Ziran and Continuous Orderly Transformation: New Interpretation of Ziran in Daodejing
Abstract
1. Introduction
2. Ziran Attributed to All Things and the Common People
2.1. Ziran of All Things Followed by the Dao
A Buddhist monk asked, “Since the Dao is the supreme and greatest, with nothing surpassing it, can we then say that the Dao is the highest principle and that there is nothing which the Dao itself follows as a principle?”
The Daoist replied, “the Dao is indeed the highest principle, and there is nothing that it follows as a principle.”
The monk refuted this, saying, “But the Daodejing explicitly states: ‘Humans follow the Earth, the Earth follows Heaven, Heaven follows the Dao, and the Dao follows ziran’, Why, then, do you contradict the words of the Daodejing by insisting that there is nothing the Dao follows as a principle? Moreover, if the Dao is the highest principle yet still follows something as its principle, then why claim that it is the greatest and that nothing surpasses it?”
The Daoist replied, “the Dao is ziran, and ziran is the Dao. Therefore, the Dao does not take anything else as its principle.”
The monk challenged this, asking, “If saying that the Dao follows ziran means that Ziran is identical to the Dao, then can we also say that ziran follows the Dao as its principle?”
The Daoist responded, “the Dao follows ziran, but ziran does not follow the Dao as its principle.”
All-pervading is the Great Dao! It may be found on the left hand and on the right. All things depend on it for their production, which it gives to them without assuming any proprietary claim. When its work is accomplished, it does not claim the name of having done it. It clothes all things as with a garment, and makes no assumption of being their lord. it may be named small because of its no private desire; it may be named great for helping all things return (to their root) without making any assumption of being their lord. It is through its not regarding himself great (when accomplishing its work) that it become great.(Ch. 34; Lou 1980, p. 85; see Legge 2008, p. 62)
There was something undefined and complete, coming into existence before Heaven and Earth. ……It may be regarded as the mother of all things. I do not know its name, and I give it the designation of the Dao (the Way or Course). Making an effort (further) to give it a name I call it The Great.(Ch. 25; Lou 1980, pp. 62–63.; Legge 2008, p. 46)
Lives of all things are given by the Dao and nourished by Virtue. As a result, things receive their shapes and become tools when they are completed. Therefore, all things without exception honor the Dao and exalt Virtue. This honoring of the Dao and exalting of Virtue is not the result of any ordination, but always a spontaneous tribute (mozhiming er changziran, 莫之命而常自然). Thus, it is that the Dao gives all things lives, nourishes them, brings them to their full growth, nurses them, completes them, matures them, maintains them, and overspreads them. It gives them lives and makes no claim to their possession of them; it carries them through their processes and does not vaunt its ability in doing so, it nurtures them to maturity and exercises no control over them. This is called dark virtue.”(Ch. 51; Han 2012, p. 179; Legge 2008, p. 92)
2.2. Ziran of the Common People Followed by the Ideal Ruler
3. Ziran as Orders of Lives and Their Criteria
3.1. Ziran as Internal and External Orders of the Common People’s Lives
Not to promote those of superior ability is the way to keep the common people from rivalry among themselves; not to prize things that are difficult to procure is the way to keep them from becoming thieves; not to show them what is likely to excite their desires is the way to keep their minds from disorder. Therefore, the sage’s ruling empties their minds, fills their bellies, weakens their wills, and strengthens their bones. He constantly (tries to) keeps them unprincipled in their knowing and objectless in their desires and, where there are sophists, to keep them at bay. It is simply in doing things noncoercively that everything is governed properly.(Ch. 3; Lou 1980, p. 8)
The five colors blind people’s eyes, the five notes impair people’s ears. the five flavors destroy people’s palates, the hard riding of the hunt bring disorder to people’s mind, things that are difficult to procure leads people to subvert proper conduct. Thus, the sage’s governance seeks to satisfy (the craving of) people’s belly, and not the (insatiable longing of the) their eyes. Thus, the sage’s ruling exerts his efforts to satisfy people’s belly rather their eyes.(Ch.12; Gao 1996, p. 275)
The sages said, “I do things noncoercively (wuwei, 無為), and the common people develop their life themselves (zihua, 自化); I cherish equilibrium (haojing, 好靜), and the common people form order themselves (zizheng, 自正); I am non-interfering in our governance (wushi, 無事), and the common people prosper themselves (zifu, 自富), I have no excessive desire (wuyu, 無欲), and the common people are of themselves like unworked wood (zipu, 自樸).(Ch. 57; Lou 1980, p. 280)
3.2. The Orderly Continuous Transformation of Things as the Criteria of Their Ziran
The Dao always act noncoercively and there is nothing which it does not do. Were the nobles and kings able to preserve this, all things would be able to develop their lives themselves. having developed their lives themselves, they desire to depart from this, I would realign them with a nameless scrap of unworked wood. Realigned with this nameless scrap of unworked wood, they would leave off desiring. In not desiring, they would achieve equilibrium, and all the world would form order by itself.(Ch.37; Lou 1980, pp. 90–91; see Ames and Hall 2003, p. 134)
The world is a sacred vessel, and is not something that can be ruled coercively. Those who would rule it coercively ruin it; those who would control it coercively it lose it. The course and nature of things are such that what was in front is now behind; what was warm is now freezing; what was strong is now weak; what was accumulating is now collapsing. Therefore, the sage puts away excessive effort, extravagance, and easy indulgence.(Ch. 29; Lou 1980, p. 76; Legge 2008, p. 53).
A violent wind does not last for a whole morning; a sudden rain does not last for the whole day. To whom is it that these (two) things are owing? To heaven and earth. If Heaven and Earth cannot make such actions last long, how much less can man!故(Ch. 23; Lou 1980, p. 57; Legge 2008, p. 43).
In the past, among those who attain the One (the Dao) were these: heaven attained the One and become clear; earth ttained the One and become stable……Following this line of thinking, if the heaven cling to be clear endlessly, it may well have fallen into pieces; if the earth cling to be stable endlessly, it may well have collapsed.(Ch. 39; Han 2012, p. 175).
4. Conclusions
Funding
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Although A. C. Graham has argued that the Daodejing was composed after the Zhuangzi and has dated its earliest possible compilation to around 200 BCE (Graham 1986, pp. 111–12), William Baxter and Liu Xiaogan, through a careful analysis of the rhetorical style and metrical patterns of the Daodejing, have provided compelling evidence that the Daodejing was likely compiled in the late Spring and Autumn period or the early Warring States period (Baxter 1990, pp. 233, 249; X. Liu 2007, pp. 9–14). Moreover, Roger T. Ames and David Hall have noted that Baxter and Liu’s conclusions align chronologically with the Daodejing manuscripts excavated at Guodian in the 1990s (Ames and Hall 2003, pp. 2–3). Building upon these studies, this paper maintains that Laozi and his work, the Daodejing, can be regarded as the earliest Daoist text. |
2 | Recent scholarship has engaged in considerable debate on this issue; here, I provide only the conclusion. For a more in-depth discussion, see Section 3.2. |
3 | In this paper, I adopt Roger T. Ames’s translation of wuwei as “noncoercive action”. The more prevalent translation of wuwei as “taking no action” (Lau 1963, pp. 58–59) often conveys a misleading sense of complete inaction, which obscures its true meaning. In reality, wuwei represents a distinct and essential mode of action. As Ames explains, wuwei “really involves the absence of any course of action that interferes with the particular focus of those things contained within one’s field of influence” (Ames and Hall 2003, p. 39). This interpretation is well-founded, as it aligns with the statement in Daodejing Chapter 64 that a sage “helps all things follow their ziran without engaging in any coercive action”. Edward Slingerland offers a similar perspective, though he translates wuwei as “effortless action” (Slingerland 2007, pp. 29–30), which literally emphasizes the easiness of an action as such and thus misses the political feature of wuwei in the Laozi to some extent. |
4 | In this paper, ontology is understood as the doctrine concerned with the ground of all things, which is consistent with its main meaning in the 17th century. |
5 | If we recalls that both heaven and sages (as representives of heaven) are the ideal models to be followed by all things (including people), this proposition that the Dao follows ziran theoretically breaks the hierarchical chain of emulation expressed in Chapter 25, wherein lower-order beings emulate higher-order ones, this is, “the man (or the king) follows earth, earth follow heaven, and heaven follows Dao”. By breaking this chain, Laozi asserts that although the Dao may be ontologically foundational for all things, it does not serve as a model to be followed universally in the same way as heaven and sages in Confucianism. Rather, precisely because the Dao affirms the self-sufficient value of all things, it resists becoming a paradigmatic authority demonstrated by heaven and sages in Confucianism. |
6 | There is a contextual connection between Chapter 17 and Chapter 23, as evidenced by the shared statement in both chapters that “When a ruler lacks credibility, the common people will not trust him” (Lou 1980, pp. 40, 58). |
7 | In fact, the ritual-ruling is the political expression of the authority and exemplary role played by heaven and the sages in shaping the proper way of life for all things. The sanctity and authority of ritual are precisely safeguarded by heaven and the Confucian sage, the Duke of Zhou. In this sense, Laozi’s critique of governing by ritual already implies a rejection of the patriarchal or ancestral authority central to Confucianism. This rejection simultaneously affirms the intrinsic value of all things. The ontological claim that Dao follows ziran is thus to affirm the value of all things and to challenge the authority system established by Confucian thought. |
References
- Ames, Roger T., and David Hall. 2003. Daodejing: Making This Life Significant: A Philosophical Translation. New York: Ballantine Books. [Google Scholar]
- Baxter, William. 1990. Situating the Language of the Lao-tsu: The probable Date of the Tao-te-ching. In Lao-Tsu and the Tao-te-Ching. Edited by Livia Kohn and Michael Lafargue. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Chen, Guying 陳鼓應. 2003. A Modern Commentary and Translation on Laozi 老子今註今譯. Beijing: Shangwu Yinshuguan 商務印書館. [Google Scholar]
- Chikyu, Tomohisa. 2019. Asking About the Dao: A Careful Reading of Laozi’s Thought 問道:《老子》思想細讀. Translated by Qifa Wang 王啟發, and Feng Cao 曹峰. Guilin: Guangxi Normal University Press 廣西師範大學出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Chikyu, Tomohisa 池田知久. 2009. On Lao Zhuang’s Ziran: Also on the Ideological Development of Ziran in Chinese Philosophy 論老莊的自然:兼論中國哲學“自然”觀念的研究綜述. Journal of Huan University 湖南大學學報 6: 26–37. [Google Scholar]
- Du, Zhengsheng 杜正胜. 2005. Cong Meishou Dao Changsheng: From Meishou to Longevity: Medical Culture and Chinese Ancient View of Life 從眉壽到長生——醫療文化與中國古代生命觀. Taibei: San Min Book Company. [Google Scholar]
- Gao, Ming 高明. 1996. A Proofreading and Commentary of Mawangdui Silk Version of the Laozi 帛書老子校註. Beijing: Zhonghua Shuju 中華書局. [Google Scholar]
- Graham, Angus Charles. 1986. The Origins of the Legend of Lao Tan 老聃. In Studies in Chinese Philosophy & Philosophical Literature. Singapore: The Institute of East Asian Philosophies, pp. 7–66. [Google Scholar]
- Guo, Qingfan 郭慶藩. 2012. The Collected Interpretations of Zhuangzi 莊子集釋. Beijing: Zhonghua Shuju. [Google Scholar]
- Han, Wei 韓巍. 2012. Han Dynasty Bamboo Book Collected by Peking University (Vol. 2) 北京大學藏西漢竹簡 (二). Shanghai: Shang Hai Ancient Books Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hutton, Eric L. 2014. Xunzi: The Complete Text. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ivanhoe, Philip J. 2003. The Daodejing of Laozi. Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company. [Google Scholar]
- Lao, Sze-Kwang 勞思光. 2003. Illusion and Hope: On Contemporary Philosophy and Culture 虛境與希望:論當代哲學與文化. Hong Kong: The Chinese University of Hong Kong. [Google Scholar]
- Lau, D. C. 1963. Lao Tsu Dao Te Ching. Singapore: Penguin Books. [Google Scholar]
- Legge, James. 2008. Dao Te Ching or the Dao and Its Characteristics. Auckland: The Floating Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lin, Guanghua 林光華. 2017. Independent Nature and Dependent Nature: Laozi’s Ziran and Its Modern Meaning 無待自然與有待自然:《老子》之”自然”及其當代意義. The Journal of Humanities 人文雜誌 7: 1–7. [Google Scholar]
- Liu, Linkui 劉林魁. 2018. A Collection of the Debates Between Buddhist Monks and Daoists 集古今佛道論衡. Beijing: Zhonghua Shuju. [Google Scholar]
- Liu, Xiaogan 劉笑敢. 1995. Three Meanings of Ziran in the Laozi 老子自然觀念的三種含義. Philosophical Trends 哲學動態 5: 39. [Google Scholar]
- Liu, Xiaogan 劉笑敢. 1996. A New Interpretation to the Ideas of Ziran and Wuwei in the Laozi 老子自然與無為觀念新詮. China Social Science 中國社會科學 6: 136–49. [Google Scholar]
- Liu, Xiaogan 劉笑敢. 2006. The Laozi from Ancient to the Modern Comparative Studies of the Five Versions, Including Introductory Analyses Criticisms (with Comparative Concordance) 老子古今:五種対勘與與析評引論. Beijing: China Social Science Press. [Google Scholar]
- Liu, Xiaogan 劉笑敢. 2007. Laozi: A New Research of Its Period and New Interpretation of Its Thought 老子:年代新考與思想新詮. Taibei: Dongda Chubanshe. [Google Scholar]
- Lou, Yulie 樓宇烈. 1980. A Proofreading and Interpretation to Wangbi’s Interpreatation of Laozi’s Daodejing 老子道德經註校釋. Beijing: Zhonghua Shuju. [Google Scholar]
- Luo, Anxian 羅安憲. 2019. On the Two Exclusive Meanings of Ziran 論自然的兩層排斥含義. Philosophical Research 哲學研究 2: 66–73. [Google Scholar]
- Meng, Qingnan 孟慶楠. 2016. Natural State and Governance: A Comparative Study of the Doctrines of Natural State Proposed by Different Scholars in the Pre-Qin Period. 自然與治道:先秦諸子自然狀態學說的比較研究. Journal of Yunnan University 雲南大學學報 1: 37–45. [Google Scholar]
- Slingerland, Edward. 2007. Effortless Action: Wu-Wei as Conceptual Metaphor and Spiritual Ideal in Early China. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Song, Hongbing 宋洪兵. 2015. The Idea of Ziran in the Laozi and the Hanfeizi and Its Political Meaning 老子、韓非子的“自然”概念及其政治蘊含. Jianghuai Tribune 江淮論壇 2: 80–86. [Google Scholar]
- Tadd, Miasa. 2019. Ziran: Authenticity or Authority? Religions 10: 207. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wang, Bo 王博. 2010. The Self-estraint of Power: An interpretation of Laozi’s Philosophy 權力的自我節制:對老子哲學的一種解讀. Philosophical Research 哲學研究 6: 45–55. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Ka 王卡. 1993. Heshang Gong’s Comments to Laozi Daodejing 老子道德經河上公章句. Beijing: Zhonghua Shuju. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Qingjie 王慶節. 2004. Laozi’s Idea of Ziran: Itself-so-ing and Other-ing 老子的自然觀念:自我的自己而然與他人的自己而然. Journal of Seeking Truth 求是學刊 6: 1–50. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Xianqian 王先謙. 1988. The Collected interpretations of Xunzi 荀子集解. Beijing: Zhonghua Shuju. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Yiming 王一鳴. 2022. From Noncoercive Action to Shapelessness: On the Ontological Ground of Laozi’s Political Philosophy. Religions 13: 807. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wang, Zhongjiang 王中江. 2010. Spontaneousness of Things: A Study On the Meaning of Laozi’s ‘Dao Emultaes What is Spontaneous So’ 道與事物的自然:“道法自然”實義考論. Philosophical Research 哲學研究 8: 37–47. [Google Scholar]
- Xiong, Tieji 熊鐵基, and Hongxing Chen 陳紅星. 2011. A Collection of Editions and Commentaries for the Laozi (Volume 1) 老子集成(第一卷). Beijiing: Zongjiao Wenhua Chubanshe 宗教文化出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Zheng, Kai 鄭開. 2019. A Profound Interpretation of Daoism Political Philosophy 道家政治哲學發微. Beijing: Peking University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ziporyn, Brook A. 2020. Zhuangzi: The Complete Writings. Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Wang, Y. Ziran and Continuous Orderly Transformation: New Interpretation of Ziran in Daodejing. Religions 2025, 16, 902. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16070902
Wang Y. Ziran and Continuous Orderly Transformation: New Interpretation of Ziran in Daodejing. Religions. 2025; 16(7):902. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16070902
Chicago/Turabian StyleWang, Yiming. 2025. "Ziran and Continuous Orderly Transformation: New Interpretation of Ziran in Daodejing" Religions 16, no. 7: 902. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16070902
APA StyleWang, Y. (2025). Ziran and Continuous Orderly Transformation: New Interpretation of Ziran in Daodejing. Religions, 16(7), 902. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16070902