Rethinking Moral Responsibility: The Case of the Evil-Natured Tyrants in Confucian Thought
Abstract
1. Introduction
2. Evil-Natured Tyrants and the Problem of Divine Punishment
Come, you multitudes. Listen to my words. It is not I, a little child, who dared to call myself a King and created chaos. [King Jie] of Xia had many sins. Heaven ordered that he be executed.格爾眾庶,悉聽朕言,非台小子,敢行稱亂!有夏多罪,天命殛之。
As the sins of [King Zhou] of Shang filled [the world], Heaven ordered that he be slain. If I disobeyed Heaven, my sin would equal [his].商罪貫盈,天命誅之。予弗順天,厥罪惟鈞。
When [good ministers like] Yu, Ji, and Xie helped [the sage-kings] Yao and Shun to do good, they did so. [But] when [bad people like] Gun and Huan Dou sought to help them do evil, [Yao and Shun] executed them. Those who can be helped to do good but not to do evil are called [people of] “highest wisdom.” [In contrast,] King Jie and Zhou killed [the good ministers] Guan Longfeng and Bigan when they wished to help them do good. [But] when the [bad advisors like] Yu Xin and the Marquis of Chong helped them do evil, they did so. Those who can be helped to do evil but not to do good are called the “lowest folly.” The Duke Huan of Qi became a hegemon with Guan Zhong’s assistance but fell into disorder when aided by Shu Diao. Those who can be helped do both good and evil are called “average people.”譬如堯舜,禹、稷、镨與之為善則行,鯀、讙兜欲與為惡則誅。可與為善,不可與為惡,是謂上智。桀紂,龍逢、比干欲與之為善則誅,于莘、崇侯與之為惡則行。可與為惡,不可與為善,是謂下愚。齊桓公,管仲相之則霸,豎貂輔之則亂。可與為善,可與為惡,是謂中人。
The Master said: Only those of the highest wisdom and those of the lowest folly do not change.子曰:「唯上知與下愚不移。」
3. The Problem of Will Under Unequal Conditions: A Neo-Confucian Dilemma
Human nature is fundamentally good, [but] why are there those who cannot change? Speaking of human nature, everyone is good, [but] speaking of [one’s] talent, there are those of the lowest folly who “do not change.” The so-called “lowest folly” is of two kinds: those who injure themselves and those who abandon themselves. If a person truly regulates oneself with goodness, then there is nothing that cannot be changed. Even the most benighted and foolish can make gradual progress. Only those who injure themselves deny [this possibility] by disbelief, while those who abandon themselves sever [this opportunity] by not doing it… When the sage [i.e., Confucius] spoke of the “lowest folly”, he was referring to those who have cut themselves from goodness.人性本善,有不可移者何也?語其性則皆善也,語其才則有下愚之不移。所謂下愚有二焉:自暴自棄也。人苟以善自治,則無不可移,雖昏愚之至,皆可漸磨而進也。惟自暴者拒之以不信,自棄者絕之以不為⋯聖人以其自絕於善,謂之下愚。
Yang Yinshu asked: Cheng Yi said, “Speaking of one’s talent, there are those of the lowest folly who do not change.” This does not seem to agree with Mencius’ saying “It is not the case that there are differences in [individuals’] talent that Heaven bestowed upon them.”楊尹叔問:「伊川曰『語其才則有下愚之不移』,與孟子『非天之降才爾殊』語意似不同?」
There is naturally a slight difference between what Master Mencius and Master Cheng said. Mencius saw only that human nature is good and thus regarded [even] one’s talent as good. He did not understand that individuals all differ in what is called the “endowment of qi….” Mencius, having seen the goodness of human nature, just grasped the principles in its basic foundations and did not further contemplate the origins of good and evil below that level or know of the individual differences in the so-called “endowment of qi.”孟子之說自是與程子之說小異。孟子只見得是性善,便把才都做善,不知有所謂氣稟各不同。⋯孟子已見得性善,只就大本處理會,更不思量這下面善惡所由起處,有所謂氣稟各不同。
People’s endowments of qi vary in clarity and turbidity. There are those above average and those below. In relation to the Way, some are born knowing and act with ease; others must learn and act with effort. Those at the lowest end must apply one hundred efforts for every one by others, or one thousand for every ten.人之氣質,清濁粹駁。有中人以上,中人以下。其於道,有生知安行,學知利行,其下者,必須人一己百,人十己千。
While it is out of one’s control and has nothing to do with one’s will that one is born with and in the impure qi, clearly, for Wang, it is not the functioning of such impure qi that causes the will’s being lacking; rather, it is the will’s being lacking that allows the functioning of the impure qi, and so as soon as one firms up one’s will, the impure qi will not be able to function and one will cease to be selfish.
4. Confucian Recognition of Moral Luck and Limits of Moral Responsibility
Someone who was an officer in a concentration camp might have led a quiet and harmless life if the Nazis had never come to power in Germany. And someone who led a quiet and harmless life in Argentina might have become an officer in a concentration camp if he had not left Germany for business reasons in 1930.
To be of stable minds without stable livelihoods—only a gentleman can do it. As for the common people, without stable livelihoods, they cannot have stable minds. When truly without a stable mind, they will be self-indulgent, unruly, wicked, and wasteful in that there would be nothing that one would not do. And once they have fallen into committing crimes, they are sought after and punished. This is [like capturing] people in a net. When a humane person is on the throne, how could [the government] capture people in such a way? (Mencius 1A.7)無恆產而有恆心者,惟士為能。若民,則無恆產,因無恆心。苟無恆心,放辟,邪侈,無不為已。及陷於罪,然後從而刑之,是罔民也。焉有仁人在位,罔民而可為也?
In the past, newly assimilated people often abandoned their clans and betrayed their villages, spreading in all directions to commit acts of violence. Can this be attributed solely to a difference in their nature, and held entirely as their personal fault? It is also because we, the officials, governed them without proper methods and failed to educate them with appropriate guidance.往者新民蓋常棄其宗族,畔其鄉里,四出而為暴,豈獨其性之異,其人之罪哉?亦由我有司治之無道,教之無方。
5. The Grounds of Confucian Judgment
King Wen had no intention of attacking King Zhou, yet Heaven granted him [all under Heaven], and the people rallied to him. [This is all done] only after the circumstances were that King Zhou had to be punished. Thus, it is said, ‘he respectfully upheld Heaven’s authority, [though] the great achievement was not completed [before his death].’ However, when King Zhou was yet to be entirely evil, Heaven’s Mandate was [also] yet to be revoked. Therefore, King Wen, even while obtaining two-thirds of the [world], still served King Zhou. If King Wen had not passed away and another twelve or thirteen years had passed, with King Zhou showing no sign of repentance and Heaven’s Mandate fully withdrawn, would King Wen have been able to avoid the events at Mengjin [where his son King Wu launched his decisive campaign against King Zhou]? From this, we can see that the intentions of Kings Wen and Wu were never different; neither acted out of personal motives but only observed [the will of] Heaven and the people.文王無伐紂之心,而天與之,人歸之,其勢必誅紂而後已,故有‘肅將天威,大勳未集’之語。但紂惡未盈,天命未絶,故文王猶得以三分之二而服事紂。若使文王未崩,十二三年,紂惡不悛,天命已絶,則孟津之事文王亦豈得而辭哉?以此見文·武之心未嘗不同,皆無私意,視天與人而已。
Confucius is someone who is born with the [complete] knowledge [of the cosmic pattern]. Saying as if he reached this [stage] through learning is to encourage people of the later generations [to focus on moral cultivation.] … Confucius himself says that the steps in the advancement of one’s virtue is like this, but the sage need not be like this. He is only establishing the rules for the learners.孔子生而知之也,言亦由學而至,所以勉進後人也。⋯孔子自言其進德之序如此者,聖人未必然,但為學者立法。
6. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | The Xia, Shang, and Zhou dynasties are traditionally regarded as the “Three Dynasties” (三代), forming the earliest lineage of hereditary kingdoms to rule the Central Plains. Although the historicity of the Xia remains debated (See e.g., Nivison 2002; Shaughnessy 2009; Mair 2013), it was long accepted in traditional sources as the first dynasty, followed by the Shang, whose existence is more firmly supported by archaeological and textual evidence. The Zhou 周 dynasty (11th C.—256 BCE), which succeeded the Shang, laid the ideological foundation for much of early Chinese political and moral thought. |
2 | It seems to first appear towards the end of the Western Zhou dynasty (ca. 1050—771 BCE). See Kern (2009, pp. 149–51). |
3 | While I frame the Mandate of Heaven as a form of punishment for an individual’s actions, the classical Chinese concept is considerably more complex, encompassing not only moral judgment but also the broader maintenance of cosmic and political order. For further discussion concerning the role of Heaven in classical Chinese thought, see, for example, Schwartz (1985, pp. 50–52). |
4 | Some readers may find the term “divine” misleading, particularly given that in Confucian—especially Neo-Confucian—contexts, Heaven (tian) is not conceived as a personal God in the way the Judeo-Christian tradition envisions but rather as a cosmic principle or moral order that operates according to its own internal patterns. For this reason, I avoid using the term “divine” when directly engaging Neo-Confucian texts. Nonetheless, I retain the term in discussions of earlier periods, when the foundational narratives of dynastic succession were first formulated and Heaven was more readily imagined as a willful, quasi-personal power that judged and responded to human virtue or vice. |
5 | See, for example, Wang Chong’s (fl. 1st C CE) discussion of human nature in the “benxing [original nature] 本性” chapter of The Balance of Discourse (C. Wang 1990, pp. 134–35). Xun Yue (荀悅148—209 CE) also commented on the pure evilness of Jie and Zhou, noting that “[if, as some say,] human nature is good but emotions are evil, then Jie and Zhou would be without nature. 性善情惡,是桀紂無性.” Cf. Ch’en (1980, p. 188). |
6 | All translations of Chinese in this article are mine. |
7 | While some chapters of the Book of Documents were almost certainly written on much later dates, the chapters containing these quotes are probably from the earlier part of the Zhou dynasty. For a brief introduction to the textual history of the Documents, see Shaughnessy (1993). |
8 | |
9 | It has been shown, however, that even when Wang Chong claims that the likes of Jie and Zhou can also change for the better, there is little implication that such transformations can be self-caused (Song 2020, pp. 300–1). In other words, the apparent malleability of the tyrants’ moral tendencies that Wang admits is probably irrelevant to our discussions on the problem of free will. |
10 | Wang Chong, one of its earliest proponents, lived nearly four centuries later. |
11 | Reference to ‘self-injury’ also appears in Mencius 2A.6. For further explanation of Mencius’ position on moral failure, see Goldin (2020, pp. 92–95). |
12 | Wang Yangming’s position may be more complex than that of Cheng Yi and Zhu Xi, as he famously stated that “the mind is originally without good or evil” (無善無惡是心之體), while also identifying human nature with the substance of the mind (性, 是心之體) (S. Wang 1992, pp. 5, 117). But this should not be taken to mean that he denied the moral potential of human nature (Cai 1983, p. 125). Modern scholars like Tan Guo (2017), for example, explains this view as part of Wang’s broader effort to integrate ontological insight with moral practice. |
13 | |
14 | Novice.-Can the devil harm a man just as he wills? Monk.-Certainly not; never at all without God’s permission, and then only in the body as in the case of Job. Never can he injure a man in the soul, i.e., never can he induce him to sin unless the man consents in his heart. (Caesarius 1929, p. 353). |
15 | This passage is also cited in Huang (2018, p. 70). Huang Yong uses it to illustrate Wang’s awareness of the influence of social and political conditions on moral behavior, though he ultimately maintains that Wang upholds full moral responsibility through the will. |
16 | To be sure, the “Heaven” that Wang refers to here can hardly be the sky deity to whom King Zhou appealed in his address recorded in the Book of Documents; as noted above (n.4), by Wang’s time, the term had come to signify the normative principle inherent within human nature. Even so, it still conveyed a sense of cosmic order—a larger moral framework beyond human control—and continued to hold a “normative and religious significance, which relates in part to its early religious meaning” (Angle and Tiwald 2017, p. 43). More importantly, whether understood as the cosmic pattern, innate principle, or a deity, what remains pertinent for our purposes is the unmistakable stance reflected in Wang’s remark: that King Zhou’s downfall was a morally justified action, aligned with a higher order. |
17 | |
18 | Kantian ethics can also be read as suggesting that certain forms of mental illness—particularly those that impair one’s capacity to form intentions or engage in the exchange of reasons—undermine the very conditions for moral agency and, by extension, moral responsibility (Scholten 2016). |
References
- Angle, Stephen C., and Justin Tiwald. 2017. Neo-Confucianism: A Philosophical Introduction. Hoboken: John Wiley & Sons. [Google Scholar]
- Arpaly, Nomy. 2009. Merit, Meaning, and Human Bondage: An Essay on Free Will. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ban, Gu 班固. 1964. Hanshu [Book of Han] 漢書. 2nd reprint. With Yan Shigu 顏師古. Beijing: Zhonghua Shuju Press. [Google Scholar]
- Benn, Piers. 1999. Freedom, Resentment, and the Psychopath. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 6: 29–39. [Google Scholar]
- Caesarius. 1929. Caesarius, The Dialogue on Miracles. Translated by Henry von Essen Scott, and C. C. Swinton Bland. 2 vols, Orlando: Harcourt, Brace and Company, Available online: http://archive.org/details/caesariusthedialogueonmiraclesvol.1 (accessed on 22 May 2022).
- Cai, Renhou 蔡仁厚. 1983. Wang Yangming zhexue [Wang Yangming’s Philosophy] 王陽明哲學. Taipei: Sanmin Shuju Press. [Google Scholar]
- Cane, Anthony. 2017. The Place of Judas Iscariot in Christology. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Carleo, Robert A., III. 2020. Is Free Will Confucian? Li Zehou’s Confucian Revision of the Kantian Will. Philosophy East and West 70: 63–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ch’en, Chi-yen. 1980. Hsun Yueh and the Mind of Late Han China: A Translation of the SHEN-CHIEN. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chen, Ning. 1997. Confucius’ View of Fate (Ming). Journal of Chinese Philosophy 24: 323–59. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Cheng, Hao 程顥, and Yi Cheng 程颐. 1981. Er Cheng ji [Works of Cheng Brothers] 二程集. Edited by Xiaoyu Wang 王孝魚. 新編諸子集成. Beijing: Zhonghua Shuju Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dennett, Daniel C. 1984. Elbow Room: The Varieties of Free Will Worth Wanting. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Fingarette, Herbert. 1972. Confucius-the Secular as Sacred. New York: Harper & Row. [Google Scholar]
- Fischer, John Martin, and Mark Ravizza. 1991. Responsibility and Inevitability. Ethics 101: 258–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gao, Ruiquan 高瑞泉. 2022. Yinxian Zhi Jian: Xinxue Licheng Zhong de ‘Ziyou Yizhi’ 隐显之间:心学历程中的‘自由意志.’ [The Obscure and the Conspicuous: The Concept of Free Will in the Course of Development of Monism of Mind]. Xueshu yuekan [Academic Monthly] 学术月刊 54: 5–16. [Google Scholar]
- Goldin, Paul R. 2020. The Art of Chinese Philosophy: Eight Classical Texts and How to Read Them. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Graham, Angus Charles. 1958. Two Chinese Philosophers; Darlinghurst: Open Court Pub Co. Available online: http://archive.org/details/in.gov.ignca.28748 (accessed on 5 August 2025).
- Graham, Angus Charles. 1989. Disputers of the Tao: Philosophical Argument in Ancient China. Darlinghurst: Open Court. [Google Scholar]
- Guo, Tan 郭坦. 2017. Wang Yangming ‘siju jiao’ qianxi [New Analysis of Wang Yangming’s Four Dicta] 王陽明‘四句教’淺析. Journal of Confucian Philosophy and Culture, 139–52. [Google Scholar]
- Hansen, Chad. 1972. Freedom and Moral Responsibility in Confucian Ethics. Philosophy East and West 22: 169. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Huang, Yong. 2018. Moral Luck and Moral Responsibility. In Why Traditional Chinese Philosophy Still Matters: The Relevance of Ancient Wisdom for the Global Age. Edited by Mingdong Gu. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Inwagen, Peter Van. 1983. An Essay on Free Will. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kane, Robert. 1998. The Significance of Free Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kern, Martin. 2009. Bronze Inscriptions, the Shijing and the Shangshu: The Evolution of the Ancestral Sacrifice during the Western Zhou. In Early Chinese Religion: Part One: Shang through Han (1250 BC-220 AD). Edited by John Lagerwey and Marc Kalinowski. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Levy, Neil. 2014. Psychopaths and Blame: The Argument from Content. Philosophical Psychology 27: 351–67. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Liu, Huajun 刘华军. 2005. Ziyou yizhi yu liangzhi—Kangde yu Wang Yangming daode zhexue zhi bijiao [Free will and Innate Conscience—A Comparison of Kant’s and Wang Yangming‘s Moral Philosophy] 自由意志与良知——康德与王阳明道德哲学之比较. Beijing hangkong hangtian daxue xuebao (shehui kexue ban) [Journal of Beijing University of Aeronautics and Astronautics (Social Science Edition)] 北京航空航天大学学报(社会科学版) 4: 33–36. [Google Scholar]
- Mair, Victor H. 2013. Was There a Xià Dynasty? Sino-Platonic Papers 238: 1–39. [Google Scholar]
- Makeham, John. 2020. Transmitters and Creators: Chinese Commentators and Commentaries on the Analects. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- McCann, Hugh J., and Daniel M. Johnson. 2022. Divine Providence. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Winter 2022 ed. Edited by Edward N. Zalta and Uri Nodelman. Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2022/entries/providence-divine/ (accessed on 17 May 2025).
- McLeod, Alexus. 2018. The Philosophical Thought of Wang Chong. Berlin and Heidelberg: Springer. [Google Scholar]
- Nagel, Thomas. 2002. Moral Luck. In Mortal Questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Nienhauser, William H., ed. 1994. The Grand Scribe’s Records: The Memoirs of Pre-Han China by Ssu-Ma Ch’ien. Tsai-fa Cheng, Zongli Lu, William H. Nienhauser, and Robert Reynolds, trans. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, vol. I. [Google Scholar]
- Nivison, David S. 2002. The Xia-Shang-Zhou Chronology Project: Two Approaches to Dating. Journal of East Asian Archaeology 4: 359–66. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Qiu, Shuangcheng 邱双成, and Wancheng Gong 巩万成. 2008. Wang Yangming ‘liangzhi’ yu Kangde ‘ziyou yizhi’ bijiao [Comparison of Wang Yangming’s “Innage Knowledge” and Kant’s “Free Will”] 王阳明‘良知’与康德‘自由意志’比较. Chongqing jiaotong daxue xuebao (shehui kexue ban) [Journal of Chongqing Jiaotong University (Social Science Edition)] 重庆交通大学学报(社会科学版) 2: 61–66. [Google Scholar]
- Ramirez, Erick. 2013. Psychopathy, Moral Reasons, and Responsibility. In Ethics and Neurodiversity. Edited by Christopher D. Herrera and Alexandra Perry. Cambridge: Cambridge Scholars University. [Google Scholar]
- Sampson, Robert J., and John H. Laub. 1995. Crime in the Making: Pathways and Turning Points Through Life. London: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Scholten, Matthé. 2016. Schizophrenia and Moral Responsibility: A Kantian Essay. Philosophia 44: 205–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Schwartz, Benjamin I. 1985. The World of Thought in Ancient China. London: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Shao, Yiping 邵毅平. 2009. Lunheng yanjiu [A Research on The Balance of Discourse] 论衡研究. Shanghai: Fudan University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Shaughnessy, Edward L. 1993. Shang Shu. In Early Chinese Texts: A Bibliographical Guide. Edited by Michael Loewe. Berkeley: Society for the Study of Early China. [Google Scholar]
- Shaughnessy, Edward L. 2009. Chronologies of Ancient China: A Critique of the ‘Xia-Shang-Zhou Chronology’ Project. In Windows on the Chinese World: Reflections by Five Historians. Edited by Clara Wing-chung Ho. Lanham: Lexington Books. [Google Scholar]
- Shisan Jing Zhushu Zhengli Weiyuan Hui十三經注疏整理委員會, ed. 2000. Shangshu zhengyi [The Correct Meaning of the Book of Documents] 尚書正義. 十三經注疏. Beijing: Beijing University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Song, Yunwoo. 2020. Wang Chong’s Fatalism. Early China 43: 285–310. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Strawson, Peter. 1982. Freedom and Resentment. In Free Will. Edited by Gary Watson. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Chong 王充. 1990. Lunheng jiaoshi [The Annotated Interpretations to The Balance of Discourse] 論衡校釋. Edited by Huang Hui 黄暉. 新編諸子集成. Beijing: Zhonghua Shuju Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Shouren 王守仁. 1992. Wang Yangming quanji [The Complete Works of Wang Yangming] 王陽明全集. Shanghai: Shanghai Shuju Press. [Google Scholar]
- Watson, Gary. 2011. The Trouble with Psychopaths. In Reasons and Recognition: Essays on the Philosophy of T.M. Scanlon, 1st ed. Edited by R. Jay Wallace, Rahul Kumar and Samuel Freeman. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wilson, William Julius. 2012. The Truly Disadvantaged: The Inner City, the Underclass, and Public Policy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Young, Jock. 1999. The Exclusive Society: Social Exclusion, Crime and Difference in Late Modernity. Melbourne: SAGE. [Google Scholar]
- Zhu, Jieren 朱傑人, Yan Zuozhi 嚴佐之, and Liu Yongxiang 劉永翔, eds. 2002. Zhuzi quanshu [Complete Works of Master Zhu] 朱子全書. 27 vols, Shanghai: Shanghai Guji Press. [Google Scholar]
- Zhu, Xi 朱熹, ed. 1983. Sishu zhangju jizhu [Collected Commentaries to the Chapters and Verses of the Four Books] 四書章句集注. 新編諸子集成. Beijing: Zhonghua Shuju Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Song, Y. Rethinking Moral Responsibility: The Case of the Evil-Natured Tyrants in Confucian Thought. Religions 2025, 16, 1062. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16081062
Song Y. Rethinking Moral Responsibility: The Case of the Evil-Natured Tyrants in Confucian Thought. Religions. 2025; 16(8):1062. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16081062
Chicago/Turabian StyleSong, Yunwoo. 2025. "Rethinking Moral Responsibility: The Case of the Evil-Natured Tyrants in Confucian Thought" Religions 16, no. 8: 1062. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16081062
APA StyleSong, Y. (2025). Rethinking Moral Responsibility: The Case of the Evil-Natured Tyrants in Confucian Thought. Religions, 16(8), 1062. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16081062