3.1. Derrida and the Fetish: Meaning, Excess, and Undecidability
Derrida’s “Restitutions,” in The Truth in Painting, is a densely layered reflection on value, fetishism, and interpretation—framed through Heidegger’s famous reading of Van Gogh’s painting of peasant shoes. In order to understand how Derrida rethinks fetishism here, we must consider his references to Marx and Freud, as well as his own deconstructive practice. He is particularly concerned with the moment when an object loses its functional utility and is reabsorbed into symbolic or philosophical meaning. The shoes depicted in the painting, no longer worn or usable, become instead objects of aesthetic contemplation. But it is this very uselessness, Derrida argues, that opens up the potential for fetishization. He writes:
If one could speak here, if not of fetishization, at least of the conditions of a fetishization, both of the product and of the work, both of the shoes and of the painting, one would have to take hold of them again at the moment when the detached (relatively unstrictured) out-of-service gives rise, in its very detachment, in its dereliction or its separation, to a sort of abyssal surplus value. To a bottomless outbidding. In the form of what one might call a truth-effect. The useless gives way to a speculative exploitation. It escapes from the space of production and tends toward absolute rarity, irreplaceable uniqueness.
The moment of detachment—the object no longer in use—becomes the condition for its reattachment into a symbolic, even metaphysical economy of meaning. The shoes, displaced from their original function, are now re-inscribed as bearers of truth, as emblems of Being in Heidegger’s interpretation. Such a transformation mirrors the Freudian fetish, in which a substitute object simultaneously veils and compensates for a traumatic loss. The fetish emerges not simply to deceive, but to stabilize meaning where something has been withdrawn or is lacking.
Derrida’s reading also recalls Marx’s critique of commodity fetishism (
Derrida 1994). In capitalism, products become alienated from the labor that produced them; they appear autonomous and gain surplus value that masks their social origins. Similarly, Heidegger’s philosophical interpretation of Van Gogh’s shoes as revealing the essence of the peasant’s life is, in Derrida’s eyes, a speculative projection—an idealization that attributes metaphysical depth, meaning a supposed access to fundamental or ultimate truth, to an aesthetic artifact. In this move, Derrida sees a kind of philosophical fetishism: the shoes, stripped of function, are made to stand in for something deeper, more “authentic,” more ontologically significant.
The act of interpretation thus becomes complicit in fetishization. Heidegger’s claim that the shoes disclose Being is not a neutral observation but a reinvestment of value into detachment itself. For Derrida, fetishism is not an error to be corrected, but a structural feature of how meaning, value, and presence emerge. What appears as a “truth-effect” is precisely the speculative overinvestment in what has been rendered useless—what he calls a “bottomless outbidding” (
Derrida 1987, p. 345). The object is no longer just an object; it becomes singular, irreplaceable, elevated beyond its material existence.
For Derrida, fetishism is not just psychological (as in Freud) or economic (as in Marx), but ontological and aesthetic. It shows how our systems of value—be they interpretive, artistic, or philosophical—depend on reattaching significance to absence, disuse, or loss. For Derrida, to call this “truth” is already to have performed the fetishistic gesture. What is revealed is not Being, but the mechanism of idealization itself.
Grasping Derrida’s notion of fetishism in Glas requires moving beyond conventional views that dismiss fetishism as merely a psychological distortion or a relic of so-called primitive religion. Derrida does not treat the fetish as a simple Ersatz (artificial substitute) for a lost object, nor as a false object of devotion. Instead, he presents the fetish as a structural figure of undecidability—a condition in which a decision must be made, but no definitive criteria exist to ground it. Fetishism, for Derrida, does not merely mark a deviation from some prior truth; it discloses the structural impossibility of such truth ever being fully present or recoverable.
Derrida states that all efforts to found or to destroy religion converge on a desire to reduce fetishism: “To found or to destroy religion (the family production) always comes down to wanting to reduce fetishism” (
Derrida 1990, p. 206). But the fetish resists such reduction. It cannot simply be discarded as a false object or impure belief. The drive to unveil the “thing itself”—to expose pure presence—always fails, precisely because the fetish
interrupts that unveiling. It dramatizes the impossibility of returning to any stable, originary ground.
Central to Derrida’s formulation is the idea that the fetish is split by contraries. As he writes, “the fetish is split [
clivé] by two contrary positions” (
Derrida 1990, p. 226). This splitting is not a flaw or contradiction to be resolved; it is what gives the fetish its power. Drawing on Freud’s concept of disavowal (
Verleugnung), Derrida explains that the fetish simultaneously affirms and denies castration, presence, or loss. It is constructed “at once on the denial and on the affirmation (
Behauptung), the assertion or the assumption of castration” (
Derrida 1990, p. 210). This simultaneous contradiction forms what Derrida calls
an economy of the undecidable. That is, the fetish functions precisely because it cannot be decisively categorized or resolved. Such undecidability of the fetish is not a breakdown of meaning, but a productive structure. It fuels what Derrida describes as a “speculation on the undecidable”—a logic of play, of feints, that mimics the dialectic without resolving into synthesis. As he writes, “This speculation is not dialectical, but plays with the dialectical. The feint consists in pretending to lose, to castrate oneself, to kill oneself in order to cut [
couper] death off. But the feint does not cut it off… On this condition does the economy become general” (ibid.). Here, Derrida proposes that the fetish does not seek truth in the traditional metaphysical sense. Instead, it circulates in a
general economy, in which meaning is always deferred, bound by contradiction, and resistant to final grounding.
The distinction between
restricted economy and
general economy comes from Georges Bataille (
Bataille 1997) and helps illuminate Derrida’s understanding of the fetish. A restricted economy operates within limits: it is goal-oriented, focused on utility, efficiency, and measurable exchanges—like a business that produces and sells goods for profit. In contrast, a general economy considers the broader, excessive circulation of energy, meaning, or value that exceeds usefulness. It includes waste, sacrifice, luxury, and symbolic acts that do not serve practical ends. For example, in a potlatch ceremony, value is expressed not by saving wealth, but by giving it away or even destroying it—an act that creates social meaning through excess. The fetish does not belong to a system of use or truth; instead, it operates within a general economy where meaning arises through contradiction, excess, and undecidability. Like energy that cannot be contained, the fetish resists being reduced to a fixed symbol or simple substitute. It gains force not through clarity or stability, but through its oscillation between opposites—presence and absence, truth and illusion, loss and compensation.
The entanglement of the fetish in excess, contradiction, and undecidability is precisely why Derrida insists: “As soon as the thing itself, in its unveiled truth, is already found engaged, by the very unveiling, in the play of supplementary difference, the fetish no longer has any rigorously decidable status” (
Derrida 1990, p. 226). The unveiling of truth always already brings with it supplementarity, mediation, and spacing. There is no untouched presence; thus, the fetish cannot be reduced to a simple substitute or error. Instead, it shows that what we call the “thing itself” is never simply there—it is always produced within a differential structure of signs.
Building on the logic of undecidability and structural excess, Derrida draws a further, crucial conclusion: “If the fetish is all the more solid, has all the more consistency and economic resistance and it is doubly bound to contraries, the law is indicated in the very subtle case and in the appendix” (ibid.). In other words, the power of the fetish—its persistence and resistance to critique—comes precisely from its undecidable bond to opposing poles. The more deeply it is entangled in contradiction, the more indestructible it becomes. He continues:
The fetish’s consistency, resistance, remanence [restance], is in proportion to its undecidable bond to contraries. Thus, the fetish—in general—begins to exist only insofar as it begins to bind itself to contraries. So this double bond, this double ligament, defines its subtlest structure. All the consequences of this must be drawn. The economy of the fetish is more powerful than that of the truth—decidable—of the thing itself or than a deciding discourse of castration (pro aut contra). The fetish is not opposable. It oscillates like the clapper of a truth that rings awry [cloche].
In other words, fetishism is not something we outgrow, eliminate, or surpass; it is a structural condition for how we relate to meaning, presence, and value. This metaphor of the clapper or bell-pendulum is key: the fetish does not rest at either pole of presence or absence, but continually swings between them, never allowing closure. That is why “the fetish is not opposable.” It cannot be clearly set against the “truth” or “the real thing,” because it contaminates those very notions with supplementarity and substitution. Rather than being a mistake or corruption, the fetish marks the place where all meaning is negotiated—precariously, repeatedly, and without guarantee.
By utilizing Derrida’s understanding of the fetish, one comes to recognize that it is not merely a substitute for a lost origin or a token of false belief. The fetish is a signifier that occupies the place of a loss—without ever revealing or replacing what is missing. It exists in the space of the undecidable; it is neither presence nor absence, neither truth nor illusion, neither origin nor supplement, but something more fundamental: a structure that makes meaning possible through displacement, contradiction, and repetition. In this sense, Derrida does not simply generalize fetishism—he reveals that all meaning is structured like a fetish.
3.2. The Derridean Supplement
In Derrida’s thought, the fetish and the supplement are twin figures of substitution—each revealing absence even as they conceal it, displacing origins, and unsettling any stable sense of presence. Just as the fetish replaces the “real thing” while disavowing its loss, the supplement fills a perceived lack in the self or a system—but in doing so, it also affirms that lack. Religion and transhumanism both depend on this structure of supplementarity: they engage in a recursive process of self-corruption, becoming-other, and technical self-replacement as the very means of their survival. This self-alteration—a constitutive act of
différance—marks the unfolding of being not as identity, but as continual deferral and displacement of presence (
Derrida 1982). The supplement, in Derrida’s usage, is not merely an addition to something whole, but a necessary support that paradoxically reveals the incompleteness of what it supplements.
For Derrida, no concept, being, or institution can survive without engaging in a structure of auto-affection, which never yields a pure presence but only the trace of presence through substitution. As he writes: “the presence that it then gives itself is the substitutive symbol of another presence… this play of substitution and this symbolic experience of auto-affection… Such is the constraint of the supplement” (
Derrida 1976, p. 154). The supplement is thus not merely an additive gesture but a structural necessity: it allows something like religion, the human, or transhumanism to persist by means of what it is not—by becoming other than itself. There is no essence, no pure self, but only the survival of the name through supplementation.
According to Derrida, the supplement is dangerous. It names both lack and support, presence and deferral. It fills a void only by acknowledging the void it fills, and so, as Derrida warns, it threatens us with death even as it enables the process of life: “this presence is at the same time desired and feared… the supplement is dangerous in that it threatens us with death” (
Derrida 1976, p. 155). To supplement is to survive through a kind of loss—a becoming-technological, or becoming-prosthetic, in which one replaces part of oneself with an other, a proxy, or sign. Such an iterative process constitutes the structure of technics according to Derrida: “There is no future without everything technical, automatic, machine-like supposed by iterability” (
Derrida 2002b, p. 83). Here, Derrida introduces a spectral machine of life and death: a structure where life persists only through repetition, displacement, and sacrifice. Survival demands technical mediation. Salvation, particularly in the transhumanist context, becomes entangled with a logic of sacrificial replacement—what Derrida names autoimmunity. The future is promised not through preservation, but through prosthetic substitution: through the death of what was, to make possible what is the unconditional to-come.
The structural paradox of the supplement deepens when Derrida turns to “mechanical reproduction”: far from reducing life to literal machines, he shows how iteration introduces novelty, rupture, and unpredictability into systems of survival. Rather, he describes a structure of iteration that introduces difference, unpredictability, and novelty. In this sense, the “machine” is a figure for technics as a condition of future survival. Transhumanist discourses, with their emphasis on bodily and cognitive enhancement, prosthetic extension, and technological salvation, that Tirosh-Samuelson clearly acknowledges and is concerned about, depend on this logic. But transhumanists and Tirosh-Samuelson alike misunderstand it: they treat the supplement as mastery, ultimate truth or reality, something God-like, rather than as the opening to alterity and death.
Religion, transhumanism, and the human itself survive by way of this prosthetic machinery of supplementation. Each is “bound up with complex, quasi-mechanical and technically replicable processes” (
Armand and Bradley 2006, p. 3). Existence is prosthetic. To persist, an entity must put itself outside itself, exposing itself to the supplement, to technics, to a necessary contamination. As Derrida famously puts it, “technology has not simply added itself, from the outside or after the fact, as a foreign body… this foreign or dangerous supplement is ‘originarily’ at work and in place in the supposedly ideal interiority of the ‘body and soul’” (
Derrida 1995, pp. 244–45). Thus, life and technics are not opposed. Rather, technics haunts life from the beginning. Life is already technical: a process of self-replacement, an economy of death and repetition. As Derrida notes, “life is always already inhabited by technicisation” (
Derrida and Beardsworth 1994, p. 52). The human is not a natural whole later disrupted by machines; the human is always already prosthetic, always already distributed across biological and non-biological supports.
Religions, likewise, survive through the same structure. As Derrida states, without contemporary technologies “there could be no religious manifestation today” (
Derrida 2002b, p. 62). From sacred texts to live-streamed sermons, the religious is sustained through ever-evolving supplements. Even the Abrahamic traditions, as “religions of the book,” are inseparable from the technology of writing, inscription, and dissemination. In turn, these supplements are not neutral—they transform what they carry forward.
The operation of X without X—as in a religion without religion, or a human without humanism—clarifies this point. These are not contradictions, but ways of naming entities that persist through transformation, through the dislocation of their supposed essence. The X survives not in its original form, but through différance—by being emptied, re-inscribed, substituted, yet still recognizable in spectral form. What ensures this spectral continuity is the name: a trace that both refers and defers, that maintains identity through displacement. As Caputo puts it, “the thing itself slips away leaving nothing behind, save the name” (
Caputo 1997, p. 43). The name becomes the placeholder for what was, enabling the survival of what no longer is. Through it, we trace the transformation of religion or the human, marking their deaths and survivals through prosthetic supplements.
The supplement—like the fetish—is both prosthesis and threat, promise and loss. It opens religion, transhumanism, and the human to the future, but only through sacrifice, repetition, and the incalculable. This is the structure of what Derrida calls autoimmunity: to survive, the self must continually supplement itself—opening to the other, becoming other, and risking itself in the very process of preserving itself. For religion, or for techno-ideological worldviews like transhumanism, survival depends on the constant use of the supplement—what may also be regarded as a kind of fetish. In this way, the logic of the supplement links directly to Derrida’s messianic structure of the unconditional to-come (à venir), which names not a specific future event, but an openness to radical alterity, to what cannot be foreseen or programmed. The fetishistic supplement is what sustains this openness, keeping the future radically unpredictable by ensuring that no presence is ever complete or immune to change. In both religion and transhumanism, this structure disrupts dreams of mastery and totality, revealing survival itself as a prosthetic gesture toward the unknowable and unconditional to-come.
3.3. The Fetish and the Messianic To-Come
The logic of the fetish and the supplement, as developed by Derrida, is intimately bound to the structure of the messianic and the
à venir—the unconditional to-come. The fetish, like the supplement, emerges from a perceived lack or loss; it is both a prosthesis and a substitution, a stand-in that acknowledges absence while simultaneously disavowing it. In this sense, the fetish and the supplement never simply restore what is missing—they delay, defer, and displace it. They signal that what is desired can never be fully present, never entirely fulfilled. This deferral is precisely the movement of
différance, through which meaning and identity are never complete but are instead always becoming, always arriving,
à venir (to-come) (
Derrida 1982).
The structure of delay and non-arrival is what underpins Derrida’s notion of the
messianic without messianism—a messianicity emptied of determinate content. Just as the supplement adds only by replacing, and just as the fetish substitutes in the absence of the “real thing,” the messianic holds open the promise of a future that is unforeseeable, incalculable, and not guaranteed. It is not the coming of a particular messiah—religious, political, or technological—but the expectation of something
other, of the event, of the
arrivant whose identity is never fixed in advance. “The messianic belongs from the very beginning to the experience of faith, of believing, of a credit that is irreducible to knowledge” (
Derrida 2002b, p. 56). It is not governed by any teleological program, nor does it conform to any specific messianism—even if, as Derrida stresses, it “remains marked by the Abrahamic traditions” (ibid.).
The fetish and the supplement sustain this structure of anticipation and deferral. As Derrida writes, the supplement “adds only to replace… if it fills, it is as if one fills a void… it is not simply added to the positivity of a presence, it produces no relief” (
Derrida 1976, p. 145). The fetish, too, works by standing in for what is absent, allowing desire and belief to persist in the face of indeterminacy. Both figures refuse the closure of certainty, thereby enabling a relation to the future not grounded in foreknowledge but in an openness to the unknown, the incalculable, and the impossible. The event of the messiah, if it is to remain an event in the eyes of Derrida, must “puncture every horizon of expectation… there where one neither can nor should see coming what ought or could—perhaps—be yet to come” (
Derrida 1994, p. 213).
The supplement and the fetish thus serve as mechanisms by which the self, religion, or transhumanism maintain themselves across time—not by staying the same, but by becoming other. Their survival requires continual replacement, which is a form of death—a structural autoimmunity in which one must risk the self to preserve the self (
Derrida 2002b, pp. 82–83). In this way, the supplement is a vehicle of both preservation and transformation. It keeps open the future not by securing it in advance, as transhumanist Singularitarians attempt to do with predictive models of what could be understood as an “AI messiah,” but by resisting any final closure, any determinable arrival.
For Derrida, the future—if it is to remain truly open—must remain undecidable. As John Caputo explains, the
viens of the messiah “is not the call for a fixed and identifiable other, foreseeable and foregraspable… it does not give voice to a determinate vocation, an identifiable destined
telos” (
Caputo 1997, p. 99). The messianic promise is not fulfilled in a predetermined, and teleologically programmatic Singularity or a techno-utopia; rather, it is sustained in the same way a fetish sustains longing and desire: by standing in for what cannot yet come, or may never come, but which nonetheless animates and haunts the present. The fetish and the supplement are not errors or deviations—they are the very condition for waiting, for faith, for a future that remains unconditionally
to-come.
The logic of the fetish and the supplement, when situated within Derrida’s notion of the unconditional to-come, underscores the structure of endless deferral at the heart of the messianic. What is to come (à venir) must always remain to-come—that is, not something that can be grasped, known, or secured in advance. The danger arises when this openness is foreclosed by substituting a present object for what should remain indeterminate. To transform the promise into presence, to replace the messianic event with a determinate figure or object—be it a prophet, a machine, or a transhumanist utopian future—is to transform messianicity into idolatry. This act of transformation mirrors the very logic of idolatry Derrida warns against: freezing the flow of openness and deferral by elevating a particular presence to the status of finality. The supplement, though it stands in for what is absent, never completes the circuit—it functions only by deferring and displacing; it names a structure in which no final presence can be secured, only promised and postponed.
Even for the messiah to remain faithful to the structure of the messianic, must never fully arrive—at least not in a way that exhausts the promise of the
to-come. As soon as the messiah appears as a concrete, identifiable figure, he risks becoming an idol: an object that attempts to arrest time, to close the openness of futurity, and to install a presence where there should remain an absence. For Derrida, the messiah is the figure of the
perhaps, a future that should not be planned or programmed. This is why any attempt—religious or technological—to name or secure the future is not only an epistemological closure but an ethical failure. The figure of the “AI messiah” found in transhumanist projections often associated with the Singularity (
Kurzweil 2005,
2024), for example, becomes an idol precisely because it claims to realize the promise—to bring the future into the present and to abolish uncertainty. Such fulfillment is not salvation but foreclosure: it kills the messianic by making it visible, graspable, decidable. It closes interpretation and closes off the new and the unexpected. Against this, Derrida insists on a fidelity to the promise as promise—a promise whose truth is in its postponement, whose force lies in its inability to be fulfilled without ceasing to be itself.
Having explored the intertwined structures of the fetish, the supplement, and the messianic to-come, I move to examine how these logics manifest within contemporary transhumanist discourse. The technological promises of figures like Kurzweil, Prisco, and others can be read as fetish-objects—supplements that simultaneously expose lack and defer fulfillment. Yet, when their ambiguity is suppressed and the future is rendered certain, these fetishes risk hardening into idols. In what follows, I argue—contra Tirosh-Samuelson—that while transhumanism harbors fetishes that may become idols, so too does Judaism. Therefore, we should not assume that a technological fetish is automatically an idol, but instead examine the conditions under which ambiguity, absence, and deferral are either preserved or foreclosed.