Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāzī on the Existence and Nature of the Jinn
Abstract
Introduction
Historical Context
- Substance (jawhar, pl. jawāhir): an indivisible, spatially situated atomic unit.
- Accident (ʿaraḍ, pl. aʿrāḍ): a transient property that inheres in a substance.
- Body (jism, pl. ajsām): any composite of multiple substances arranged together in space.
Sources and Scope
Guiding Questions and Taxonomy
1. The Denialist View
1.1. Objection 1: The Nature of Bodies
1.2. Objection 2: The Problem of Retaliation
1.3. Objection 3: The Challenge to Prophethood
1.4. Objections 4 and 5: The Poverty of Practitioners and the Rationality of Jinn
1.5. From Neutralisation to Affirmation
2. The Immaterialist View
3. The Non-Essentialist Corporealist View
4. The Essentialist Corporealist View—Structural Independence
5. The Essentialist Corporealist View—Structural Dependence
Conclusion
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | See Q. 23:12, Q. 32:7, Q. 38:71–72, Q. 55:14, Q. 76:2, Q. 90:10, and Q. 33:72. |
2 | See Q. 21:26–27, Q. 66:6, Q. 97:4, Q. 41:31, and Q. 35:1. |
3 | See Q. 51:56, Q. 55:15, Q. 72:1–2, Q. 72:6, and Q. 72:11. |
4 | The jinn in Islamic thought do not correspond neatly to demons in Christian theology. In Christian demonology, demons are typically conceived as fallen angels, originally pure spiritual beings who rebelled against God. In Islam, by contrast, the jinn form a distinct ontological category, separate from both angels and humans. This distinction is often blurred in comparative discussions of “demonology,” which can lead to misleading equivalences. For this reason, I have chosen to retain the term jinn rather than translate it as “devils.” |
5 | The specifics of this ontology were subject to considerable debate among the schools. On Muʿtazilī positions, especially the Basran school’s account of atoms, space, and void, see Dhanani (1993) and Frank (1978, 2007). For Ashʿarī developments, see Frank (2008) and Aktaş (2021). On Māturīdī perspectives and related kalām debates, see Bulğen (2019, 2021). |
6 | |
7 | This divergence in metaphysical outlook also explains why different proofs for God’s existence were emphasised in the two traditions. The mutakallimūn, operating with an ontology in which only temporal, composite beings exist, privileged the kalām cosmological argument (dalīl al-ḥudūth). For them, the finitude of the temporal order was essential: if the world were eternal, the argument would collapse. By contrast, the falāsifa, working within a framework that admitted immaterial created entities, developed the argument from contingency (dalīl al-imkān). From this angle, even a temporally infinite world could still be conceived as contingent and dependent on a necessary existent. This distinction lay at the heart of the divide between the Neoplatonic system of Ibn Sīnā and the Ashʿarī framework of Abū Ḥāmid al-Ghazālī (d. 1111), as he set out in his Incoherence of the Philosophers (Tahāfut al-Falāsifa). See al-Ghazālī (2002). |
8 | As a case in point, in The Sublime Objectives, al-Rāzī juxtaposes the kalām cosmological argument with the contingency argument and clearly favours the latter. See al-Rāzī (2024, Vol. 1, pp. 57–328). |
9 | For specific locations, see al-Rāzī (2021, Vol. 3, pp. 359–506) for The Summative Account on Logic and Philosophy; al-Rāzī (2015, Vol. 4, pp. 48–79) for The Utmost Attainment in the Grasp of Foundational Principles of Religion; al-Kātibī (2018, Vol. 2, pp. 5–246) for The Compendium in Najm al-Dīn al-Kātibī’s (d. 675/1277) Detailed Commentary on “The Compendium”; al-Rāzī (2018, pp. 366–76) for The Book of Forty Foundational Principles of Religion; and al-Rāzī (2024, Vol. 7) for The Sublime Objectives. |
10 | The two positions are that the jinn are airy bodies or that they are immaterial souls (al-Rāzī 2024, Vol. 7, pp. 489–90). This difference does not indicate a contradiction with the five-fold taxonomy in The Great Exegesis but reflects the differing focus of the two works. |
11 | The interested reader may also consult al-Rāzī’s wider remarks in both The Great Exegesis and The Sublime Objectives in Metaphysics. For the former, see al-Rāzī (2012, Vol. 11, pp. 39–58); for the latter, see al-Rāzī (2024, Vol. 7, pp. 5–44). A condensed version of al-Rāzī’s discussion of the jinn is also found in Shihāb al-Dīn Maḥmūd al-Ālūsī’ (d. 1270/1854) Spirit of the Meanings in the Exegesis of the Mighty Qurʾān and the Seven Oft-Repeated (Rūḥ al-Maʿānī fī Tafsīr al-Qurʾān al-ʿAẓīm wa-l-Sabʿ al-Mathānī). See al-Ālūsī (2022, Vol. 27, pp. 479–82). |
12 | Although al-Rāzī refers to the work as Fī ḥudūd al-ashyāʾ, the text in question is Ibn Sīnā’s Kitāb al-Ḥudūd (Book of Definitions). The abbreviated title was sometimes used generically for works on definitions, which explains why al-Rāzī employs it here. This is an extant work. See Kennedy-Day (2003). |
13 | In Ibn Sīnā’s exegesis of the final chapter of the Qurʾān, Sūrat al-Nās (Q. 114), Ibn Sīnā comments on the verse, “from the evil of the whisperer who retreats (al-khannās)” (Q. 114:4). He explains that the whisperer (al-waswās) is not an external being but the imaginative faculty (al-quwwa al-mutakhayyila) of the animal soul, which casts suggestions into the human soul and distracts it from its orientation toward transcendent principles. The one who retreats is this same faculty withdrawing and pulling the soul toward material attachments, while the phrase “from among the jinn and humankind” (min al-jinnati wa-l-nās) (Q. 114:6) is taken to symbolise the hidden and manifest faculties of the human being. In this way, Qurʾānic references to the jinn and Satan (al-shayṭān) are reinterpreted as descriptions of internal psychological processes (Ibn Sīnā 1983, pp. 124–25). These exegetical remarks seem to support al-Rāzī’s interpretation of Ibn Sīnā based on the Treatise on the Definitions of Things. This also clarifies why, pace the forthcoming immaterialist position, the jinn cannot be assimilated into the class of immaterial beings within Avicenna’s metaphysical framework. Immaterial existence for Avicenna is confined to God, the separate intellects, the celestial souls, and the rational soul, each of which is characterised by simplicity, incorruptibility, and intellectual activity. The jinn, by contrast, are defined by appetites, passions, and deception, operations that Avicenna locates in faculties dependent on bodily organs. Since such functions presuppose matter and change, the jinn cannot qualify as immaterial substances. At most, they represent symbolic designations of psychic functions or corrupted human souls, but never genuine immaterial beings. |
14 | After this first mention of the distinction between jinn and devils, I have opted to refer only to the jinn throughout the article, except in cases where al-Rāzī explicitly uses the terms ‘devil’ (shayṭān) or ‘devils’ (shayāṭīn). This choice is made for the sake of clarity while keeping close to the wording of the text. Otherwise, all references should be understood as pertaining to the jinn. Also, see Moad (2017). |
15 | Hippocrates’ treatise is sometimes alternatively rendered in English as Climates and Regions. The work belongs to the Hippocratic corpus and examines how environmental factors such as air, water, and geography influence health and disease. |
16 | On the notion of prophetic miracles, which forms part of al-Rāzī’s discussion, see Malik and Kocsenda (2025). |
17 | When al-Rāzī speaks of whisperings as if from an external agent, he means that such thoughts cannot plausibly be reduced to the human self or its faculties. His reasoning is that people often feel repulsion toward these intrusions, and despite active resistance, they remain unable to dispel them. This rules out the human being as their true source. Nor can they be attributed to an internal faculty, since no attribute of the self can generate actions contrary to the will of the person. From this, al-Rāzī infers the necessity of another agent, one that is knowledgeable and powerful enough to produce ordered speech and impose it upon the human heart and mind. For him, this external agent is nothing other than the jinn. Thus, what might first appear as a matter of inner psychology is interpreted by al-Rāzī as rational evidence that points beyond the self to the influence of non-human intelligences (al-Rāzī 2024, Vol. 7, pp. 500–1). The inquisitive reader may wonder whether such an account could equally apply to angels. Al-Rāzī does not address this possibility directly, but the distinction is implicit: angels in Islamic theology are associated with guidance, inspiration, and obedience to God, not with intrusive, disruptive, or morally harmful whisperings. It is precisely the negative, disordered, and resisted character of these thoughts that, for al-Rāzī, makes their attribution to angels impossible and confirms their jinnic origin. This is made explicit in his exegesis, as will be made evident in Position 2: The Immaterialist View. |
18 | Al-Rāzī’s reference to the hierarchy of lower and celestial spirits anticipates his use of it in the third immaterialist model below, where the question of souls re-attaching to bodies becomes central. |
19 | |
20 | Al-Rāzī entertains the same three possibilities in The Sublime Objectives, where he outlines (i) souls that act and know without bodily instruments, (ii) souls that act and know through subtle vehicles such as portions of air or ether, and (iii) disembodied rational souls that, having been perfected in the spiritual realm, may form a new attachment to bodies resembling those they once inhabited. The discussion in the exegesis closely mirrors this three-fold scheme, though with minor variations in presentation and emphasis. See (al-Rāzī 2024, Vol. 7, pp. 489–90). |
21 | In his exegesis, al-Rāzī speaks only of the jinn attaching themselves to a portion of air. However, in The Sublime Objectives he entertains two possibilities: air as one medium, and the celestial spheres composed of aether (kurat al-athīr) as another (al-Rāzī 2024, Vol. 7, p. 489). In that context, he allows for the idea that the jinn may require bodily instruments not merely from air but also from the more refined substance of the celestial realm. In Aristotelian cosmology, aether (al-athīr) was regarded as the incorruptible fifth element that composed the heavenly spheres beyond the moon. This conception was later taken up into Ibn Sīnā’s metaphysics. Al-Rāzī’s presentation reflects yet another interesting exchange between kalām and falsafa that helped to shape the contours of post-classical kalām. |
22 | This line of reasoning reflects the views of Abū al-Barakāt al-Baghdādī (d. 560/1165), particularly as developed in his Book of Reflection on The Metaphysics of Ḥikma (al-Kitāb al-Muʿtabar fī al-Ḥikma al-Ilāhiyya), where he rejected the idea of a single shared essence for all bodies and argued instead for diversity of bodily essences. See al-Baghdādī (2012, pp. 512–18). Al-Rāzī mentions him semi-explicitly as “the companion of al-Muʿtabar” (ṣāḥib al-Muʿtabar) in The Eastern Investigations, which is a common way of indicating authorship. See al-Rāzī (1990, Vol. 2, pp. 393–98). |
23 | Abū al-Ḥasan al-Ashʿarī was the founder of the Ashʿarī school of theology, which came to represent one of the main strands of Sunnī orthodoxy. Trained initially in the Muʿtazilī tradition under Abū ʿAlī al-Jubbāʾī (d. 303/915), a leading figure of the Basran Muʿtazila who systematised doctrines of divine justice and human responsibility, al-Ashʿarī eventually broke away from his teacher and the Muʿtazilī tradition altogether. In mid-life, al-Ashʿarī articulated a theological vision that combined rational argumentation with fidelity to revelation. Of his many works, a small number survive, the most important being The Doctrines of the Islamic Sects (Maqālāt al-Islāmiyyīn), a heresiographical survey of Muslim sects and doctrines; The Book of Concise Remarks (Kitāb al-Lumaʿ), an early systematic presentation of Ashʿarī theology; and The Elucidation of the Principles of Religion (al-Ibāna ʿan Uṣūl al-Diyāna), which affirms his commitment to the doctrines of Ahl al-Ḥadīth while still engaging in rational theology. |
24 | For details on the Muʿtazilī position, one can consult the extant primary works of Qāḍī ʿAbd al-Jabbār ibn Aḥmad (d. 415/1025) and Abū Muḥammad Ibn Mattawayh (d. 469/1076). See ʿAbd al-Jabbār (1965, Vol. 11) and Ibn Mattawayh (1986, Vol. 2, pp. 239–82). For excellent secondary references, see Elkaisy-Friemuth (2006), Vasalou (2007), and Zafar (2020). |
25 | This discussion clearly cuts across and parallels the discussion of the beatific vision. See al-Rāzī (2024, Vol. 2, pp. 133–45) for his very non-Ashʿarī stance on beatific vision. |
26 | By saying that the falāsifa hold perception to be “always necessary,” al-Rāzī is pointing to their broader commitment to necessitarianism, the conviction (especially in Aristotelian and Avicennian systems) that causal connections operate with strict invariability: given the proper conditions, the effect must follow (Ibn Sīnā 2005, 2009, 2011). For them, the intelligibility of the cosmos and the very possibility of demonstrative science (ʿilm burhānī) depend on stable causal relations such as fire necessarily burning, light necessarily shining, and the presence of a dense visible object under suitable conditions necessarily producing perception. This outlook was part of their wider cosmology in which the emanation of intellects and spheres and the natural dispositions (ṭabāʾiʿ) of bodies all flowed with necessity, subject only to interfering conditions (ʿawāriḍ) but never to outright suspension. In contrast, the Ashʿarīs denied intrinsic necessity, treating causal regularities as contingent habits (ʿādāt) established by divine will, which God may uphold or interrupt at any moment. See Rayan (2004), Griffel (2009, pp. 147–74), Moad (2023), and Muhtaroglu (2025). |
References
- ʿAbd al-Jabbār, Abū al-Ḥasan. 1965. al-Taklīf (Moral Obligations Imposed by God). Edited by Muḥammad ʿAlī al-Najjār and ʿAbd al-Ḥalīm al-Najjār. Cairo: Wizārat al-Thaqāfa wa-l-Irshād al-Qawmī, al-Idāra al-ʿĀmma li-l-Thaqāfa. [Google Scholar]
- Adamson, Peter. 2007. Al-Kindī. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Aktaş, Mehmet. 2021. The Model of Universals in Kalām Atomism: On al-Juwaynī’s Theory of al-Aḥwāl. Nazariyat: Journal for the History of Islamic Philosophy and Sciences 7: 55–90. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- al-Ālūsī, Shihāb al-Dīn Maḥmūd. 2022. Rūḥ al-Maʿānī fī Tafsīr al-Qurʾān al-ʿAẓīm wa-l-Sabʿ al-Mathānī (The Spirit of the Meanings in the Exegesis of the Mighty Qurʾān and the Seven Oft-Repeated [Verses]). Beirut: Dār al-Risālah al-ʿĀlamiyyah. [Google Scholar]
- al-Baghdādī, Abū al-Barakāt. 2012. al-Kitāb al-Muʿtabar fī al-Ḥikma al-Ilāhiyya (The Book of Reflection on The Metaphysics of Ḥikma). Baghdad–Beirut: Manshūrāt al-Jamal/Al-Kamel Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- al-Bājūrī, Ibrāhīm ibn Muḥammad. 2016. Tuḥfat al-Murīd Sharḥ Jawharat al-Tawḥīd (The Seeker’s Gift: A Commentary on the Jewel of Monotheism). Edited by Aḥmad al-Shādhilī al-Azharī. ʿAmmān: Dār al-Nūr al-Mubīn li-l-Nashr wa-l-Tawzīʿ. [Google Scholar]
- al-Ghazālī. 2002. The Incoherence of the Philosophers (Tahāfut al-Falāsifa), 2nd ed. Translated, Introduced, and Annotated by Michael E. Marmura. Provo: Brigham Young University Press. [Google Scholar]
- al-Kātibī, Najm al-Dīn ʿAlī ibn ʿUmar. 2018. Al-Mufaṣṣal fī Sharḥ al-Muḥaṣṣal (The Detailed Commentary on “al-Muḥaṣṣal”). With the complete text of Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāzī’s Muḥaṣṣal Afkār al-Mutaqaddimīn wa-l-Mutaʾakhkhirīn min al-ʿUlamāʾ wa-l-Ḥukamāʾ wa-l-Mutakallimīn (The Compendium of the Opinions of the Ancients and Moderns among the Scholars, Philosophers, and Theologians). Edited by ʿAbd al-Jabbār Abū Sinīnah and Muḥammad Akram Abū Ghūsh. Introduced by Saʿīd ʿAbd al-Laṭīf Fūda. Dubai: Aslein Studies & Publication/Kalam Research & Media. [Google Scholar]
- al-Rāzī, Fakhr al-Dīn Muḥammad ibn ʿUmar. 1990. al-Mabāḥith al-Mashriqiyya fī ʿIlm al-Ilāhiyyāt wa-l-Ṭabīʿiyyāt (Eastern Investigations in Metaphysics and Physics). Edited by Muḥammad al-Baghdādī. Beirut: Dār al-Kitāb al-ʿArabī. [Google Scholar]
- al-Rāzī, Fakhr al-Dīn Muḥammad ibn ʿUmar. 2012. Al-Tafsīr al-Kabīr aw Mafātīḥ al-Ghayb (The Grand Exegesis or The Keys to the Unseen). Edited by Sayyid ʿImrān. Cairo: Dār al-Ḥadīth. [Google Scholar]
- al-Rāzī, Fakhr al-Dīn Muḥammad ibn ʿUmar. 2015. Nihāyat al-ʿUqūl fī Dirāyat al-Uṣūl (The Utmost Attainment in the Grasp of the Foundational Principles of Religion). 4 vols. Edited by Saʿīd ʿAbd al-Laṭīf Fūda. Beirut: Dār al-Dhakhāʾir. [Google Scholar]
- al-Rāzī, Fakhr al-Dīn Muḥammad ibn ʿUmar. 2018. Kitāb al-Arbaʿīn fī Uṣūl al-Dīn (The Book of Forty in the Foundational Principles of Religion). 2 vols. Edited and annotated by Aḥmad Ḥijāzī al-Saqqā. Reviewed by Abū Bakr Maḥmūd ʿAbd al-Hādī. Cairo: Al-Maktaba al-Azharīya li-l-Turāth. [Google Scholar]
- al-Rāzī, Fakhr al-Dīn Muḥammad ibn ʿUmar. 2021. Mulakhkhaṣ fī al-Manṭiq wa-l-Ḥikmah (Compendium on Logic and Philosophy). Edited by Abd Allāh Muḥammad Ismāʿīl, Aḥmad Ṣābir Muṣṭafā and Rājiḥ Hilāl. Supervised by Ḥasan al-Shāfiʿī. Cairo: Markaz Iḥyāʾ li-l-Buḥūth wa-l-Dirāsāt. [Google Scholar]
- al-Rāzī, Fakhr al-Dīn Muḥammad ibn ʿUmar. 2024. Al-Maṭālib al-ʿĀliya min al-ʿIlm al-Ilāhī (The Sublime Objectives in Metaphysics). Edited by ʿAbd Allāh Muḥammad Ismāʿīl and Muḥammad Ḍargām. Kuwait: Dār al-Ḍiyāʾ. [Google Scholar]
- al-Shimmari, Mudhi. 2021. The Physical Reality of Jinn Possession According to Commentaries on the Quran (2:275). In Islam, Migration and Jinn. Edited by Annabelle Böttcher and Birgit Krawietz. Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 65–76. [Google Scholar]
- Bulğen, Mehmet. 2019. al-Māturīdī and Atomism. ULUM Journal of Religious Inquiries 2: 223–64. [Google Scholar]
- Bulğen, Mehmet. 2021. Science and Philosophy in the Classical Period of Kalām: An Analysis Centered upon the Daqīq and Laṭīf Matters of Kalām. Kader 19: 938–67. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Burge, Stephen. 2024. Angels (malāʾika). In St Andrews Encyclopaedia of Theology. Edited by Brendan N. Wolfe. St Andrews: The University of St Andrews. Available online: https://www.saet.ac.uk/Islam/Angels (accessed on 20 August 2025).
- Davidson, Herbert A. 1992. Alfarabi, Avicenna, and Averroes, on Intellect: Their Cosmologies, Theories of the Active Intellect and Theories of Human Intellect. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dein, Simon, and Abdool S. Illaiee. 2013. Jinn and Mental Health: Looking at Jinn Possession in Modern Psychiatric Practice. The Psychiatrist 37: 290–93. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dhanani, Alnoor. 1993. The Physical Theory of Kalām: Atoms, Space, and Void in Basrian Muʿtazilī Cosmology. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Doostdar, Alireza. 2018. The Iranian Metaphysicals: Explorations in Science, Islam, and the Uncanny. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Elkaisy-Friemuth, Maha. 2006. God and Humans in Islamic Thought: Abd al-Jabbar, Ibn Sina and al-Ghazālī. Abingdon: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- El-Zein, Amira. 2009. Islam, Arabs, and the Intelligent World of the Jinn. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Frank, Richard M. 1978. Beings and Their Attributes: The Teaching of the Basrian School of the Muʿtazila in the Classical Period. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Frank, Richard M. 2007. Early Islamic Theology: The Mu’tazilites and al-Ash’ari. Edited by Dimitri Gutas. Aldershot: Ashgate Variorum. [Google Scholar]
- Frank, Richard M. 2008. Classical Islamic Theology: The Ashʿarites. Edited by Dimitri Gutas. Aldershot: Ashgate Variorum. [Google Scholar]
- Gianotti, Timothy J. 2001. Al-Ghazālī’s Unspeakable Doctrine of the Soul: Unveiling the Esoteric Psychology and Eschatology of the Iḥyāʾ. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Griffel, Frank. 2009. Al-Ghazālī’s Philosophical Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Griffel, Frank. 2021. The Formation of Post-Classical Philosophy in Islam. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hassan, Laura. 2020. Ashʿarism Encounters Avicennism: Sayf al-Dīn al-Āmidī on Creation. Piscataway: Gorgias Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn Mattawayh, Abū Muḥammad. 1986. Al-Majmūʿ fī al-Muḥīṭ bi-l-Taklīf (Compendium on Moral Responsibility). Edited by Jean Joseph Houben. Revised by Daniel Gimaret. Beirut: Dār al-Mashreq. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn Sīnā, Abū ʿAlī al-Ḥusayn ibn ʿAbd Allāh. 1983. al-Tafsīr al-Qurʾānī wa-l-Lugha al-Ṣūfiyya fī Falsafat Ibn Sīnā (Qurʾānic Exegesis and Sufi Language in the Philosophy of Ibn Sīnā). Edited by Ḥasan ʿĀṣī. Beirut: Al-Muʾassasa al-Jāmiʿiyya li-l-Dirāsāt wa-l-Nashr wa-l-Tawzīʿ. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn Sīnā, Abū ʿAlī al-Ḥusayn ibn ʿAbd Allāh. 2005. The Metaphysics of The Healing (al-Ilāhiyyāt min al-Shifāʾ). Translated, Introduced, and Annotated by Michael E. Marmura. Provo: Brigham Young University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn Sīnā, Abū ʿAlī al-Ḥusayn ibn ʿAbd Allāh. 2009. The Physics of The Healing: Books I & II (al-Ṭabīʿiyyāt Min al-Shifāʾ). Translated by Jon McGinnis. Provo: Brigham Young University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn Sīnā, Abū ʿAlī al-Ḥusayn ibn ʿAbd Allāh. 2011. The Physics of The Healing: Books III & IV (al-Ṭabīʿiyyāt min al-Shifāʾ). Translated by Jon McGinnis, and David C. Reisman. Provo: Brigham Young University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ibrahim, Bilal. 2020. Beyond Atoms and Accidents: Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāzī and the New Ontology of Postclassical Kalām. Oriens 48: 67–122. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Inati, Shams C. 1998. Soul in Islamic Philosophy. In Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Abingdon: Taylor and Francis. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kassim, Husain. 2007. Nothing Can Be Known or Done without the Involvement of Angels: Angels and Angelology in Islam and Islamic Literature. Deuterocanonical and Cognate Literature Yearbook 2007: 645–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kennedy-Day, Kiki. 2003. Books of Definition in Islamic Philosophy: The Limits of Words. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Maarouf, Mohammed. 2007. Jinn Eviction as a Discourse of Power: A Multidisciplinary Approach to Moroccan Magical Beliefs and Practices. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- MacDonald, Duncan Black. 1965. Djinn. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd ed. Leiden: Brill, vol. II, pp. 546–50. [Google Scholar]
- Majlisī, Muḥammad Taqī. 1985. Rawḍat al-Muttaqīn fī Sharḥ man lā Yaḥḍuruhu al-Faqīh (The Garden of the Godfearing in Commentary on Man Lā Yaḥḍuruhu al-Faqīh), 2nd ed.Edited by Ḥusayn Mūsawī Kirmānī and ʿAlīpanh Ishtihārdī. Qom: Muʾassasa-yi Farhangī Islāmī Kūshānpūr. [Google Scholar]
- Malik, Shoaib A. 2023. Defending ‘Islam and Evolution: Al-Ghazālī and the Modern Evolutionary Paradigm’. Theology and Science 21: 745–80. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Malik, Shoaib A., and Karim Kocsenda. 2025. Understanding Miracles in Ashʿarī Theology: A Systematic Presentation. Journal of Islamic Philosophy 16: 174–98. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Moad, Edward. 2017. The Jinn and the Shayatin. In Philosophical Approaches to Demonology. Edited by Benjamin W. McCraw and Robert Arp. New York: Routledge, pp. 137–55. [Google Scholar]
- Moad, Edward Omar. 2023. Coherence of the Incoherence: Between al-Ghazali and Ibn Rushd on Nature and the Cosmos. Piscataway: Gorgias Press. [Google Scholar]
- Muhtaroglu, Nazif. 2025. Ibn Sīnā and al-Ghazālī on Causality as Necessary Connection, and Occasionalism. Theology and Science 23: 628–39. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nünlist, Tobias. 2021. Demonic Beings: The Friends and Foes of Humans. In Islam, Migration and Jinn. Edited by Annabelle Böttcher and Birgit Krawietz. Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 17–43. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Olomi, Ali A. 2021. Jinn in the Qur’an. In The Routledge Companion to the Qur’an. Edited by George Archer, Maria M. Dakake and Daniel A. Madigan. Abingdon: Routledge, pp. 330–41. [Google Scholar]
- Rassool, G. Hussein. 2019. Evil Eye, Jinn Possession, and Mental Health Issues: An Islamic Perspective. Abingdon: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Rašić, Dunja. 2024. Bedeviled: Jinn Doppelgangers in Islam and Akbarian Sufism. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rayan, Sami. 2004. Al-Ghazali’s Use of the Terms ‘Necessity’ and ‘Habit’ in his Theory of Natural Causality. Theology and Science 2: 255–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rothenberg, Celia E. 2004. Spirits of Palestine: Gender, Society, and Stories of the Jinn. Lanham: Lexington Books. [Google Scholar]
- Sabra, Abdelhamid I. 2009. The Simple Ontology of Kalām Atomism: An Outline. Early Science and Medicine 14: 68–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Ṣadr, Muḥammad. 2007. Mā Warāʾ al-Fiqh (Beyond Jurisprudence), 3rd ed. Beirut: Al-Muḥibbīn li-l-Ṭibāʿa wa-l-Nashr. [Google Scholar]
- Shihadeh, Ayman. 2012. Classical Ashʿarī Anthropology: Body, Life and Spirit. The Muslim World 102: 433–77. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Shihadeh, Ayman. 2015. Al-Ghazālī and Kalām: The Conundrum of His Body-Soul Dualism. In Islam and Rationality: The Impact of al-Ghazālī. Papers Collected on His 900th Anniversary. Edited by Frank Griffel. Leiden: Brill, vol. 2, pp. 113–41. [Google Scholar]
- Vasalou, Sophia. 2007. Subject and Body in Baṣran Muʿtazilism, or: Muʿtazilite Kalām and the Fear of Triviality. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 17: 267–98. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Wessel, Felix. 2021. Tipping the Scales Toward an Islamic Spiritual Medicine: Ibn Qayyim al-Jawziyya on Jinn and Epilepsy. In Islam, Migration and Jinn. Edited by Annabelle Böttcher and Birgit Krawietz. Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 45–63. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wisnovsky, Robert. 2003. Avicenna’s Metaphysics in Context. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wisnovsky, Robert. 2004. One Aspect of the Avicennian Turn in Sunnī Theology. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 14: 65–100. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Yosefi, Maxim. 2019. The Origins of the Traditional Approach towards the Jinn of Poetic Inspiration in Tribal Arab Culture. Proceedings of the Seminar for Arabian Studies 49: 353–63. [Google Scholar]
- Zafar, Abdul Basit. 2020. The Historical Account of ʿAbd al-Jabbār al-Hamadānī’s Physicalist Conception of the Human Soul. Ondokuz Mayıs Üniversitesi İlahiyat Fakültesi Dergisi 48: 483–504. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Malik, S.A. Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāzī on the Existence and Nature of the Jinn. Religions 2025, 16, 1141. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16091141
Malik SA. Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāzī on the Existence and Nature of the Jinn. Religions. 2025; 16(9):1141. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16091141
Chicago/Turabian StyleMalik, Shoaib Ahmed. 2025. "Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāzī on the Existence and Nature of the Jinn" Religions 16, no. 9: 1141. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16091141
APA StyleMalik, S. A. (2025). Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāzī on the Existence and Nature of the Jinn. Religions, 16(9), 1141. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16091141