The Christology of Bonaventure
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Trinitarian Framework
The reduction is not merely a technique—it is the soul of the return to God; and since all knowledge depends on principles, and principles are born within us under the regulating and motivating action of divine ideas, the certitudes which seem most capable of being self-sufficient are necessarily linked, by means of the first principles, with the eternal reasons and their divine foundation. To reduce, then, the truth of any judgment amounts to bringing back this judgment, from condition to condition, to the eternal reasons upon which it is established
3. Christ in the Trinity
4. Historical Christology
If the historical thesis is true—i.e., if God deigned to restore an understanding of the essence of time through, specifically, the figurae sacramentales (Bonaventure 1993; Ratzinger 2020)44 and the witness of St. Francis of Assisi as alter Christus (Vloebergs 2016, pp. 1–29)— any thesis of “doctrinal development” inferred from such a thesis would have to, on one hand, give careful attention to the historical situation of Bonaventure (viz., the Joachimite controversy over the Eternal Gospel, which claimed a new Age of the Holy Spirit and abrogated the Age of the Son), and, on the other hand, it would have to be properly and assiduously faithful to the concept of revelation deepening across time. In this latter sense, one would have to concede at the very least that whatever understanding of Scriptural revelation there will be in the end times, it would have to be one of supreme wisdom such that nature, grace, and glory are all in agreement. Indeed, whatever this understanding is, Bonaventure says by means of it “the monsters of heresies will flee from the use of wisdom” (Bonaventure 2018, p. 238).45The universal Principle of things, being supremely wise, observes the order of wisdom in all its works, but should do so especially in those matters related to their consummation. In this way, the beginning will be in harmony with the intermediate stage, and the intermediate stage with the end; thus, in the perfectly fitting order of all things, the ordering wisdom, the goodness, and the loftiness of that first supreme Principle will clearly be seen
5. Christocentric Epistemology
One of the benefits of Bonaventure’s theory is that it tidily explains why Christ in the Gospels does not know everything the Father knows.61 While the soul of Christ is super excellent and super dignified in its unity of created and uncreated and is supremely graced by a beholding of divine wisdom in ecstasy, and communicates the Father’s will as the Father communicates it, still the comprehensive knowledge of the soul of Christ is limited and so sense-experience plays an important role in the divine plan (Bonaventure 2005a, 2005b, pp. 171–72).62 How then shall one understood the whole soul of the knowledge of Christ? Some scholars have introduced the concept of “unibility” for acquiring an understanding of the operative mode of unity between created (body) and uncreated (soul) (Osborne 1999, pp. 227–50). A few other theories may be considered (see Table 1).But even the loftiest creature is limited in its substance, power, and action. Furthermore, the human mind, though it does not find rest except in the infinite Good, cannot comprehend that Good—since, to use the term ‘comprehension’ in its full meaning, the infinite cannot be comprehended by the finite. And so it follows that in the second way of knowing, that is by virtue of his glorified humanity, the intellect of Christ grasps everything within the reach of finite nature beatified by the infinite Good to which it is supremely united. Hence, the intellect of Christ knows the finite by actually comprehending it; but the infinite it does not know except perhaps through a knowledge that is due to an infused habit or even ecstatic. For neither in its knowing nor in any other way can the created mind be equated with the Word
6. Christ as Mediator, Redeemer, and Restorer
The reason why it was necessary—though not “absolutely” so—that a redeemer redeem humankind is due mainly to the corrupting penalties of sin, the “universal infection”, which is incompatible with the blessed life and cannot be remedied by natural power alone (Bonaventure 2005a, pp. 158–59, 285; 2018, pp. 175–78).76 However, the contamination of original sin conveys the fault of creatures, not God. Humans could have freely chosen not to sin, as they were created capable of choosing good. As Bonaventure clarifies: “[I]f God had created humankind in such wretchedness from the very beginning, he would have violated his own love and righteousness by oppressing his own handiwork with such miseries through no fault of its own” (Bonaventure 2005a, p. 110).77 Hence, if God had created humans in a state of misery, it would have violated the First Principle as utterly good.Since it was proper that Christ the mediator possess innocence and the bliss of enjoying the vision of God while still being mortal and capable of suffering, he had to be at one and the same time a pilgrim on earth and one possessing the beatific vision. Something of both states existed in him: thus, it is said that he assumed the sinlessness of the state of innocence, the mortality of the state of fallen nature, and the perfect blessedness of the state of glory
The effects of the passion of Christ, the Mediator and Redeemer, brought about an “entirely sufficient” restoration, “for it embraced those in heaven, on earth, and under the earth” (Bonaventure 2005a, p. 165).83 To those under the earth, the satisfaction of Christ’s passion granted pardon; to those on earth, grace; and to those in heaven, glory (Bonaventure 2005a, loc. cit.). Christ’s passion granted pardon to those on the earth through grace, and as grace is directed to glorification—viz., because “[It] is the function of grace (gratia) to order our mind to due worship of the First Principle” (Bonaventure 2005a, pp. 197, 282)84 and the glory of the mind is in the worship of the First Principle—so the pardoning by grace is directed to the glorification of worship. This is why Bonaventure regards both the passion and resurrection of Christ as essential to pardon and its effects: as justice demands reward (or punishment) in soul and body together—just as matter seeks or is inclined towards form (Bonaventure 2018, pp. 96, 351)85—so too “the restoration of grace demands that the entire body be likened to Christ, whose dead body had to rise again because it was inseparably united to his Godhead” (Bonaventure 2005a, p. 283).86And so, choosing to enjoy the fruit of the forbidden tree, [Adam] sinned, yielding to his own lust and rising up in pride; through his sin, the whole human race was infected, forfeiting immortality and incurring inevitable death. And so, to heal humankind by an appropriate remedy, God-made-human willed to be humiliated and to suffer on a tree. As an antidote to universal infection, he willed to suffer a passion that was all-embracing; as an antidote to lust, a passion most bitter; as an antidote to pride, a passion most ignominious; as an antidote to a death deserved but unwilled, he chose to suffer a death undeserved but freely willed
7. Christ and Creation: A Bonaventurian Perspective on Animals in the New Creation
Various topics are presented in this passage: glory, hope, creation, freedom, futility, will, adoption, and so forth. The hope presented is a “hope-for” the glory of creation in God. The glory presented is that glory, which is to be revealed by means of some revelation of the children of God, and in this glorious revelation, which involves the redemption of bodies, “creation itself will be set free from its enslavement.” Elsewhere, in 2 Corinthians, Paul writes, “So if anyone is in Christ, there is a new creation: everything old has passed away; look, new things have come into being! All this is from God, who reconciled us to himself through Christ …”.97 Numerous other biblical passages refer to the concept of a “new creation” or of God making “all things new” in Christ.98 But what does all this mean for, say, animals?I consider that the sufferings of this present time are not worth comparing with the glory about to be revealed to us. For the creation waits with eager longing for the revealing of the children of God, for creation was subjected to futility, not of its own will, but by the will of the one who subjected it, in hope that the creation itself will be set free from its enslavement to decay and will obtain the freedom of the glory of the children of God. We know that the whole creation has been groaning together as it suffers together the pains of labor, and not only the creation, but we ourselves, who have the first fruits of the Spirit, groan inwardly while we wait for adoption, the redemption of our bodies. For in hope we were saved. Now hope that is seen is not hope, for who hopes for what one already sees? But if we hope for what we do not see, we wait for it with patience.96
And elsewhere, in the Itinerarium, Bonaventure writes the following:Vegetative and sensitive beings do not possess the power of perpetual life and eternal duration that is reserved to the higher state, and so their whole substance will be consumed. However, they will be preserved as ideas; and in a certain manner they will survive also in their likeness, humankind, who is kin to creatures of every species. And so one can say that all things will be made new and, in a certain sense, rewarded in the renovation and glorification of humanity
In the above passage from the Itinerarium, Bonaventure is suggesting that God decreed that creatures represent (spiritual) things according to a variety of senses (sign, effect, figure, likeness, etc.), for various reasons (prophetic, angelic, ecclesial), and all for the sake of drawing creation into Christ (eternal Wisdom). If we take both passages together in the context of a “new creation”, animals preserved merely as ideas, or as concepts or principles, seems appropriate. After all, “a proper act must be accomplished in its proper matter”, and as only the nature of the rational and immortal soul demands such, only this soul would require a body in the necessity of nature.105 But what about animals surviving, “in the renovation and glorification of humanity”, according to a “certain manner” of likeness? This is not in the order of natural necessity, but it nevertheless seems fitting (congruous) for animals to survive in, by, or through humans according to some manner of likeness. But by which manner of likeness?[C]reatures of this visible world signify the invisible things of God: partly, because God is the Origin, Exemplar, and End of every creature,—and every effect is a sign of its cause; every example is a sign of its exemplar; and every way a sign of the end to which it leads,--partly by their own power of representation; partly because of their prophetic prefiguring; partly because of angelic operation; partly also by virtue of supernatural institution. For every creature is by its very nature a figure and likeness of eternal Wisdom, but especially a creature that has been raised by the Spirit of Prophecy to prefigure spiritual things in the book of Scriptures; and more especially those creatures in whose figures it pleased God to appear through the ministry of the angels; and, finally, and most especially, any creature which He chose to institute for the purpose of signifying, and which not only has the character of sign in the ordinary sense of the term, but also the character of sacrament as well
Because of Christ, sensitive beings can become proper objects of the hope of glory for the freedom of creation by participation in an emanation of God through a medium (humans) in substantia, in corporeitate, in animalitate (Bonaventure 2018, pp. 132–33, 207–8, 390; Bonaventure 1993, p. 25; Bonaventure 2005a, pp. 280–81; Gracy 2024).110 By sight, Christ made a way for animals to draw near to the form of beauty in humanity; by smell or hearing, he made a way for them to draw near its sweetness; and by taste or touch, he made a way for them to draw near its wholesomeness. Animals do not know this intellectually, but by sense, will, and a generic power of imagination.[A]fter [his birth], [the Virgin] perhaps wrapt Him in her veil, and placed Him in the manger. And now the ox and ass, with bended knees, and with their heads placed over the manger, breathed upon Him, as if they were gifted with reason, and knew that their warm breath would be of service to an infant so slightly protected from the severity of the season
If you wish to know how these things may come about, ask grace, not learning; desire, not understanding; the groaning of prayer, not diligence in reading, the Bridegroom, not the teacher; God, not man; darkness, not clarity; not light, but the fire that wholly inflames and carries one into God through transporting unctions and consuming affections. God Himself is this fire, and His furnace is in Jerusalem…
8. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Scholars are somewhat divided over the exact date of Bonaventure’s birth. Gilson, Cullen, Crowley, Copleston, and others have regarded the later date of 1221 as more plausible. Others, such as Hughes, Cousins, and Abate, regard the early date of 1217. There are good arguments for either position. I tend to favor the later date of 1221, but I do not hold to this unquestioningly. Nevertheless, aside from the data about Bonaventure’s inceptio, his entrance into the Franciscan Order, and other things, the essential piece of data for aligning Bonaventure’s historical chronology is his own testimony: “[W]hen I was a boy, as I still vividly remember, I was snatched from the jaws of death by his [St. Francis’s] invocation and merits” (see Bonaventure 2000b). |
2 | “What is wiser and more fitting than to bring the entire universe to full perfection by uniting the first and last, that is, the Word of God, which is the origin of all things, and human nature, which was the last of all creatures?” (Bonaventure, Breviloquium, 4.1.2). |
3 | I Sent., d. 34, ch. 1. |
4 | Cf. I Sent., d. 34, ch. 1 and Myst. Trin., q. 2, a. 2, obj. 4/resp. 4. |
5 | I Sent., d. 34, ch. 2. |
6 | “…[L]et us say that because the most pure and absolute being which is unqualifiedly being is the first and last, it is therefore the origin and the fulfilling end of all things. As eternal and most present, it encompasses and enters all durations, existing, as it were, at one and the same time as their center and their circumference. Likewise, because it is the most simple and the greatest, it is wholly within all things and wholly outside them; hence it is ‘the intelligible sphere, whose center is everywhere and whose circumference is nowhere’” (Bonaventure, Itinerarium, 5.8). |
7 | While copious scholarship exists on Bonaventure’s illuminationist epistemology (which is essential for understanding Bonaventure’s Christology as well as his Trinitarian theology), there has been a rather regretful lacuna in scholarship on Bonaventure’s Trinitarian theology. In recent time, this has been remedied by Jared Goff’s seminal and extensive treatment of Bonaventure’s De Mysterio Trinitatis. Additionally, I should add that recent Bonaventure scholarship has been somewhat preoccupied with assessing and navigating the extent of Aristotelian influence in Bonaventure’s thought. Two of the most recent works suggest not only a fundamental Aristotelian influence in Bonaventure’s ontology (Van Buren 2023), but also to a far greater Aristotelian influence on Bonaventure’s thought in the realm of Trinitarian theology than may be assumed (Goff 2015). In any case, Bonaventure scholars across the spectrum of agreement generally agree the Seraphic Doctor incorporates a wide range of influences—e.g., Aristotle, Pseudo-Dionysius, Richard of St. Victor, Hugh of St. Victor, Alexander of Hales, Plotinus, Augustine et al.—for his task of theological–metaphysical clarification. The description of Bonaventure as aristotélisme éclectique néoplatonisant et surtout augustinisant remains an amusing one. |
8 | Hex., 2.20–7, 13.12. |
9 | “[A]lthough the metaphysician may rise from a consideration of the principles of created and particular substasnce to the universal and uncreated and to that ‘to Be’ (esse), so that one has the relation (ratione) of beginning, middle (medii), and ultimate end, yet one does not have th at ‘to Be’ in the relation (ratione) of the Father, Son, and Holy Spirit …But when one considers that ‘to Be’ (esse) in the relation (ratione) of the exemplar (exemplantis) of all things, one communicates with no other science and is a true metaphysician” (Bonaventure, Hexaëmeron, 1.13). All translations of Bonaventure’s Hexaëmeron are taken from Jay Hammond unless otherwise noted. |
10 | I Sent., d. 43, a. 1, q. 1. |
11 | Hex., 2.23. |
12 | Hex., 3.4. Cf. Pseudo-Aristotle, The Book of Causes, prop. 16–17 and Myst. Trin., q. 4, a. 1, concl. (V, 80ff). The infinite power of the divine attributes is rooted in the divine essence prior to the created mind’s act of cognition and links divine simplicity to infinity-immensity, which preserves “non-formal identity of attributes within real identity” and preserves the nobility of the divine essence via recognition that the created intellect, through abstraction, knows the divine essence and its attributes in a finite mode, “and thus discretely, without attributing finitude and real distinction to the divine essence itself” (cf. Goff 2015, p. 236). This type of distinction in Bonaventure is typically defined as virtual distinction or distinction of attribution. |
13 | I Sent., d. 45, a. 2. |
14 | Hex., 12.12–13. |
15 | Brev., 7.4.7. |
16 | “ …therefore [the first cause] is most actual according to the intrinsic act, which is ‘to speak.’ Hence, from eternity God said this thing would happen and at this time” (Hex., 12.10). Intrinsic causes are causes inside of an effect (e.g., soundwaves). Creatures that become extinct subsist in the knowledge of God and are discernible as an emanation of this knowledge. |
17 | Hex., 12.7. |
18 | Hex., 11.13. Cf. I Sent., 6.1.3 (I, 129) and 27.2.1ff (I, 484ff). Contuition is “a co-recognition, a co-knowledge of one object together with another, so that one cannot recognize one without also recognizing the other” (Goff 2015, p. 170). |
19 | Hex., 4.13. |
20 | “Therefore, to be sanctified is to be drawn away from all polluted and corrupted love …” (Hex., 2.5). Bonaventure often quotes from the Book of Wisdom, which describes Wisdom as a “pure emanation of the glory of the all-powerful God” of which “nothing defiled enters in” (cf. Wis 7:24–26, 29). |
21 | I Sent., d. 3, p. 1, q. 4, concl. |
22 | Hex., 11.14. |
23 | Hex., 11.2–3. Cf. 1 Cor 13:12. |
24 | Hex., 11.10–12.11. |
25 | Any “nominal” attributions to God must therefore respect this division and must, likewise, be tested alongside Bonaventure’s theological–metaphysical structure. It has become something of a novel or fashionable trend to associate Bonaventure with the more “progressive” form of process philosophy/theology—modeled not so much by Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914), but by other pragmatists, process thinkers, and their poststructuralist commentators. The sort of creative endeavor seen in works of this sort come too close to subordinating Bonaventure’s thought, by way of “updating” it, to trends in panentheism, modern empirical science, and progressive politics. For a proper-progressive understanding of what the analogical division of Creator and creature may well imply for Bonaventure, there is some interesting work being conducted on the relation between Bonaventure’s illuminationist epistemology and Scotus’s univocity of being. The suggestion is that Scotus’s univocity formally translates the content of Bonaventure’s divine illumination. For more on this, see Fehlner’s Collected Essays on Mariology. |
26 | Hex., 11.11. |
27 | Cf. Hex., 6.2, 7.9. Also see Augustine, On the Trinity, 13.19.24. This relates back to the need for a speculative center or mediator for philosophy because the ancient philosophers were ignorant of the cause of separability of body and soul as well as the infection of the intellect which cannot resolve this cause on its own. The philosophers were right to indicate that the soul (anima) is naturally united to the body and while, ordinarily speaking, there is no illness in the contraction of a natural unity, nevertheless an illness was introduced by the fault of Adam (“hoc tamen fit per culpam a principio originali, scilicet Adam”) (Hex., 7.9). |
28 | Scien. Chr., q. 6. |
29 | Hex., 10.7. |
30 | Hex., 21.5. |
31 | Physics, 2.9. |
32 | Hex., 2.9. |
33 | ST I, q. 45, a. 1. |
34 | I Sent., d. 32, a. 1, q. 1. The Father and Son love themselves by the Holy Spirit in the reckoning of a quasi-formal effect. |
35 | Cf. Comm. John, 1.1.1–8. |
36 | There are differing scholarly accounts on the inner-workings of Bonaventure’s Trinitarian theology. For example, Goff suggests a kind of prescient Latin–Greek, Greek–Latin interchange that was “translated into philosophical and theological language, at once doing justice to the demands of Aristotelian science, while insisting ever more vehemently upon a life of Gospel perfection: even when speculating upon the seemingly most abstract and difficult of topics” (Goff 2015, p. 310). Others have undertaken a comprehensive examination of the early Franciscan school of theology under Alexander of Hales, indicating that the early Franciscans departed from a more Augustinian, psychological model of the Trinity to a more social-communitarian model (Schumacher et al. 2020). However, Bonaventure is not featured heavily in Schumacher’s study. |
37 | Bonaventure uses different senses or referents for “love.” Three stand out the most: dilectio (“affection towards, choice/selection of love”), amor (“fondness or affection”), and caritas (“dearness, costliness, high price”). |
38 | Hex., 3.5. |
39 | Brev., 4.4.5. |
40 | Bonaventure says in his Itinerarium that God, as eternal and most present, “encompasses and enters all durations, existing, as it were, at one and the same time as their center and their circumference” (Itin., 5.8). Costa has an article critiquing Cross’s view that Bonaventure held a four-dimensionalist view of time. Costa offers five reasons for this, one of which being that Bonaventure explicitly held to a view of substances as permanent entities, not as successive beings having temporal parts that persist or perdure across time. A thorough understanding of the Joachimite influence on Bonaventure, along with Bonaventure’s penchant for aeviternal creation and his disagreement with St. Thomas about a beginning of things in time, seems to favor an “age-theory” of time. Hayes suggests that the Joachimite influence Bonaventure includes three points for understanding Christ as universal or historical center: (1) the conviction that there will be a new turning-point in history; (2) the doctrine of progressive illumination in history; and (3) the prophetic expectation of a coming triumph of grace (Hayes 2000, p. 211). I have argued elsewhere that (2) is problematic and requires some off-setting from Ranke’s and Hegel’s philosophies of history. And as for (1) and (3), these may not fully express the apocalyptic temperament of Bonaventure, which is distinct from that of the Spiritual Franciscans. |
41 | Cf. II Sent. d. 1, p. 1, a. 1, q. 2. |
42 | Hex., 8.13. |
43 | Brev., 7.4.3. |
44 | The most concise and simplistic formulation of the figurae sacramentales is given in Bonaventure’s Itinerarium: “For creatures of this visible world signify the invisible things of God: partly, because God is the Origin, Exemplar, and End of every creature,--and every effect is a sign of its cause; every example is a sign of its exemplar; and every way a sign of the end to which it leads,—partly by their own power of representation; partly because of their prophetic prefiguring; partly because of angelic operation; partly also by virtue of supernatural institution. For every creature is by its very nature a figure and likeness of eternal Wisdom …” (Itin., 2.12). |
45 | Hex., 13.7. |
46 | Hex., 1.1–39. These subjects are divided according to secular and divine science, and the coordination of the two is the task of the learner: for the subject of essence, there is exemplary-metaphysical study; for generation, natural philosophy and incarnation; for distance, mathematics and crucifixion; for sound teaching, logic and resurrection; for virtue, ethics and ascension; for justice, law and final judgment; and for reconciliation and concord, theology and everlasting beatitude. |
47 | Hex., 22. |
48 | Hex., 1.22–23. |
49 | Cf. Hex., 8.7–17. |
50 | Cf. Hex., 2.29, 9.27–29, and elsewhere. According to Ratzinger, Bonaventure agreed with a doctrine “which saw the highest summit in the creature’s ascent to God to consist in a contact with God that would be fully free of knowledge and would therefore be super-intellectual.” |
51 | To be elevated to perpetual matters is easier with the “seasoning (condimentum) of faith” (Hex., 4.5). |
52 | Cf. II Sent., 17.1.2., ad 6. |
53 | Scien. Chr., q. 4. |
54 | Scien. Chr., q. 4, concl. |
55 | Brev., 4.6.1. |
56 | Scien. Chr., q. 1, concl. |
57 | Scien. Chr., q. 7, concl. |
58 | Brev., 4.6.1-8. |
59 | Cf. III Sent., 14.1.2 (III, 298–302). |
60 | Brev., 4.6.5. |
61 | Cf. Matt 24:36. |
62 | Cf. Scien. Chr., q. 6, concl. |
63 | Cf. Hex., 6.20–26 and II Sent., 17.2.3. |
64 | Cf. I Sent., 45, a. 3, qq. 1–2. |
65 | E.g., Matt 5:48: “Be perfect, therefore, as your heavenly Father is perfect”. |
66 | White compares transcendental elements in Kant and Bonaventure, arguing that the notion of a “third term” is common to both. I have contended elsewhere that the divergence between Kant and Bonaventure concerns the nature of notional assent, especially as articulated by John Henry Newman, as well as a split between transcendental realism and transcendental idealism. Nevertheless, Kant uses “dynamic sublimity” in his aesthetics. If one were to apply a similar notion to Bonaventure, it would be situated more concretely in the person of Christ whom, in teaching inwardly, reveals the true splendor and mystery of the rational–intellectual–spiritual mind. |
67 | Scien. Chr., q. 2, no. 2. Cf. Augustine, On the Trinity, 6.10.11. |
68 | Cf. II Sent., d. 6, a. 2, qq. 1–2. |
69 | See note 55 above. |
70 | Heb 5:8. |
71 | Brev., 4.1.1–2. Hunter has brought forward an analysis of Bonaventure’s thought on the hypothetical question—famously attended to by medieval theologians—about whether Christ would have incarnated had no sin been committed by Adam. According to Hunter, Bonaventure’s answer to the hypothetical is an (implicit) negative. On the face of it, this seems to be a reasonable position given the assumption that Bonaventure followed Anselm in maintaining that while there was no absolute necessity for God to redeem man, there was a necessity for God to redeem man if God was going to complete the good he had begun in man (Cullen 2006, p. 142). After all, without the condition of man’s fallenness, what good would need to be completed in man? And yet, if man was not created perfected in habitual or sanctified grace in his prelapsarian state, would God not have incarnated in order to prefect this “preternatural man” regardless of the fall? Given Bonaventure’s views about this, there seems to be room to affirm that Hunter’s “implicit negative” cannot be understood as an “explicit negative” and that Bonaventure’s Christology could support an “implicit affirmative” to the hypothetical. |
72 | E.g., “[T]he most fitting way for human beings to be raised from this condition [of sin] was for the First Principle to come down to their level by making itself knowable, lovable, and imitable” (Brev., 4.1.3). |
73 | Brev., 4.9.4. |
74 | Brev., 4.8.3. |
75 | Brev., 4.8.4. |
76 | Cf. Brev., 4.8.4, 7.5.5 and Hex., 7.8–12. Bonaventure says that the “whole soul” of the philosophers was infected because they were ignorant of the illnesses (i.e., infirmity, ignorance, malice, and yearning or lust) in the internal powers of the soul, thinking them rather to be in the phantasm (phantasia) (Hex., 7.8). More specifically, “[T]hey believed that just as a sphere is moved against another sphere, so a phantasm (phantasia) would move and incline toward exterior things, but the intellect (intellectus) would move naturally towards the higher; yet they were deceived, because these illnesses are in the intellectual (intellectuali) part of the soul, not only in the sensitive …” (Hex., 7.8). They failed to know the illness “because they were ignorant (ignoraverunt) of its cause” (Hex., 7.9). Moreover, they mistakenly believed the soul’s internal powers to be sound and their merits to be sufficient in the present (Hex., 7.12). To offer an illustration of Bonaventure’s critique here, we ought to first ask: To what extent is the soul, stabilized as it were by understanding implanted by nature, preserved by a “purely intellectual cause”? The answer is: the soul can be preserved in an original state by a purely intellectual cause, but not ultimately healed. If you can, imagine a black hole: “the false cycles of happiness” are like a “doom-cycle” of fate, in which the mind occasionally glimpses at the intentional wisps of light that signify an elevation of thought or repose from the “eternal world.” Bonaventure is therefore alerting us to this and to the remedy, namely, grace. As the apostle writes: The light shines in the darkness, and the darkness did not overtake it (Jn 1:5). |
77 | Brev., 3.5.3. |
78 | See note 73 above. |
79 | Brev., 4.9.3. |
80 | Brev., 4.8.5. |
81 | Cf. III Sent., d. 1, a. 1, q. 4, 4 concl. Interestingly, Bonaventure does not consider the incarnation of another person of the Godhead (other than the Son) as an impossibility; rather, he regards such a hypothetical as less-fitting than the Incarnation of the Son. |
82 | See note 73 above. |
83 | Brev., 4.10.3. |
84 | Brev., 5.7.3. Also cf. Brev., 7.5.2. For Bonaventure, the First Principle is utterly universal and sufficient for the order of natures, graces, and rewards. |
85 | “[The] observance of justice disposes one to possessing wisdom, just as the appetite (appetitus) of matter inclines toward the form and makes it easy to be joined with the form’s mediating dispositions” (Hex., 2.6). Bonaventure also adduces this principle to the desire for contemplation: “[J]ust as a bride desires a groom, and matter form, and the ugly the beautiful, so the soul seeks to be united through an excess of contemplation” (Hex., 20.19). See also Aristotle, Physics, 1.9. |
86 | Brev., 7.5.2. Here, is indicated Bonaventure’s doctrine of pluriformism. For more on this, see II Sent., 3.1.1.1; 7.2.2.1, resp; and 18.1.2. See also Hex., 4.10 and Aristotle, On the Soul, 2.3, where the Philosopher states: “For what applies to the soul is just about the same as what concerns geometrical figures, for always in the one next in succession there is present in potency the previous one, both in figures and in things with souls, as the triangle is in quadrilateral and the nutritive potency in the perceptive one” (414b 30-415a; tr. Sachs). In short, for Bonaventure the rational form of the soul is not one in the sense that it either does not or cannot virtually contain the other souls (vegetative and sensitive) in itself, nor in the sense that the rational form is final and thereby lacks potency to receive a new act of matter. Gilson explains it this way, “It can in fact be said that in a sense there is no theory of plurality of forms in [Bonaventure’s] teaching. He never sets out to develop directly and ex professo the thesis that the substantial composita given in experience imply the co-existence of a plurality of forms hierarchically ordered within a single subject …but …the structure of natural beings imply, indeed necessarily involve, the possibility of this co-existence …In a universe filled with virtual forms, none of them can develop from potency to act without an actual form to perfect it and an appropriate matter for it to perfect in its turn. This matter is appropriate to the precise degree in which an anterior form, of less perfection, has disposed it towards the higher form which it is about to receive” (Gilson 2020, pp. 273–74; my emphasis). Hex., 5.24. |
87 | Brev., 7.3.2. |
88 | Brev., 7.5.2. |
89 | See note 87 above. |
90 | Brev., 5.2.1–4. |
91 | Cf. I Sent., d. 45, a. 3, q. 1–2. According to Bonaventure, the Divine Will is an “infinite sea of substance.” And yet, God’s will is distinguished according to “the Will of Good Pleasure” and “the will of a sign.” The will of a sign is “that which causes one to come unto another, while it offers itself to the senses.” For Bonaventure, the five basic signs of the Divine Will are either antecedent or conditional and accord with present (and past-present) or future things through a specific way of reckoning. Hence, the will of a sign, as it is with respect to the Divine Will, includes: to precept, to permit, to prohibit, to counsel, and to fulfill. As Christ receives the Father’s good pleasure in the ecstatic mode, obeys the Father’s will according to the various powers of the will of a sign, and comprehends according to both, the “two wills” of Christ become plainly a matter of created and uncreated wisdom, human and divine nature. |
92 | Brev., 5.2.3. |
93 | See note 92 above. |
94 | Brev., 5.2.1. |
95 | This is a formidable controversy, but in effect the question of an independent philosophy boils down to whether there is such a thing as, properly speaking, “Christian philosophy” and whether the tradition of fides quaerens intellectum or the Thomistic-Aristotelian approach are not both legitimate, yet unequal, methods or approaches to exemplifying the fundamental unity of faith and reason. |
96 | Rom 8:18–25 (NRSV). |
97 | 2 Cor 5:17–18 (NRSV). |
98 | E.g., Rev 21:5; Is 43:19, 65:17; Eph 2:15, 4:24; Heb 8:13. |
99 | Hex., 7.8–12 and 10.12. See also Brev., 7.5.5: “God has imprinted this order upon nature, but nature itself cannot fulfill it, since it cannot raise the dead”. |
100 | This anointing is “sacramental”, which is an inferior of the superordinate concept of “sacrament”: “sensible signs divinely instituted as remedies in which, ‘under the cover of material realities, divine power operates in a hidden manner’” (Brev., 6.1.2). One clear instance of anointing of “sacramental character” in animals, which is materially and formally distinct from humans, is the Blessing of Animals. |
101 | See Num 22:21–39. According to Bonaventure, angelic operation conveys, elevates, and exhibits a supreme power (Hex., 5.27). |
102 | Cf. 2 Pet 2:16. St. Francis admonishment of the wolf of Gubbio is also indicative of prophetic prefiguring, for it prefigured the repentance of those who would, despite having a similar spiritual disposition as the wolf, repent of their sin. |
103 | See note 15 above. |
104 | Itin., 2.12. |
105 | Brev., 7.5.5. |
106 | “Nullum enim sensibile movet potentiam cognitivam, nisi mediante similitudine, quae egreditur ab obiecto, sicut proles a parente …” (Red. art., par. 8). |
107 | “Illa autem similtudo non tacit completionem in actu sentiendi, nisi uniatur cum organo et virtute; et cum unitur, nova fit perceptio …” (Ibid., loc. cit.). |
108 | Itin., 2.5. |
109 | Comm. Luke, 2.14. |
110 | “ …God is seen to be as all in all when we contemplate Him in our minds where He dwells through the gifts of the most bountiful love” (Itin., 4.4). Hex., 4.8–9; 10.7–15; 22.24ff; and Brev., 7.4.7. Also cf. Rom 8:18–23. As it relates to the glorification of vegetative (plant) and sensitive (animal) souls, the argument implied in Gracy’s work is that Bonaventure’s Christology and metaphysical pluriformism can accommodate the preservation of the ideas or likeness of plants and animals as reformed substances via the divine Art. In other words, plants and animals can become proper objects or subjects of the finalized, glorified expression of the soul by the affectivity of sense, will, imagination, and by means of their relation to some exemplar in the human person. |
111 | “Phantom” is a phenomenological term. Husserl’s notion of the phantom is defined as: “What is left of a material thing when its capacity to suffer or exercise causality is left out of consideration.” “Phantom-consummation” is a term I am using to denote “the rational creature’s perception of a new creation according to a reformed substance and the working of the divine Art.” |
112 | Scien. Chr., q. 6, concl. |
113 | Cf. Eph 3:20 and 1 Cor 2:9. Also see Brev., 7.7.6. Bonaventure concludes his Breviloquium with a very lengthy quotation from Anselm’s Proslogion, which speculates on the rewards of paradise. Part of the quotation reads: “O what shall those have who will enjoy this Good, and what they shall not have! Surely, whatever they wish will certainly be theirs and whatever they do not wish will not be theirs. In fact, all the goods of body and soul will be there—such as no eye has seen, nor ear heard, nor the human heart conceived” (7.7.6). |
114 | Matt 7:7–8. |
115 | Brev., 7.4.6. |
116 | See note 115 above. |
117 | Cf. Mark 2:22. |
118 | Brev., 7.2.6. |
119 | Itin., 7.4. Cf. Rev 2:17. |
120 | “[Christ] mixed bitterness with consolations, punishment with enjoyment …Hence, to the example of Christ in consolation, fear is to be added, and in sadness, consolation is to be added” (Hex., 18.11). |
121 | Itin., 7.4–6. |
122 | Hex., 18.21. Cf. Augustine, City of God, 22.30.5. |
123 | Cf. Jn 8:12. |
124 | Hex., 4.10. |
125 | Hex., 2.30. |
126 | Hex., 19.2. Cf. Jms 3. |
127 | Hex., 7.14. Cf. III Sent., 36.6. See also Augustine, City of God, 14.7.2. |
References
- Aquinas, Thomas. 2018. Summa Theologiae. Translated by Fathers of the English Dominican Province. Claremont: Coyote Canyon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. 2011. Physics. Aristotle’s Physics: A Guided Study. Translated by Joe Sachs. Masterworks of Discovery: Guided Studies of Great Texts in Sciences. Edited by Harvey M. Flaumenthaft. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bonaventure. 1881. On the Birth of Jesus Christ. In The Life of Christ. Translated and Edited by William H. Hutchings. London: Rivingtons, Presented by the Stanford University Library. [Google Scholar]
- Bonaventure. 1993. The Journey of the Mind to God (Itinerarium Mentis in Deum). Translated by Philotheus Boehner. Edited by Stephen F. Brown. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company. [Google Scholar]
- Bonaventure. 1996. On the Reudction of the Arts to Theology. Bonaventure Texts in Translation Series I; Translated with Introduction and Commentary by Zachary Hayes. New York: Franciscan Institute Publications, St. Bonaventure University. [Google Scholar]
- Bonaventure. 2000a. Disputed Questions on the Mystery of the Trinity. Translated by Zachary Hayes. Bonaventure Texts in Translation Series III; New York: Franciscan Institute Publications, St. Bonaventure University. [Google Scholar]
- Bonaventure. 2000b. The Major Legend. Francis of Assisi: Early Documents. Edited by Regis J. Armstrong, J. A. Wayne Hellmann and William J. Short. New York: New City Press, vol. II. [Google Scholar]
- Bonaventure. 2001. Commentary on the Gospel of Luke (Part 1). Edited by Robert Karris. Bonaventure Texts in Translation Series VIII; New York: Franciscan Institute Publications, St. Bonaventure University. [Google Scholar]
- Bonaventure. 2005a. Breviloquium. Edited by Dominic V. Monti. Bonaventure Texts in Translation Series IX; New York: Franciscan Institute Publications, St. Bonaventure University. [Google Scholar]
- Bonaventure. 2005b. Disputed Questions on the Knowledge of Christ. Edited by Zachary Hayes. Bonaventure Texts in Translation Series IV; New York: Franciscan Institute Publications, St. Bonaventure University. [Google Scholar]
- Bonaventure. 2007. Commentary on the Gospel of John. Translated with Introduction and Notes by Robert J. Karris. Bonaventure Texts in Translation Series XI; New York: Franciscan Institute Publications, St. Bonaventure University. [Google Scholar]
- Bonaventure. 2014. Commentaries on the First Book of Sentences: On the One & Triune God. Edited by Alexis Bugnolo. Opera Omnia of St. Bonaventure. Mansfield: The Franciscan Archive. [Google Scholar]
- Bonaventure. 2018. Collations on the Hexaemeron. Conferences on the Six Days of Creation: The Illuminations of the Church. Bonaventure Texts in Translation Series XVIII; Translated with Introduction and Notes by Jay M. Hammond. New York: Franciscan Institute Publications, St. Bonaventure University. [Google Scholar]
- Bougerol, J. Guy. 1963. Introduction to the Works of Bonaventure. Edited by José de Vinck. Paterson: St. Anthony Guild Press. [Google Scholar]
- Boulter, Matthew R. 2022. Repetition and Mythos: Ratzinger’s Bonaventure and the Meaning of History. Eugene: Pickwick Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Bowman, Leonard J. 1975. The Cosmic Exemplarism of Bonaventure. The Journal of Religion 55: 181–98. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Copleston, Frederick. 1994. A History of Philosophy. New York: Image Books, vol. 2. First published 1974. [Google Scholar]
- Costa, Damian. 2020. Was Bonaventure a four-dimensionalist? British Journal for the History of Philosophy 28: 393–404. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cullen, Christopher. 2006. Bonaventure. Great Medieval Thinkers. Edited by Brian Davies. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Cullen, Christopher. 2011. Bonaventure on Nature before Grace. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 85: 161–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fehlner, Peter Damian. 2023a. Bonaventure and Contemporary Thought: Comments on the Convocation Address of Ewert H. Cousins. In Studies Systematic and Critical. The Collected Essays of Peter Damian Fehlner 8. Edited by Jared Isaac Goff. Eugene: Wipf & Stock. [Google Scholar]
- Fehlner, Peter Damian. 2023b. Part Three: Virgo Facta Ecclesia: The Role of Charity in the Ecclesiology of St. Bonaventure (1965). In Franciscan Mariology: Francis, Clare, and Bonaventure. The Collected Essays of Peter Damian Fehlner 3. Edited by Jared Isaac Goff. Eugene: Wipf & Stock. [Google Scholar]
- Gilson, Etienne. 2020. The Philosophy of Saint Bonaventure. Providence: Cluny Publishing. [Google Scholar]
- Goff, J. Isaac. 2015. Caritas in Primo: A Study of Bonaventure’s Disputed Questions on the Mystery of the Trinity. New Bedford: Academy of the Immaculate. [Google Scholar]
- Gracy, Lance. 2024. Saint Bonaventure and the Theology of Animals. In I Believe in God the Father Almighty, Creator of Heaven and Earth: Studies in the Theology of Creation. Edited by Gideon Lazar. St. Basil Institute Press: vol. 1. [Google Scholar]
- Hayes, Zachary. 2000. The Hidden Center: Spirituality and Speculative Christology in St. Bonaventure. New York: Franciscan Institute Publications, St. Bonaventure University. [Google Scholar]
- Hunter, Justus H. 2020. If Adam Had Not Sinned: The Reason for the Incarnation from Anselm to Scotus. Washington: The Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
- Johnson, Junius. 2016. The One and the Many in Bonaventure: Exemplarity Explained. Religions 7: 144. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Noone, Timothy. 1999. The Franciscan and Epistemology: Reflections on the Roles of Bonaventure and Scotus. In Medieval Masters: Essays in Memory of E.A. Synan. Edited by Rollen E. Houser. St Paul: Center for Thomistic Studies, University of St. Thomas. [Google Scholar]
- Osborne, Thomas. 1999. Unibilitas: The Key to Bonaventure’s Understanding of Human Nature. Journal of the History of Philosophy 37: 227–50. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pidel, Aaron. 2015. Christi Opera Proficiunt: Ratzinger’s Neo-Bonaventurian Model of Social Inspiration. Nova et Vetera 13: 693–711. [Google Scholar]
- Ratzinger, Joseph. 2020. The Theology of History in Saint Bonaventure. Providence: Cluny Media. [Google Scholar]
- Reynolds, Philip L. 2004. Bonaventure’s Theory of Resemblance. Traditio 58: 219–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Scarpelli, Therese. 2007. Bonaventure’s Christocentric Epistemology: Christ’s Human Knowledge as the Epitome of Illumination in De scientia Christi. Franciscan Studies 65: 63–86. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schumacher, Lydia, Isabelle Mandrella, and Martin Thurner, eds. 2020. The Summa Halensis: Doctrines and Debates. Veröffentlichungen des Grabmann-Institutes zur Erforschung der Mittelalterlichen Theologie und Philosophie. Berlin: De Gruyter. [Google Scholar]
- Sokolowski, Robert. 1974. Husserlian Meditations: How Words Present Things. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Speer, Andreas. 1997. Bonaventure and the Question of a Medieval Philosophy. Medieval Philosophy and Theology 6: 25–46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Thurow, Joshua. 2017. Finding Collectivee Sin and Recompeense in Anselm’s Cur Deus Homo. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 91: 431–46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Van Buren, Franziska. 2023. Aristotle and the Ontology of St. Bonaventure. Leuven: Leuven University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Vloebergs, Sander. 2016. Wounding love: A mystical-theological exploration of stigmatization. International Journal of Philosophy and Theology 77: 1–29. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- White, John. 2008. Divine light and human wisdom: Transcendental elements in Bonaventure’s illumination theory. International Philosophical Quarterly 48: 175–85. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Temperance | Prudence | Fortitude | Justice | |
---|---|---|---|---|
Father (Producing Power) | To Cleanse | To Enlighten | To Strengthen | To Perfect |
Son (Wisdom of Produced Power) | Cleansing Mind | Enlightening Intention | Strengthening Resolve | Perfecting Law |
Holy Spirit (Goodness Proceeding in Love and Desire of Wisdom) | Imparting Subtlety of Spirits | Imparting Liveliness of Senses | Imparting Strengthening Power | Imparting Discretion of Qualities |
Material | Formal | Efficient | Final |
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Gracy, L.H. The Christology of Bonaventure. Religions 2025, 16, 606. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16050606
Gracy LH. The Christology of Bonaventure. Religions. 2025; 16(5):606. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16050606
Chicago/Turabian StyleGracy, Lance H. 2025. "The Christology of Bonaventure" Religions 16, no. 5: 606. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16050606
APA StyleGracy, L. H. (2025). The Christology of Bonaventure. Religions, 16(5), 606. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16050606