Rethinking Black Rage in and with James Cone’s Black Theology and Black Power
Abstract
:“For it is not light that is needed, but fire; it is not the gentle shower, but thunder. We need the storm, the whirlwind, and the earthquake”—Frederick Douglass.
“The sin of American theology is that it has spoken without passion”—James Cone.
1. Introduction
2. Rage in Cone
2.1. The Significance of Rage: Emotional and Ethical
There are two significant features of the affective substructure suggested by this passage: the emotional and the ethical. Both are coordinated with concepts, such as anger, attitude, authority, anti-objectivity, and anti-neutrality. The emotional/impassioned and the ethical are co-constitutive. One is entailed in the other. They are separated for heuristic purposes.This work, then, is written with a definite attitude, the attitude of an angry black man, disgusted with oppression of black people in America and with the scholarly demand to be ‘objective’ about it. Too many people have died, and too many are on the edge of death. In fairness to my understanding of the truth, I cannot allow myself to engage in a dispassionate, non-committed debate on the status of the black-white relations in America by assessing the pro and con of Black Power. The scholarly demand for this kind of ‘objectivity’ has come to mean being uninvolved or not taking any sides.
2.2. Anger’s Appearance, Attitude and Anti-Objectivist Objectivity
2.2.1. Anger: Its Appearance and Role
Writing through his anger was Cone choosing not to be destroyed by it. The refusal to be destroyed by anger gave birth to Black theology, a new discipline, which testifies to the fact that anger does not always destroy. Anger also creates new life. “The writing of Black Theology and Black Power”, Cone notes, “was also a conversion experience. It was like experiencing the death of white theology and being born again into the theology of the black experience” (ibid., p. 48). Anger, then, created new life not only in the world of Cone—the arrival of Black theology into the world—but also in the person of Cone—the transformation of a theologian who happens to be Black into a Black theologian (J. H. Cone 1999, p. 251).By the summer of [1968], I had so much anger pent up in me that I had to let it out or be destroyed by it. The cause of my anger was not merely my reaction to the murder of Martin King. Neither was it due simply to the death of Malcolm X or the killing of so many blacks in the cities. My anger stretched back to the slave ships, the auction block, and the lynchings. But even more important were my personal encounters with racism in Bearden, Little Rock, Evanston, and Adrian.
2.2.2. Anger as Attitude
Cone’s “definite attitude” has an uncanny resemblance to Baldwin’s “special attitude”. The latter (Baldwin’s “special attitude”) comprises of a distinctive or special African (American) inflected affect, perspective, heritage, role, and deep sense of self within at least one “scheme” that is organized by modern European concepts of “race” or, more precisely, “racecraft” (See Fields and Fields 2010). This special attitude is what Baldwin himself possesses as an African American and brings particularly to European literature, music, art, history, culture, and religion. In this sense, Baldwin’s “special attitude” can be understood to inform the meaning of Cone’s “definite attitude”.11 In fact, just as Baldwin “brought to Shakespeare, Bach, Rembrandt, to the stones of Paris, to the cathedral at Chartres, and to the Empire State Building, a special attitude”, Cone later tells his reader that his first book “attempts to bring to theology a special attitude permeated with black consciousness” (J. H. Cone 1997, p. 32). Here, later in BTBP, Cone replaces “definite attitude” with Baldwin’s exact phrase, “special attitude”. Although Cone does not explicitly cite Baldwin in this passage, the striking Baldwinian resonance seems hard to deny.12I know, in any case, that the most crucial time in my own development came when I was forced to recognize that I was a kind of bastard of the West; when I followed the line of my past I did not find myself in Europe but in Africa. And this means that in some subtle way, in a really profound way, I brought to Shakespeare, Bach, Rembrandt, to the stones of Paris, to the cathedral at Chartres, and to the Empire State Building, a special attitude. These were not really my creations, they did not contain my history; I might search in them in vain forever for any reflection of myself. I was an interloper; this was not my heritage. At the same time I had no other heritage which I could possibly hope to use–I had certainly been unfitted for the jungle or the tribe. I would have to appropriate these white centuries, I would have to make them mine–I would have to accept my special attitude, my special place in this scheme–otherwise I would have no place in any scheme.
2.2.3. Anger as Anti-Objectivist Objectivity
From the beginning, Cone’s rage alerts him to the inherent dangers of white theological methods that demand “objectivity” that it is more akin to “objectivism”.13 For Cone, to be objective, from the white scholarly view, is to be dispassionate, disinterested, and disengaged. On this view, emotions, unlike reason, are generally regarded as weaker, insufficient, or invalid grounds for determining what’s objective or the truth. This kind of “objectivity” inherently grants ultimate epistemic authority not merely to “reason” for it is assumed to be a stronger and more stable ground, but also to whoever can lay claim to that reason.14 Cone, however, finds this white scholarly approach to Christian theology to be deeply troubling because, at the most fundamental level, it is morally indifferent to the suffering and death of Black people, undoubtedly, for its own “reason”.Too many people have died, and too many are on the edge of death. In fairness to my understanding of the truth, I cannot allow myself to engage in a dispassionate, non-committed debate on the status of the black-white relations in America by assessing the pro and con of Black Power. The scholarly demand for this kind of ‘objectivity’ has come to mean being uninvolved or not taking any sides.
Cone’s rage exposes the ways in which white theology masquerades as objective and value-neutral, thereby concealing its own hidden, subjective interests, and passions. Cone’s impassioned meta-philosophical analysis and criticism are not just evident in the aforementioned passage, but also across his entire corpus. One common way of characterizing Cone’s new theology and the passion with which he gave deep articulation to it can be usefully summarized by Cecil Cone, theologian and one of the fiercest critics and brother of James: “Cone’s Black Theology is threatening to many white people. Proceeding in a rational, objective manner, Cone develops his Black Theology in such a way that the sound and tone of his work becomes that of an angry black militant, not only chiding his people for their ‘hang-ups on white ways’ but unleashing the full depth of his anger against white men and their structures in society” (C. W. Cone 2003, p. 81).Although God is the intended subject of theology, God does not do theology. Human beings do theology. The importance of this point cannot be emphasized too strongly because there are white theologians (as well as others greatly influenced by their definitions of theology) who still claim an objectivity regarding theological discourse, which they consider vastly superior to the subjective, interest-laden procedures of black and other liberation theologians.15
2.3. The Moral Visions and Vexations of Anger
There are numerous aspects of this passage worth considering, not least its insight into the theoretical background of Cone’s thinking. First, it should be noted that the passage begins with “moral issues are at stake”. Whatever else is known about objectivity, what needs to be understood is that morality cannot be easily disassociated from it. Second, human feelings should not be dislodged from what counts as “objective” because they are “part of the evidence”, clues pointing to what the truth might be. Third, to exclude anger out of hand limits what can be known about the truth. Fourth, possessing feelings does not foreclose the possibility of being objective. Lastly, embracing the swaying power of emotions is less risky than living with the malpractices from misjudgments that would ensue without them.moral issues are at stake, noninvolvement and non-commitment and the exclusion of feeling are neither sophisticated nor objective, but naive and violative of the scientific spirit at its best. When human feelings are part of the evidence, they cannot be ignored. Where anger is appropriate response, to exclude the recognition and acceptance of anger, even to avoid the feeling itself as if it were an inevitable contamination, is to set boundaries upon truth itself. If a scholar who studied Nazi concentration camps did not feel revolted by the evidence no one would say he was unobjective but rather fear for his sanity and moral sensitivity. Feeling may twist judgment, but the lack of it may twist it even more.18
That the exemplars of the Christian tradition, including Jesus, “got angry” suggests that anger should not be dismissed. Cone goes so far as measuring “the importance of any study in the area of morality or religion” based upon “the emotion expressed”. It is important to recognize Cone’s metaethics and metaethical analysis, and the normative role anger plays within them. This enables him to gain a more critical foothold on the “coolness” of most theological works in his view. For Cone, those works should be regarded with some suspicion precisely because they are too cool, too dispassionate and detached. By the following year when he wrote his second book, A Black Theology of Liberation, Cone intensifies his metaethical critique of coolness.The prophets certainly spoke in anger, and there is some evidence that Jesus got angry. It may be that the importance of any study in the area of morality or religion is determined in part by the emotion expressed. It seems that one weakness of most theological works is their ‘coolness’ in the investigation of an idea. Is it not time for theologians to get upset?
White American theology, in Cone’s view, can be cool, calm, or silent in the face of human evil because it “is largely an intellectual game unrelated to the issues of life and death” (J. H. Cone 1997, p. 85).The sin of American theology is that it has spoken without passion. It has failed miserably in relating its work to the oppressed in society by refusing to confront the structures of this nation with evils of racism. When it has tried to speak for the poor, it has been so cool and calm in its analysis of human evil that it implicitly disclosed whose side it was on. Most of the time American theology has simply remained silent, ignoring the conditions of the victims of this racist society.
3. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | For one of the most relevant scholarly treatment that examines the significance of Rev. Sekou, his two books, Urban Souls and Gods, Gays, and Guns: Essays on Religion and the Future of Democracy, and his engagement with black youth culture, see (McCormack 2013, pp. 220–33). |
2 | While theological accounts of the Civil Rights Movement are important to any serious interpretation of that movement, there has been a tendency to obscure some of its “unreligious” elements (e.g., leaders, beliefs, or institutions that are generally non-religious or anti-religious) at certain historical moments and throughout the Black Freedom Movement in general, see (Marsh 2002, pp. 231–50; Chappell 2004; Dickerson 2005, pp. 217–35). For a contemporary analysis of the Black Lives Matter movement that is attentive to “unreligious” perspectives as well as to non-Christian religions like Islam, see (Lloyd 2018, pp. 215–37), and the collection of essays in (Cameron and Sinitiere 2021). |
3 | For an extensive treatment on the cognitive structures of emotions and how emotions involve judgments, see (Nussbaum 2001). |
4 | For an extensive treatment that challenges whether and to what degree African American literature is “secular” or “profane”, see (Sorett 2016). |
5 | Amiri Baraka (LeRoi Jones), as cited in (J. H. Cone 1997, p. 3). Baraka’s quote deploys heavily gendered language that I have not emphasized here. A full discussion of the way Baraka and other Black writers of this moment were thinking about gender is beyond the scope of this brief essay, but for context, see (Collins 2006, pp. 106–12). |
6 | The answer that is BTBP was indeed heard and, no less, by Amiri Baraka, the year after its publication. In reflecting about his first encounter with Baraka and vice versa, Cone writes, “Black Theology and Black Power also received a wide audience among black nationalist groups, especially the Congress of African People (CAP) which was led by Amiri Baraka (LeRoi Jones). I first Baraka in Newark and he later invited me to be one of the leaders of the religion workshop at CAP’s major meeting in Atlanta in September 1970” (J. H. Cone 1986, p. 54). |
7 | Paulo Freire as cited in (J. H. Cone 1990, p. ix). |
8 | One possible exception is the section, “Anger and Social Analysis in the Early Period” in (Burrow 1994, pp. 79–87). |
9 | It is important to note that Cone uses anger and rage interchangeably. |
10 | James Cone as cited in (Warnock 2014, p. 90). |
11 | I do not wish to overstress the connection between Baldwin’s “special attitude” and Cone’s “definite attitude”. The latter may not be fully consistent with the former with respect to how they relate to European sources. |
12 | This Baldwinian resonance might be an understatement when one considers that the year following the publication of BTBP, his 1970 article, “Black Theology and Black Liberation”, which appeared in the Christian Century magazine, Cone cites the exact aforementioned passage from Baldwin’s Notes of a Native Son in which Baldwin uses the phrase “special attitude” to describe himself as a writer. See (J. H. Cone 1970, p. 1084). |
13 | The intellectual forces or commitments that sustain the belief in and operations of objectivity can be called “objectivism”. In his Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis, Richard Bernstein defines objectivism as “the basic conviction that there is or must be some permanent, ahistorical matrix or framework to which we can ultimately appeal in determining the nature of rationality, knowledge, truth, reality, goodness, or rightness. An objectivist claims that there is (or must be) such a matrix and that the primary task of the philosopher is to discover what it is and to support his or her claims to have discovered such a matrix with the strongest possible reasons. Objectivism is closely related to foundationalism and the search for an Archimedean point. The objectivist maintains that unless we can ground philosophy, knowledge, or language in a rigorous manner we cannot avoid radical skepticism” (Bernstein 1983, p. 8). |
14 | Objectivity has not gone uncriticized by scholars, especially within the United States. See (James 1978; Dewey 1929; Rorty 2009; Bernstein 1983). |
15 | (J. H. Cone 1990, pp. xix–x). Emphasis in original. |
16 | See Bernstein’s summary and critique of “objectivism”, above footnote 13. |
17 | Here “moral objectivity” is meant to signal the title of a subsection in Kenneth Clark’s Dark Ghetto (1965) that seems to inform Cone’s critique and use of objectivity. See (Clark 1989, p. 78). Moral objectivity is also distinct from metaphysical realism. What I have in mind by moral objectivity, at a basic level, is similar to how Richard Bernstein in The Pragmatic Turn characterizes moral objectivity as offered by Hilary Putnam: It is “a normative argument about what ought to be—or, more accurately, for a state of affairs that we ought to strive to achieve” (Bernstein 2010, p. 163). |
18 | Kenneth Clark as cited in (J. H. Cone 1997, p. 2). |
19 | For more critiques of the apparent antagonism between reason and emotions, see (Solomon 1993; De Sousa 1987; Damasio 2005). |
References
- Baldwin, James. 1998. Notes of a Native Son. In Collected Essays. New York: Library of America. [Google Scholar]
- Bernstein, Richard. 1983. Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bernstein, Richard. 2010. The Pragmatic Turn. Cambridge: Polity Press. [Google Scholar]
- Burrow, Rufus, Jr. 1994. James H. Cone and Black Liberation Theology. Jefferson: McFarland & Co. [Google Scholar]
- Cameron, Christopher, and Phillip Luke Sinitiere, eds. 2021. Race, Religion, and Black Lives Matter: Essays on a Moment and a Movement. Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Chappell, David L. 2004. A Stone of Hope: Prophetic Religion and the Death of Jim Crow. Chapel Hill: The University of North Carolina Press. [Google Scholar]
- Clark, Kenneth B. 1989. Dark Ghetto: Dilemmas of Social Power, 2nd ed. Middletown: Wesleyan University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Collins, Patrica Hill. 2006. From Black Power to Hip Hop: Racism, Nationalism, Feminism. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Cone, Cecil Wayne. 2003. The Identity Crisis in Black Theology, rev. ed. Nashville: AMEC. [Google Scholar]
- Cone, James H. 1970. Black Theology and Black Liberation. Christian Century 87: 1084. [Google Scholar]
- Cone, James H. 1986. My Soul Looks Back. Maryknoll: Orbis Books. [Google Scholar]
- Cone, James H. 1990. A Black Theology of Liberation, 20th anniversary ed. Maryknoll: Orbis Books. [Google Scholar]
- Cone, James H. 1997. Black Theology and Black Power. Maryknoll: Orbis Books. [Google Scholar]
- Cone, James H. 1999. Looking Back, Going Forward: Black Theology as Public Theology. In Black Faith and Public Talk: Critical Essays On James H. Cone’s Black Theology and Black Power. Edited by Dwight N. Hopkins. Maryknoll: Orbis Books. [Google Scholar]
- Damasio, Antonio R. 2005. Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain. London: Penguin. [Google Scholar]
- De Sousa, Ronald. 1987. The Rationality of Emotion. Cambridge: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dewey, John. 1929. The Quest for Certainty: A Study of the Relation of Knowledge and Action. New York: Minton, Balch & Company. [Google Scholar]
- Dickerson, Dennis C. 2005. African American Religious Intellectuals and the Theological Foundations of the Civil Rights Movement, 1930–1955. Church History 74: 217–35. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dorrien, Gary J. 2001. The Making of American Liberal Theology: Crisis, Irony and Postmodernity, 1950-2000. Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press. [Google Scholar]
- Douglass, Frederick. 1996. What To the Slave Is the Fourth of July? In The Oxford Frederick Douglass Reader. Edited by William L. Andrews. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Fields, Karen E., and Barbara J. Fields. 2010. Racecraft: The Soul of Inequality in American Life. New York: Verso. [Google Scholar]
- Grier, William H., and Price M. Cobbs. 1992. Black Rage. New York: Basic Books. [Google Scholar]
- Han, Yuri. 2015. Leaving the Pulpit for the Streets of Ferguson. The Chicago Reporter, February 2. Available online: http://chicagoreporter.com/leaving-the-pulpit-for-the-streets-of-ferguson/ (accessed on 2 February 2015).
- hooks, bell. 1995. Killing Rage: Ending Racism. New York: H. Holt and Co. [Google Scholar]
- Jackson, Lawrence P. 2011. The Indignant Generation: A Narrative History of African American Writers and Critics, 1934–1960. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- James, William. 1978. Pragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking; The Meaning of Truth. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Jennings, William James. 2010. The Christian Imagination: Theology and the Origins of Race. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lloyd, Vincent. 2018. How Religious Is #BlackLivesMatter? In Humanism and the Challenge of Difference. Edited by Anthony Pinn. London: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Lorde, Audre. 1984. The Uses of Anger: Women Responding to Racism. In Sister Outsider: Essays and Speeches. Trumansburg: Crossing Press. [Google Scholar]
- Marsh, Charles. 2002. The Civil Rights Movement as Theological Drama-Interpretation and Application. Modern Theology 18: 231–50. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McCormack, Michael Brandon. 2013. The Preachers and the Powers That Be(t): Black Youth, Moral Panic and Public Theological Discourse in the Era of Hip-Hop. Ph.D. dissertation, Vanderbilt University, Nashville, TN, USA. [Google Scholar]
- Mead, Margaret, and James Baldwin. 1971. A Rap On Race. Philadelphia: J. B. Lippincott. [Google Scholar]
- Nussbaum, Martha C. 2001. Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Pickett, Xavier. 2018. Honoring the Sacred Fire of James Cone. Black Perspectives, September 5. Available online: https://www.aaihs.org/honoring-the-sacred-fire-of-james-cone/ (accessed on 5 September 2018).
- Roberts, J. Deotis. 1993. Black Theology in the Making. In Black Theology: A Documentary History, Volume 1: 1966–1979, 2nd ed. Edited by James H. Cone and Gayraud S. Wilmore. Maryknoll: Orbis Books. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rorty, Richard. 2009. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, 30th ed. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sloterdijk, Peter. 2010. Rage and Time: A Psychopolitical Investigation. Translated by Mario Wenning. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Solomon, Robert C. 1993. The Passions: Emotions and the Meaning of Life. Indianapolis: Hackett Pub. Co. [Google Scholar]
- Sorett, Josef. 2016. Spirit in the Dark: A Religious History of Racial Aesthetics. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Warnock, Raphael G. 2014. The Divided Mind of the Black Church: Theology, Piety, and Public Witness. New York: NYU Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Pickett, X. Rethinking Black Rage in and with James Cone’s Black Theology and Black Power. Religions 2025, 16, 675. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16060675
Pickett X. Rethinking Black Rage in and with James Cone’s Black Theology and Black Power. Religions. 2025; 16(6):675. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16060675
Chicago/Turabian StylePickett, Xavier. 2025. "Rethinking Black Rage in and with James Cone’s Black Theology and Black Power" Religions 16, no. 6: 675. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16060675
APA StylePickett, X. (2025). Rethinking Black Rage in and with James Cone’s Black Theology and Black Power. Religions, 16(6), 675. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16060675