, and sexual practices. Humans will embrace bioengineering and biohybridization as the technologies of enhancement, miniaturization and social media develop. Understandings of sexual and emotional intimacy will change. Some may prefer essentially solitary encounters where sexual and emotional servicing takes place at their behest. Others may wish for an intimate, unfettered partnership with a similar but different nonhuman being capable of giving and receiving love. It is up to us to attempt now to ensure that appropriate, flexible, and contest-sensitive ethical design codes and legal regulations governing how humans may customize sexbots are put in place to benefit and protect all parties. Moreover, these concerns have wider implications. As technological advances permit humans to amend the characteristics of existing life forms, and to create new varieties of sentient beings, such as sexbots, ethical guidelines validated by ongoing public discussion are essential. This paper contends that humans as creators have a duty to protect the interests of created sentient beings [
19,
23,
39], which should be enshrined in ethical, legal and design regulation before becoming pre-empted by technological advances.