Anthropogenesis, the Original State of Human Nature, and the Classical Model of Original Sin: The Challenge from Natural Science
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Historical-Critical Exegesis of Genesis 1–11
2.1. Human Origins and PO—Protestant Interpretations
2.2. Human Origins and PO—Catholic Interpretations
The Bible itself tells us about the origin of the universe and its structure, not to give us a scientific treatise, but to clarify the proper relationship of man with God and with the universe. Sacred Scripture simply wants to affirm that the world was created by God, and to teach this truth it uses the terms of the cosmology in use at the time of the writer. … it does not want to teach how the heaven was made, but how the heaven should be looked at(John Paul II 1981, § 2, translation is mine).8
The theological teaching of the Bible—like the doctrine of the Church which explains it—teaches us not so much about the how but rather about the why of things; it reveals to us God’s plan for all creation, for the visible and invisible universe and for man—the unheard-of and primordial grace that God has given him, his destiny, the mystery of his freedom, the gravity of his sin, and the Redemption. This plan of God, which illuminates Christian anthropology, cannot be deduced from scientific data, nor has it come to the heart of man(Cf. 1 Cor 2:9) (John Paul II 1986, § 4, translation is mine).
As “creation accounts”, they do not show “how” the world and humanity began but speak of the Creator and his relationship with what he had created. Much misunderstanding results from reading these texts from a modern perspective, seeing them as affirmations of “how” the world and humanity were formed. To respond more adequately to the intention of the biblical texts, it is necessary to oppose such a reading, but without putting their assertions in competition with the knowledge that has come from the natural sciences of our time
[I]t would also be wrong to reduce original sin to a mysterious ontological defect [ontologischen Defekt] that mysteriously passes from generation to generation based on an isolated single act of an individual at the beginning of history
The transmission of original sin does not occur through an incomprehensible infection (unbegreifliche Infektion) of the soul, but takes place in the overall transmission of a human existence shaped by self-rule
An etiology is a literary device deployed across ancient cultures in which a given reality is explained by linking it to something already familiar to an audience. Often, this ‘cause’ posited is not the real historical or scientific one for the reality in question, and the etiology’s essential point is not married to it. On the contrary, etiology is a poetic, vivid, and therefore memorable way to drive home important points
3. Scientifically Informed Theological Reflection on the Origins of the Human Species
3.1. Evolutionary and Theological Anthropogenesis
[T]he Teaching Authority of the Church does not forbid that, in conformity with the present state of human sciences and sacred theology, research and discussions, on the part of men experienced in both fields, take place with regard to the doctrine of evolution, in as far as it inquires into the origin of the human body as coming from pre-existent and living matter—for the Catholic faith obliges us to hold that souls are immediately created by God
3.2. Mono- Versus Polygenetic Origin of the Human Species
- (1)
- Strict monogenism assumes a reduction in the transitional population to exactly one or two organisms. This is highly detrimental to survival, securing energy for brain development, and operation of factors harmonizing biological novelty within a given biological niche.
- (2)
- Strict monogenism assumes the highest possible level of inbreeding, which radically weakens the genetic material.
- (3)
- Strict monogenism does not withstand the data concerning genetic variety observed in the human population. Population genetics helps us realize that the number of alleles of many human genes (shared with chimpanzees—which points toward our sharing a common ancestor with them) requires an inter-species window much broader than just one or two organisms.14
4. Scientifically Informed Theological Reflection on the Original State of Human Nature
4.1. Physical Immortality
[W]hoever says that Adam, the first man, was made mortal, so that, whether he sinned or whether he did not sin, he would die in body, that is he would go out of the body not because of the merit of sin but by reason of the necessity of nature, let him be anathema(DZ, § 101).23
Death is a consequence of sin. The Church’s Magisterium, as authentic interpreter of the affirmations of Scripture and Tradition, teaches that death entered the world on account of man’s sin. (Cf. Gen 2:17; 3:3; 3:19; Wis 1:13; Rom 5:12; 6:23; DS 1511.) Even though man’s nature is mortal God had destined him not to die. Death was therefore contrary to the plans of God the Creator and entered the world as a consequence of sin. (Wis 2:23–24) “Bodily death, from which man would have been immune had he not sinned” is thus “the last enemy” of man left to be conquered. (GS 18 # 2; cf. 1 Cor 15:26)”(CCC, § 1008).
4.2. Infused Knowledge
4.3. Impassibility
4.4. Freedom from Concupiscence
4.5. Bestowal and Loss of the Praeternatural Gifts
- (1)
- Aspects of sense knowledge—in particular external and internal senses, including common sense, imagination, estimative sense, and memorative sense.
- (2)
- Aspects of intellectual knowledge—in particular complex sensible species of phantasms.
- (3)
- Aspects of affective life—in particular sense appetite.
Now for a great acquired change in man’s original nature or natural constitution to be transmitted universally there would be necessary a thorough disturbance of the physical constitution, presumably the brain, central nervous system and sense organs, through the immoral act or course of conduct, and then the transmission of that acquired physical derangement from generation to generation. Neither supposition, however, would seem to be a possibility; and certainly neither derives support from a study of the effects of ordinary sins or sinful habits, on ourselves or on posterity
4.6. The Irenaean Approach
Now it was necessary that man should in the first instance be created; and having been created, should receive growth; and having received growth, should be strengthened, and having been strengthened, should abound; and having abounded, should recover [from the disease of sin]; and having recovered, should be glorified; and having been glorified, should see his Lord
For Augustine, humanity is created perfected in maturity; so too the world. Sin brings about death, which in turn brings about the ruin of a fully matured and perfected humanity, and along with it, the world humanity inhabits. Christ’s redemptive work then, is God’s activity to restore humanity back to Adamic perfection, and to confirm humanity in this perfection. But in Irenaeus’ narrative, humanity is not created in a perfected maturity, but is created with potential to become perfected in maturity. Sin is an interruption of a well-begun upward trajectory, not a fall away from final perfection. Thus in Irenaeus, Christ’s redemptive work is God’s activity to restart the process of maturation that was interrupted by sin and death, and to enable humanity to progress onward toward full maturity
4.7. Summary
5. Challenges for the Received Classical Model of PO
5.1. Adam as Virtually Multiple
[A]ll men born of Adam may be considered as one man, inasmuch as they have one common nature, which they receive from their first parents […]. In this way […] the disorder which is in this man born of Adam, is voluntary, not by his will, but by the will of his first parent, who, by the movement of generation, moves all who originate from him, even as the soul’s will moves all the members to their actions.
[T]he action of one member of the body, of the hand for instance, is voluntary not by the will of that hand, but by the will of the soul, the first mover of the members. Wherefore a murder which the hand commits would not be imputed as a sin to the hand, considered by itself as apart from the body, but is imputed to it as something belonging to man and moved by man’s first moving principle(ST I-II, 81, 1, co.).
If we bear in mind the facts which science and experience supply as to the origin, development, and organic constitution of man, the mode of appearance of his conscience, the nature of his social and physical environment, it will seem to savour of unreality to continue to demand some event of universal or of catastrophic nature to account once and for all for our present state
When we speak, as we sometimes do, of the race as an organism, and attribute to it a life, a will or a sinfulness, of its own, we use the mode of rhetoric, not that of exact science. Apart from being merely the sum of its individuals the race is but an abstraction; and to make it the subject of sin, in any sense that is inapplicable to the individual, is to depart from the only safe region of the concrete
5.2. Adam as Actually Multiple
[W]e must … eliminate that misunderstanding which treats original sin as if the specifically and strictly subjective guilt element were passed on to those that ‘inherit’ because they are physically descended from the one who committed this subjective sin”
The notion that the personal deed of ‘Adam’ or of the first group of people is imputed to us in such a way that it has been transmitted on to us biologically, as it were, has absolutely nothing to do with the Christian dogma of original sin
“Can one think of original sin as the sin of the whole original group of human beings, polygenetically one, and that this whole group, historically united and the vanguard of mankind, committed collectively what is called peccatum originale originans, original sin at the start, and that this group can be personified as “Adam” because it represents a genuine unit?”
“[A]nother problem that confronts theories of a collective original sin is the problem of the small children. A group of any significant size will contain children below the age of reason, who are not capable of committing any sin. What would be their relation to original sin? Original sin is in all human beings. These children could not have participated in the commission of the original sin”(Kemp 2011).
5.3. Adam as Everyman
Without encroaching upon the work of exegesis or criticism, however, we can use the story [of Adam’s sin in Genesis], as the early theologians did, [Augustine 1998, ii.21] in illustration of the universal process of the rise of sin as something always and everywhere the same, and it is in this illustrative quality that, for us, the universal significance of the narrative resides. There we find in Eve, on the one hand, a clear representation of the independent activity and revolt of the sensuous element that develops so readily upon any external incentive by way of opposition to a divine command, and likewise a clear view of how there comes to be conjoined therewith an all too easily effected vitiation of the already developed God-consciousness. On the other hand, in Adam we see how easily sin is assimilated by imitation even without any overpowering activity of sense, and how this presupposes some degree of forgetfulness of God, traceable possibly to mere lack of thought”
We engage in sin because of the deception. Our voluntary committing of it is enough to make us guilty. There does not have to be a primal and once-for-all event of a fall for which Adam was guilty quite apart from all entanglement in sin. … In this sense the story of Adam is the story of the whole race. It is repeated in each individual. The point is not Adam’s first state of innocence in contrast to that of his descendants
5.4. The Communal (Social) Aspect of POOtum
[T]he moral solidarity which is thus asserted is of so different a kind from that embodied in the Augustinian theory that for him to speak of hereditary sin at all is only an inconsistent concession to traditional expressions. What Schleiermacher calls hereditary or original sin is by no means a corruption of our nature caused by Adam and physically transmitted to his posterity: it is not of the nature of punishment: it does not presuppose a fall in the head of the race
[S]in means the damaging or the destruction of relationality. Sin is a rejection of relationality because it wants to make the human being a god. Sin is loss of relationship, disturbance of relationship, and therefore it is not restricted to the individual. When I destroy a relationship, then this event—sin—touches the other person involved in the relationship. Consequently, sin is always an offense that touches others, that alters the world and damages it
To the extent that this is true, when the network of human relationships is damaged from the very beginning, then every human being enters into a world that is marked by relational damage. At the very moment that a person begins human existence, which is a good, he or she is confronted by a sin-damaged world. Each of us enters into a situation in which relationality has been harmed. Consequently, each person is, from the very start, damaged in relationships and does not engage in them as he or she ought. Sin pursues the human being, and he or she capitulates to it
[W]ith regard to freedom, responsibility, the possibility of expiation and the modes of expiation, and the conceivability of the consequences of guilt which we call punishment, in all of these respects in any case ‘original sin’ is essentially different from what we mean when we speak of personal guilt and sin, and understand them as possible or as actual from the perspective of the transcendental experience of freedom in ourselves
5.5. POOtum—Propagation Versus Imitation
“Since the human being in this earliest phase of development [i.e., in the mother’s womb] is uniquely open to the influences of environment [a fact he discusses in his book in greater detail], it is sensible to conclude that disturbances at the beginning of its development have an especially profound effect. Aggressive elements in the initial process of communication take effect on its further growth and may even enter into the physical and psychic structure of its organism. Evil migrates thus from generation to generation, and so it is understandable that people may speak of ‘hereditary transmission’. This comprehensively understood ‘hereditary transmission’ no longer stands in opposition to imitation. Rather it designates a differentiated basic process that can only be adequately described by utilizing complementary concepts stemming from different paradigms”
I claim one can best make sense of the doctrine of original sin by positing that it is maturationally natural. It isn’t carried by our genes in any deep sense. It is not communicated mysteriously, one immaterial soul to another in the womb. It certainly isn’t placed in the soul by divine fiat. Rather, if one takes human nature together with what human environments have in common, the result is a human disposition to be alienated from God, self, others, and nature
“[T]he framework within which human beings make sense of the relevance of behaviors and events is internalized from persons who model a disordered way of relating to all these things, which shapes our developmental context. These models are self-reliant and self-absorbed enough that we do not naturally develop a default reliance on God, a trustful communion with our neighbor, a harmonious relationship with nature, or, indeed, an honest acceptance of the self”
5.6. The Irenaean Take on PO
N. P. Williams was right to observe that the only account of the Fall which is tenable today is that which ‘views the first human sin rather as a praevaricatio, a stepping-aside from the true line of upward progress, than as a lapsus or fall from a high level of moral and intellectual endowment’. While modern science makes the latter view all but impossible, Scripture clearly favours the former view
6. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Hans Madueme puts this phrase in the title of his article on original sin and modern science (see Madueme 2014). |
2 | A number of recent interdisciplinary projects and publications address the issue at stake. See, e.g., Berry and Noble (2009); Madueme and Reeves (2014); Cavanaugh and Smith (2017); and Rosenberg et al. (2018). |
3 | The approach taken in this paper may be classified as an example of science-engaged theology. However, distancing myself from the recent debate concerning this category, I prefer to speak about scientifically informed theological reflection on topics related to human origins, the original state of human nature, and original sin. See Perry and Leidenhag (2023), and Kopf (2025). |
4 | “[W]e may conclude that Genesis 1 is a nonmythical text using a mythical language, what Paul Ricoeur [Ricoeur 1988, p. 311] calls ‘a narrative interpretation of the enigma of existence’” (O’Callaghan 2022, p. 48). |
5 | |
6 | When saying this, Schleiermacher refers to earlier developments in his own work (Schleiermacher 1928, §§ 60, 61, 68). It is worth noting that this reflection leads him to conclude that “an incapacity for good … was present in human nature before the first sin, and that accordingly what is now innate sinfulness was something native also to the first pair” (Schleiermacher 1928, §72.5). This controversial statement (shared by other theologians listed below) was questioned by Frederic Robert Tennant. |
7 | “At the most, men sinning under the curse of Adam’s sin could be regarded as guilty only in a legal sense, inasmuch as law deals only with the guilty deed; but then we would have no right to speak of guilt in the ethical sense” (Bultmann 1951, p. 251). |
8 | This statement echoes Galileo’s memorable declaration that the intention of Sacred Scripture is to “teach us how one goes to heaven and not how heaven goes” (Galileo 1989, p. 96). At the same it is deeply grounded in the theology of creation developed by Augustine, with his notion of rationes seminales, understood as latent forms that God laid up in the initial act of creation, which then become actualized throughout history (see Boersma 2020). |
9 | It is important to note a considerable difference in the tone of this document, in comparison with the earlier document issued by the same Commission in 1909 in which (1) man’s special creation (as opposed to evolutionary tendencies in relation to anthropogenesis), (2) the creation of the first woman out of the first man, and (3) the unity of humankind are all listed among the facts foundational for the Christian religion and given in the literal, historical sense in the first three chapters of Genesis. See Pontificia Commissione Biblica (1909). Experts in the field are of the opinion that this view reflects a particular attitude of the Magisterium, characteristic for the time of the modernist controversy. |
10 | “The biblical narrative of the origins does not relate events in the sense of modern historiography, but rather, it speaks through images. It is a narrative that reveals and hides at the same time. But the underpinning elements are reasonable, and the reality of the dogma must at all events be safeguarded” (Ratzinger and Messori 1985, p. 81). |
11 | It is worth noting that in his catechesis on creation, Ratzinger adds an important clarification on the importance and limitations of the explanation provided by evolutionary anthropology: “[T]he theory of evolution seeks to understand and describe biological developments. But in so doing it cannot explain where the ‘project’ of human persons comes from, nor their inner origin, nor their particular nature” (Ratzinger 1995, p. 50). |
12 | See Wood (2006). An extended and detailed account of anthropogenesis is offered by Foley and Lewin (2004). Research programs in behavioral genetics and evolutionary psychology should be approached with an appropriate dose of caution and critical assessment, given the numerous controversies surrounding their principles and methodologies. Nevertheless, many of their developments deserve attention and—cleansed of the traces of determinism, materialism, and gene-centrism—should be taken into account in the development of comprehensive models of anthropogenesis. |
13 | For a short overview of the ideas mentioned here, see Conrad (2025, p. 148). |
14 | A number of authors who make this point refer to the example of the DRB1 gene (contributing to the immune system), provided by Francisco Ayala in his oft-cited article (Ayala 1995). See, e.g., Lombardo (2018, pp. 531–32) and Kemp (2011, p. 224). Lombardo refers to the scientific articles critical of Ayala’s example and their use in theological argumentation. See, respectively: Bergström et al. (1998), von Salomé et al. (2007), Gauger et al. (2012, pp. 105–22); Dennis Bonnette (2013, pp. 217–25). Nevertheless, Lombardo is right to argue that the latest developments in the study of the human and the primate genomes offer many more examples confirming Ayala’s thesis (see Lombardo 2018, pp. 531–32). He goes as far as to say that the genetic evidence “not only challenges this view [strict monogenesis] but makes it completely unsustainable” (Lombardo 2018, p. 523). |
15 | The controversy about polygenism finds its roots in Pius XII’s comment in (Pius XII 1950a, § 37): “[T]he faithful cannot embrace that opinion which maintains that either after Adam there existed on this earth true men who did not take their origin through natural generation from him as from the first parent of all, or that Adam represents a certain number of first parents. Now it is in no way apparent how such an opinion can be reconciled with that which the sources of revealed truth and the documents of the Teaching Authority of the Church propose with regard to original sin, which proceeds from a sin actually committed by an individual Adam and which, through generation, is passed on to all and is in everyone as his own”. Kenneth Kemp’s careful research in the archives of the Vatican shows that, while the pope did want to express some reservation concerning this scientific opinion, he by no means thought the formula “it is in no way apparent” served as a decisive and closing dogmatic statement. See Kemp (2023b). |
16 | This statement needs further theological development, including a careful reexamination and new interpretation of St. Paul’s analogy of one Adam—one Christ. |
17 | I offer my critical evaluation of Kemp’s model in Tabaczek (2024b, pp. 258–61). See also our exchange at the 2024 Sacra Doctrina conference in Kemp et al. (forthcoming). It is important to note Kemp’s conviction that his model enables him to retain the notion of the preternatural gifts and to uphold original sin understood as the first sin of Adam and Eve. In Tabaczek (2024b, pp. 249–52) I list and shortly analyze standard theological arguments in defense of the monogenetic scenario of anthropogenesis. |
18 | I follow Aquinas’s view of OJ expressed in his Summa theologiae, where he clearly states that it is supernatural and thus an effect of the reception of sanctifying grace (as its formal cause): “it is clear that … the primitive subjection by virtue of which reason was subject to God, was not a merely natural gift, but a supernatural endowment of grace” (ST I, 95, 1, co.). Again, “the root of original righteousness, which conferred righteousness on the first man when he was made, consists in the supernatural subjection of the reason to God, which subjection results from sanctifying grace” (ST I, 100, 1, ad 2). For the contemporary debate on Aquinas’s understanding of OJ see Daniel Houck (2020, chap. 2) and Reinhard Hütter (2023). |
19 | Interestingly, in his account of those gifts in ST I, 97, Aquinas does not use the term praeter naturam. He uses it in another context, in reference to one of the three kinds of miraculous divine agency. He says that miracles can be praeter naturam when they refer to something that does occur in nature yet not without the intermediacy of secondary and instrumental causes (which are absent in miraculous instantiations of those effects). See De pot. 6, 2 and the early version of the same distinction in In II Sent., 18, 1, 3, co. |
20 | It is not altogether clear which of these two options is favored by Aquinas. See my comments below in notes 39 and 54. |
21 | Apart from the praeternatural gift of freedom from physical death (see note 29 below), other praeternatural gifts do not seem to have a clear scriptural foundation. In fact, the account of PO in Genesis is much more precise in describing the state of fallen human nature (something known to and experienced by the author(s) of that text) than in its analysis of the state of OJ. The latter is theologically (speculatively) developed on the basis of the former. |
22 | In other words, this version of the argument assumes that the first humans were in the condition of weak immortality and weak mortality (posse mori et posse non mori), as differentiated from the condition of strong mortality (non posse non mori) and the condition of strong immortality (non posse mori). |
23 | It is important to note that this passage—similar to other opinions expressed in the long history of the theology of original sin—concentrates on the person of Adam, while it ignores the person of Eve. This fact finds explanation in (1) the reference to St. Paul’s analogy between one Adam and one Christ, (2) the notion of Adam as the originator of human nature, representing and deciding in the name of all future generations as a “collective singular” (see below), and (3) the patriarchal character of both the Middle Eastern and Western cultures throughout the centuries. I believe that taking Eve into account further complicates the debate and puts into question some of its crucial developments. Nevertheless, because a thorough analysis of the issue of gender and the role of Eve in original sin goes beyond the scope of the research presented here, in the remaining part of this article I will refer predominantly to Adam (following the tradition) or to the first human beings (without specifying the exact number and gender of the first representants of our species). |
24 | Endres claims that “The strong affirmation of corporal death as the result of sin found in canon 1 has never been so strongly and unequivocally repeated in later documents, although it has been generally taught” (Endres 1967, p. 75). It is definitely (implicitly) assumed in the first canon of the decree on PO in Trent. |
25 | |
26 | “This belief of the sacred pastors and of Christ’s faithful is universally manifested still more splendidly by the fact that, since ancient times, there have been both in the East and in the West solemn liturgical offices commemorating this privilege” (Pius XII 1950b, § 16). |
27 | |
28 | Some assume that the Orthodox tradition speaks of Mary falling asleep and conceives this state as merely analogical to real human death. See Conrad (2025, p. 174). However, this would mean that Mary, being asleep, was mistakenly put in a tomb and the witnesses of these occurrences were confused as to the real condition of the person of Our Lady at the end of her life on earth. |
29 | |
30 | |
31 | As Conrad notes: “Aquinas held, Adam had an ease in ‘penetrating to God’s intellectual effects’—he was struck by the wonder of the very being of the things around him, pointing him to the One who truly possesses being, and was aware of his own mind, whose intellectuality pointed to God” [ST I, 94, 1 and 2] (Conrad 2025, p. 161). |
32 | I am not aware on what base Levering attributes the same state of infused knowledge to Eve in the view of Aquinas. |
33 | An Oxford expert in the Hebrew Scripture, Samuel Rolles Driver, expressed a similar view already in 1907: “As regards the condition of man before the Fall, there is a mistake not infrequently made, which it is important to correct. It is sometimes supposed that the first man was a being of developed intellectual capacity, perfect in the entire range of his faculties, a being so gifted that the greatest and ablest of those who have lived subsequently have been described as the ‘rags’ or ‘ruins’ of Adam. This view of the high intellectual capacities of our first parents has been familiarized to many by the great poem of Milton, who represents Adam and Eve as holding discourse together in words of singular elevation, refinement, and grace. But there is nothing in the representation of Genesis to justify it; and it is opposed to everything that we know of the methods of God’s providence” (Driver 1907, p. 56). |
34 | The qualified notion of physical immortality is important for those who would like to follow contemporary science and yet feel obliged to accept the traditional teaching concerning human death as the outcome of PO. They see freedom from bodily death before the Fall as the only praeternatural gift that has been officially defined (dogmatized) by the Magisterium. |
35 | See my comment on both causes of Adam’s incorruptibility and immortality below, in note 39. Aquinas follows Augustine’s conviction that Adam and Eve were brought into existence as adults. Assuming they were generated and were born as children changes the picture. If someone would like to follow Aquinas on Adam’s incorruptibility, a decision would have to be made as to the moment at which the maturing and aging of the first human beings (and all future generations, had there been no PO) would have stopped. |
36 | Although it is unpleasant—in fact, precisely because it is unpleasant—pain was selected positively in evolutionary transformations as a highly effective alert incentivizing self-protection in unfavorable conditions which threaten the homeostasis of organisms equipped with sensation. Hence, from the perspective of evolutionary biology, pain appears to be good, valuable, and, in a way, necessary for the proper functioning of organisms in the environment. Indeed, contrary to the commonly assumed opinion that Christianity sees pain as metaphysically evil (malum simpliciter)—where evil is defined as the lack of something good—Aquinas defines pain not as a privation but rather a passion of the soul, i.e., an emotion that depends on sensual and/or intellective cognition of something evil, is good in itself, and may serve a purpose. See ST I-II, 39, 1, co.; Tabaczek (2024a). |
37 | In reference to ST I, 102, 2, ad 2, Conrad says that Aquinas assumed that savage beasts did not inhabit Eden. He also mentions that Aquinas ruled out birth defects from the unfallen state (see ST I, 96, 3) and assumed that childbirth for human mothers would have been painless (see ST I, 98, 2, ad 4). See Conrad (2025, pp. 172–73). |
38 | Aquinas follows the view of John of Damascus (1899, ii.11), who says that “Paradise was permeated with the all pervading brightness of a temperate, pure, and exquisite atmosphere, and decked with ever-flowering plants” (ST I, 102, 2, co.). In his critical take on this and similar speculations, Conrad notes: “Aquinas held Eden to be an inaccessible geographical place, blessed with a temperate climate and free from deleterious environmental factors such as dangerous animals. [see ST I, 102, 1 and 2] He seems to have thought that, if Adam had not fallen, each of his descendants would have dwelt in Eden until he or she transitioned to heaven. [see ST I, 102, 4, co.] No such geographical region exists; the human race, evolving in Africa, always inhabited a world that contained dangerous species and was subject to natural disasters. The biblical Eden must be reinterpreted, perhaps as a symbol of an original harmony where humans were wise stewards of nature” (Conrad 2025, p. 159). |
39 | Divine action in the bestowal of praeternatural gifts seems to be yet another problem. This can be seen in the example of physical immortality and incorruptibility, already mentioned above in Section 4.1. At first, in ST I, 97, 1, Aquinas states it was “by reason of a supernatural force (vis supernaturaliter) given by God to the soul, whereby it was enabled to preserve the body from all corruption so long as it remained itself subject to God” (similar in ST I, 97, 3, ad 1). However, he does not explain what that force really was and what its impact on the human soul was. Secondly, in ST I, 97, 1, ad 3, Aquinas adds that “This power of preserving the body was not natural to the soul but was the gift of grace”. Hence, critical questions arise. Was the gift of physical immortality instantiated by grace, “supernatural force”, or both? Or maybe we should assume that the “supernatural force” in question is equivalent to the gift of grace? Finally, in ST I, 97,4, Aquinas refers to the biblical tree of life, which he sees as the source of Adam’s immortality. However, he does not explain in what way the tree of life provided physical immortality, i.e., what was the impact of consuming physical matter (the fruit from the tree of life) on the human soul “whereby it was enabled to preserve the body from all corruption” (ST I, 97, 1, co.). In other words, we do not learn what the relation was between the consuming of the physical matter (the fruit from the tree of life) and the gift of grace (and/or of “supernatural force”). Was the fruit in question the instrument of grace and/or of the “supernatural force”? |
40 | Some of the neo-Scholastic authors list one more praeternatural gift, i.e., a confirmation of the will of the first humans in goodness. They define it as a directionality and fixing of all human powers and dispositions toward the highest goal of all things, that is God. |
41 | Aquinas seems to follow Augustine who equates concupiscence with lust. More recently theologians suggest that as such, it may have other dimensions. We can speak, for example, about the desire for power, honors, material goods, etc. |
42 | |
43 | This view is often related to the theology of PO developed by Irenaeus. See Section 5.6 below. |
44 | One could hold on to the classical opinion that the first human beings were established in the adult form and in possession (from the very first moment of their existence) of both supernatural grace and the praeternatural gifts. Still, the change concerning the latter at the moment of the POOns remains a difficulty. Moreover, a similar argument may be raised with respect to the changes in the environment seemingly introduced by God in its preparation to host the first human beings, and in the detrimental loss of these “improvements” at the moment of POOns (see note 38 above). They would be associated with radical biological transformations of particular organisms and entire ecosystems. |
45 | Frederick Robert Tennant (1866–1957) was an Anglican scholar who offered (in the book quoted here) one of the first—and thus groundbreaking—attempts at a full integration of the doctrine of PO and evolution. |
46 | The argument presented here goes against a rather simplistic suggestion that supernatural and praeternatural gifts are not problematic since, by definition, they go beyond what is natural and thus they have nothing to do with, and cannot be traced by any scientific method. The tradition of praeternatural gifts gives us a more or less precise description of the way in which God’s grace or other kind of special divine action perfects human nature. While we do not have access to any physical (thus scientifically verifiable) record of human beings possessing these gifts, scientifically informed theology asks a meaningful question concerning the plausibility of the traditional understanding of the character and the sudden instantiation and loss of those gifts. |
47 | One of the reviewers of the article refers to the scholarship stating that Augustine’s account of the Fall might have been influenced by Greek and Roman ideas of a Golden Age, from which civilization has declined (the point mentioned in Section 2.1 with respect to theology of PO developed by Niebuhr). For example, Plato discusses such a decline in Republic VIII. If true, this thesis provides further reason for a critical evaluation of at least some aspects of Augustine’s model that seem to be incompatible with our strongest scientific theories of anthropogenesis, and which are not required by Scripture and Tradition. A more detailed analysis of this argument goes beyond the scope of the analysis presented here. |
48 | I quote Irenaeus after Lane (2009). Gerald Hiestand notes that “Irenaeus, with the exceptions of Theophilus (and possibly Clement) is the only extant early Christian writer to speak about the infancy of Adam and Eve” (Hiestand 2018, p. 62). He refers to Theophilus of Antioch’s Ad Autolycus where we read that “Adam being yet an infant in age, was on this account as yet unable to receive knowledge worthily” (Theophilus of Antioch 1885, 2.25), and to Clement of Alexandria’s Protrepticus where he refers (although merely in passing) to Adam as παιδίον τοῦ Θεοῦ prior to his fall (see Clement of Alexandria 1885, chap. 12). |
49 | I believe Anthony Lane is right when saying that by the knowledge of good and evil Irenaeus meant first and foremost “an intellectual awareness, not first-hand knowledge” (Lane 2009, p. 139). He says it on the basis of a passage in which Irenaeus explains Adam’s knowledge of good and evil after PO: “[M]an knew both the good of obedience and the evil of disobedience, that the eye of the mind, receiving experience of both, may with judgment make choice of the better things; and that he may never become indolent or neglectful of God’s command; and learning by experience that it is an evil thing which deprives him of life, that is, disobedience to God, may never attempt it at all, but that, knowing that what preserves his life, namely, obedience to God, is good, he may diligently keep it with all earnestness” (Irenaeus 1885, 4.39.1). As already mentioned in Section 2.1, that “the first man was immediately the first sinner” was assumed, among many others, by Barth (1956, p. 508) and Niebuhr (see Niebuhr 1996). |
50 | Consequently, we may assume that Irenaeus’s model (even if he did assume the physical immortality of Adam) remains in line with the claim made in Section 4.3 and Section 4.5, that it is meaningful to presume that even without the praeternatural gifts, Adam was properly equipped and disposed to avoid sin and grow in virtue. |
51 | Scholars keep debating whether Irenaeus had in mind a merely spiritual or both spiritual and physical childhood and immaturity of Adam and Eve. Hiestand follows Matthew Steenberg’s assertion: “One can be certain that Irenaeus did not mean ‘children’ to imply [merely] adults with a simple lack of experience … but this is as far as one can go with any attempt at a ‘physical’ description of the first humans” (Steenberg 2004, p. 21). |
52 | The question remains whether Augustine’s model truly assumes the necessity of Adam’s progress. One might argue that—at least in Aquinas’s version of this model, which assumes the highest level of infused natural and revealed knowledge—what is required of Adam is merely a right decision of his will (i.e., a decision for God), based on the judgment of his intellect. This might be seen as moral progress, yet distinct from intellectual progress, which in the case of Adam is not expected or even possible, unlike in the case of his descendants (see Section 4.2 above). |
53 | Ratzinger puts the last Adam first and says “[W]e must never treat the sin of Adam and humanity separately from the salvific context, in other words, without understanding them within the horizon of justification in Christ” (Ratzinger 2008). On another occasion, he adds: “[W]hat is disclosed in [Christ] is what the riddle of the human person really intends. Scripture … characterizes him as the true fulfillment of the idea of the human person, in which the direction of meaning of this being comes fully to light for the first time” (Ratzinger 2013, p. 114). In the Church Dogmatics, Barth states that we should not talk of an Adam-Christ but a Christ-Adam parallel. He declares Christ to be the original, and Adam merely the figure of him who was to come (see Barth 1956, pp. 512–13). This point is being emphasized by a number of contemporary theologians and the CCC (§§ 388–89). |
54 | Aquinas is so deeply committed to the theology of praeternatural gifts that, when he speculates on the “shape” of the original state of human nature without the gift of sanctifying grace, he takes it for granted that Adam would still possess those gifts. This leads him to suggest that “in the state of perfect nature, man, without habitual grace, could avoid sinning either mortally or venially” (ST I-II, 109, 8, co.), and that “man in the state of perfect nature could fulfil all the commandments of the Law” (ST I-II, 109, 4, co.). Concerning Adam’s spiritual life, Aquinas thinks that “[I]n the state of perfect nature man did not need the gift of grace added to his natural endowments, in order to love God above all things naturally, although he needed God’s help to move him to it; but in the state of corrupt nature man needs, even for this, the help of grace to heal his nature” (ST I-II, 109, 3, co.). Finally, with respect to Adam’s moral agency, we learn from Aquinas that “in the state of integrity, as regards the sufficiency of the operative power, man by his natural endowments could wish and do the good proportionate to his nature, such as the good of acquired virtue; but not surpassing good, as the good of infused virtue” (ST I-II, 109, 2, co.). |
55 | Note that the assumption of the rudimentary level of the development of specifically human features in the first human beings (or first generations of human beings) leaves space for their gradual transition from violence to altruism, care, and love. That is, only those violent acts would have been sinful that the first human beings had recognized as going against some clearly discerned and acknowledged rules concerning their relation with other human beings (and possibly with other created beings), in reference to their recognition of the grounding of those norms in the transcendental cause of all nature (i.e., God). |
56 | It is notable that neither Mary nor Christ—both free from POOtum—seem to have had those gifts in their earthly lives (see my comments on Mary’s assumption above), which becomes yet another critical argument in the debate. |
57 | However, we must not neglect the recent voices of those who defend the plausibility of the theological opinion assuming the reality of the praeternatural gifts in the context of the natural science of today. See, e.g., Conrad (2025), Hütter (2023), Macdonald (2021), Piotr Roszak (2020), and Vanzini (2023). Conrad is of the opinion that—despite the difficulties with the plausibility of some aspects of the classical notion of the praeternatural gifts—what justifies Aquinas’s position and makes it relevant today is the fact that “his hints of what humanity might have been like if Adam had not sinned imply that an unfallen race would have enjoyed a relative immortality, a relative immunity from suffering, and a relative absence of personal and social sin” (Conrad 2025, p. 144). |
58 | A number of contemporary scholars reinterpret the theological import of Paul’s analogy in a way that dispenses with the historicity of Adam. To give an example, James G. Dunn says: “It would not be true to say that Paul’s theological point here depends on Adam’s being a ‘historical’ individual or on his disobedience being a historical event as such. Such an implication does not necessarily follow from the fact that a parallel is drawn with Christ’s single act: an act in mythic history can be paralleled to an act in living history without the point of comparison being lost. So long as the story of Adam as the initiator of a sad tale of human failure was well known … such a comparison was meaningful… [T]he effect of the comparison between the two epochal figures, Adam and Christ, is not so much to historicize the individual Adam as to bring out the more than individual significance of the historic Christ” (Dunn 1988, p. 289). |
59 | The idea of Adam as the proto-human inspires challenging counterfactual scenarios in which the first sin is committed not by him but by Eve alone or by one of their children. According to the causal responsibility traditionally assigned to Adam (and not to anyone else), with respect to all future humanity, those sins would not have had any major impact on the rest of the human species, which is counterintuitive (while this is a logical consequence of Aquinas’s view of OJ and PO, at least on one occasion he says something contrary: “if one of Adam’s posterity sinned, while Adam did not, such a person would indeed die for his own actual sin as Adam did, but his posterity would die because of original sin” [De malo 5, 4, ad 8]). These and other counterfactual questions around Aquinas’s notion of PO are addressed by De Letter (1961). He claims that the first generation of Adam’s offspring would have made the accidental feature of OJ linked to human nature definitively, such that—had Adam committed POOns afterward and conceived more offspring in the state of sin—they would have been born in the state of OJ (just as “after the fall and his eventual repentance, Adam did recover sanctifying grace but not the preternatural gifts of original justice [see Comp. theol., c. 198], and did transmit original sin to his posterity even when he himself was in the state of grace [see Comp. theol. c. 198; ST I-II, 81, 3 ad 2; De malo, 4, 6 ad 4]” [De Letter 1961, p. 117]). Consequently, Aquinas must agree that while Christian parents in the state of grace beget children in the state of original sin, sinful children of righteous Adam would have begotten children in the state of OJ (see De Letter 1961, p. 123). Yet another question could be asked about whether Adam, when committing PO, was aware of its consequences for the whole of human nature and how this might have affected the extent of his guilt. |
60 | Human nature after PO is here understood as transmitted to future generations in the condition of rejection of the OJ. |
61 | “God forbid that one should seem to excuse sin at any stage of human development!”—adds Tennant (Tennant 1902, p. 112), but the model he offers does not require the notion of one proto-human deciding in the name of all humanity. |
62 | |
63 | In addition, Rahner lists several aspects which he believes confirm that “mankind remains a biological–historical unity, even in terms of polygenism:” (a) the real unity of physical existence in an ambiance; (b) the real unity of the animal population from which mankind descended; (c) the unity of the concrete biotype within which alone mankind can endure and procreate; (d) the actual human and personal intercommunication; and (e) the unity of man’s destiny toward a supernatural aim and Christ (this is not merely related to mankind as one but makes this oneness even more radically one). See Rahner (1967, p. 67). The debate on various models of mono- and polygenetic origins of the human species with respect to the doctrine of PO continues. Among more recent publications on this topic we find Flaman (2016), Suarez (2015, 2016). |
64 | |
65 | Approaching the same topic on another occasion, he states “It is our opinion that the peccatum originale originans has only a symbolical significance left” (Vanneste 1975, p. 180). |
66 | On another occasion, we find Schleiermacher saying: “Now, while the first appearance of sin in the first pair, due to that original sinfulness, not only was in itself a single and trivial event, but in particular was without any transforming influence upon human nature, yet the growth of sin in consequence of the increase of the human race by ordinary generation had its origin in the first emergence of sin, and therefore in the original sinfulness itself” (Schleiermacher 1928, § 72.5). Carl Trueman pays attention to the influence of Schleiermacher’s model of PO on Walter Rauschenbusch in industrial Great Britain. Critical about both the tendencies to reduce it to a function of society and an overemphasis on individual sin, he nonetheless strived to expose structural and institutional sin. Grounded in Hegelianism, he developed his model not so much in reference to the primeval fall of Adam but in view of the comparison of the world as it is with the ideal kingdom of God which is to come. See Trueman (2014, pp. 171–75). |
67 | Similar is the notion of original sin as the universality of personal sin, offered by Henri Rondet: “From all eternity, God sees all men in his well-loved Son, leader of a mystical body whose head, purpose and reason for existence he is. But he also sees them to be sinners, as the result at once of a personal and a collective sin which constitutes the sin of Adam” (Rondet 1972, p. 263). |
68 | See Ramage (2022, pp. 210–13). |
69 | A possible difficulty on the side of models emphasizing the communal (social) aspect of PO might be their inadvertent limitation of POOtum to the relevant negative dispositions (propensities) for sin in human society, which seem to remain after baptism. Hence, if those dispositions are seen as simply identical with POOtum—with either implicit or explicit ignorance of the aspect of guilt—then it follows that baptism does not take away POOtum, which contradicts the teaching of Trent: “If anyone denies that by the grace of our Lord Jesus Christ, which is conferred in baptism, the guilt of original sin is remitted, or even asserts that the whole of that which has the true and proper nature of sin is not taken away, but says that it is only touched in person or is not imputed, let him be anathema” (DZ, § 792). |
70 | I think that the position of Ratzinger on this issue expressed in Ratzinger (1995, pp. 71–73) is similar, although his reference to the category of guilt in this work is rather scarce. |
71 | An accessible introduction to the extended evolutionary synthesis can be found in Chiu (2022). See also Jablonka and Lamb (2014, 2020); Pigliucci and Muller (2010). |
72 | All three categories refer to traits that can be but do not have to be reflective and intentional. See Green (2022, pp. 28–31) and McCauley (2011). |
73 | Lane refers here to Williams (1927, p. 514). For his critical evaluation of the scriptural account of the state of human nature before original sin see Lane (2009, pp. 142–48). Concerning Irenaean model see also Rondet (1972, pp. 37–50), McCoy (2018), and Swinburne (2018). |
References
Primary Sources
Comp. theol.~Compendium theologiae seu brevis compilation theologiae ad fratrem Raynaldum. In Opera omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita, Vol. 42. Rome: Editori di San Tommaso, 1979, 83–191. [English translation: Aquinas Compendium of Theology, tr. C. Vollert. Saint Louis: B. Herder Book Co., 1947.]De malo~Quaestiones disputatae de malo. Vol. 23 of Opera Omnia. Rome: Typographia polyglotta, 1982. [English translation: On Evil. Translated by John A. Oesterle and Jean T. Oesterle. South Bend, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1995.]De pot.~Quaestiones disputatae de potentia Dei. Turin and Rome: Marietti, 1965. [English translation: On the Power of God. Translated by English Dominican Fathers. Westminster, MD: Newman Press, 1952.]ST~Summa theologiae. Rome: Editiones Paulinae, 1962. [English translation: Summa Theologica. 3 vols. Translated by the Fathers of the English Dominican Province. New York: Benzinger Bros., 1946.]In Sent.~Scriptum super Libros Sententiarum. Edited by S. E. Fretté and P. Maré. Vols. 7–11 of Opera omnia. Paris: Vivès, 1882–1889.DZ~Denzinger. 2012. Enchiridion Symbolorum, 43rd ed. Edited by Peter Hünermann. San Francisco: Ignatius Press.CCC~Catechism of the Catholic Church, 2nd Edition. 2nd edition. Vatican City: Libreria Editrice Vaticana, 2000. https://www.usccb.org/sites/default/files/flipbooks/catechism/VI/ (accessed on 5 May 2025).Secondary Sources
- Alexander, Andrew. 1964. Human Origins and Genetics. Clergy Review 49: 344–53. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. 2001. Metaphysics. In The Basic Works of Aristotle. Translated by William D. Ross. Edited by Richard McKeon. New York: The Modern Library, pp. 681–926. [Google Scholar]
- Augustine. 1997. The Punishment and Forgiveness of Sins and the Baptism of Little Ones. In Answer to the Pelagians. Hyde Park: New City Press. [Google Scholar]
- Augustine. 1998. De Genesi Contra Manichaeos. Edited by Dorothea Weber. Wien: Verlag der Österreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften. [Google Scholar]
- Ayala, Francisco J. 1995. The Myth of Eve: Molecular Biology and Human Origins. Science 270: 1930–36. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Barth, Karl. 1956. Church Dogmatics, Vol. 4/1, The Doctrine of Reconciliation, Part 1. Translated by Geoffrey W. Bromiley, and Thomas. F. Torrance. New York: T&T Clark. [Google Scholar]
- Barth, Karl. 1962. Christ and Adam: Man and Humanity in Romans 5. New York: Collier. [Google Scholar]
- Beatrice, Pier Franco. 2013. The Transmission of Sin: Augustine and the Pre-Augustinian Sources. Translated by Adam Kamesar. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bergström, Tomas F., Agnetha Josefsson, Henry A. Erlich, and Ulf Gyllensten. 1998. Recent Origin of HLA-DRB1 Alleles and Implications for Human Evolution. Nature Genetics 18: 237–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Berry, Robert J., and Thomas A. Noble, eds. 2009. Darwin, Creation and the Fall: Theological Challenges. Nottingham: Intervarsity Press. [Google Scholar]
- Boersma, Gerald P. 2020. The Rationes Seminales in Augustine’s Theology of Creation. Nova et Vetera 18: 413–41. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bonnette, Dennis. 2013. Origin of the Human Species, 3rd ed. Ypsilanti: Sapientia Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bultmann, Rudolf. 1951. Theology of the New Testament, Vol. 1. New York: Scribner. [Google Scholar]
- Cavanaugh, William T., and James K. A. Smith, eds. 2017. Evolution and the Fall. Grand Rapids: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing. [Google Scholar]
- Chiu, Lynn. 2022. Extended Evolutionary Synthesis: A Review of the Latest Scientific Research. Available online: https://www.templeton.org/wp-content/uploads/2022/08/EES_Review_FINAL_.pdf (accessed on 5 May 2025).
- Clement of Alexandria. 1885. Exhortation to the Heathen. In Ante-Nicene Fathers, Vol. 2. Translated by William Wilson. Edited by Alexander Roberts, James Donaldson and Arthur Cleveland Coxe. Buffalo: Christian Literature Publishing Co. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad, Richard. 2025. What If ‘Adam’ Had Not Sinned? Explorations on How Human Vulnerabilities Might Have Been Overcome in the First Human Beings and Their Descendants. In Creation through Evolution: New Perspectives from Thomistic Philosophy and Theology. Edited by Nicanor Pier Giorgio Austriaco. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, pp. 143–76. [Google Scholar]
- De Letter, P. 1961. If Adam Had Not Sinned …. Irish Theological Quarterly 28: 115–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Driver, Samuel Rolles. 1907. The Book of Genesis. London: Methuen & Co Ltd. [Google Scholar]
- Dubarle, Andre-Marie. 1964. The Biblical Doctrine of Original Sin. Translated by E. M. Stewart. London: Geoffrey Chapman. [Google Scholar]
- Dunn, James D. G. 1988. Romans 1–8, Word Biblical Commentary 38A. Edited by Bruce M. Metzger, David Allen Hubbard and Glenn W. Barker. Dallas: Word. [Google Scholar]
- Endres, Benedict J. 1967. The Council of Trent and Original Sin. Proceedings of the Catholic Theological Society of America 22: 74–75. [Google Scholar]
- Enns, Peter. 2012. The Evolution of Adam: What the Bible Does and Doesn’t Say About Human Origins. Grand Rapids: Brazos Press. [Google Scholar]
- Flaman, Paul J. P. 2016. Evolution, the Origin of Human Persons, and Original Sin: Physical Continuity with an Ontological Leap. The Heythrop Journal 57: 568–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Flick, Maurizio, and Zoltán Alszeghy. 1972. Il Peccato Originale. Roma: Queriniana. [Google Scholar]
- Foley, Robert Andrew, and Roger Lewin. 2004. Principles of Human Evolution, 2nd ed. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Galileo, Galilei. 1989. Letter to the Grand Duchess Christina. In The Galileo Affair: A Documentary History. Edited by Maurice Finocchiaro. Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 87–118. [Google Scholar]
- Gauger, Ann, Douglas Axe, and Casey Luskin. 2012. Science and Human Origins. Seattle: Discovery Institute Press. [Google Scholar]
- Green, Adam. 2022. The Maturational Naturalness of Original Sin. TheoLogica 6: 20–43. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hiestand, Gerald. 2018. A More Modest Adam: An Exploration of Irenaeus’ Anthropology in Light of the Darwinian Account of Pre-Fall Death. Bulletin of Ecclesial Theology 5: 55–72. [Google Scholar]
- Houck, Daniel W. 2020. Aquinas, Original Sin, and the Challenge of Evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hütter, Reinhard. 2023. Original Sin Revisited: A Recent Proposal on Thomas Aquinas, Original Sin, and the Challenge of Evolution. Nova et Vetera 21: 693–732. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- International Theological Commission. 2004. Communion and Stewardship: Human Persons Created in the Image of God. Vatican City: Libreria Editrice Vaticana. [Google Scholar]
- Irenaeus. 1885. Against Heresies. In Ante-Nicene Fathers. Vol 1: The Apostolic Fathers, Justin Martyr, Irenaeus. Edited by Alexander Roberts and James Donaldson. Grand Rapids: Christian Classics Ethereal Library, pp. 834–1391. [Google Scholar]
- Irenaeus. 2001. Epideixis. Translated by Norbert Brox. Freiburg im Breisgau: Herder. [Google Scholar]
- Jablonka, Eva, and Marion J. Lamb. 2014. Evolution in Four Dimensions: Genetic, Epigenetic, Behavioral, and Symbolic Variation in the History of Life. Cambridge: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
- Jablonka, Eva, and Marion J. Lamb. 2020. Inheritance Systems and the Extended Evolutionary Synthesis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- John of Damascus. 1899. De fide orthodoxa. In Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, Second Series. Translated by Edward W. Watson, and Leighton Pullan. Edited by Philip Schaff and Henry Wace. Buffalo: Christian Literature Publishing Co., vol. 9. [Google Scholar]
- John Paul II. 1981. Address to the Pontifical Academy of the Sciences. October 3. Available online: http://www.vatican.va/content/john-paul-ii/en/speeches/1981/october.index.2.html (accessed on 5 May 2025).
- John Paul II. 1985. Address to the Symposium ‘Christian Faith and the Theory of Evolution’. Translated by Paolo Zanna. Available online: http://inters.org/John-Paul-II-Faith-Evolution-1985 (accessed on 15 December 2024).
- John Paul II. 1986. Address to Participants in a Colloquium on Science, Philosophy and Theology. September 5. Available online: https://www.vatican.va/content/john-paul-ii/fr/speeches/1986/september/documents/hf_jp-ii_spe_19860905_colloquio-scienza.html (accessed on 5 May 2025).
- Kemp, Kenneth W. 2011. Science, Theology, and Monogenesis. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 85: 217–36. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kemp, Kenneth W. 2020. God, Evolution, and the Body of Adam. Scientia et Fides 8: 139–72. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kemp, Kenneth W. 2023a. Evolution, Adam, and the Catholic Church. Logos: A Journal of Catholic Thought and Culture 26: 22–43. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kemp, Kenneth W. 2023b. Humani Generis & Evolution: A Report from the Archives. Scientia et Fides 11: 9–27. [Google Scholar]
- Kemp, Kenneth W., Matthew J. Ramage, and Mariusz Tabaczek. forthcoming. Anthropogenesis: Synthesizing Evolution and Catholic Doctrine—A Panel Exchange. Lux Veritatis.
- Kopf, Simon Maria. 2025. Prospects and Pitfalls of Science-Engaged Theology. Theological Studies. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lane, Anthony N. S. 2009. Irenaeus on the Fall and Original Sin. In Darwin, Creation and the Fall: Theological Challenges. Edited by Robert J. Berry and Thomas A. Noble. Nottingham: Intervarsity Press, pp. 130–48. [Google Scholar]
- Levering, Matthew. 2017. Engaging the Doctrine of Creation: Cosmos, Creatures, and the Wise and Good Creator. Grand Rapids: Baker Academic. [Google Scholar]
- Lewis, Clive Staples. 2015. The Problem of Pain: How Human Suffering Raises Almost Intolerable Intellectual Problems. New York: HarperCollins. [Google Scholar]
- Lombardo, Nicholas E. 2018. Evolutionary Genetics and Theological Narratives of Human Origins. The Heythrop Journal 59: 523–33. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Macdonald, Paul A., Jr. 2021. In Defense of Aquinas’s Adam: Original Justice, the Fall, and Evolution. Zygon 56: 454–66. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Madueme, Hans, and Michael Reeves, eds. 2014. Adam, the Fall, and Original Sin: Theological, Biblical, and Scientific Perspectives. Grand Rapids: Baker Academic. [Google Scholar]
- Madueme, Hans. 2014. ‘The Most Vulnerable Part of the Whole Christian Account’: Original Sin and Modern Science. In Adam, the Fall, and Original Sin: Theological, Biblical, and Scientific Perspectives. Edited by Hans Madueme and Michael Reeves. Grand Rapids: Baker Academic, pp. 225–50. [Google Scholar]
- McCauley, Robert N. 2011. Why Religion Is Natural and Science Is Not. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- McCoy, Andrew M. 2018. The Irenaean Approach to Original Sin through Christ’s Redemption. In Finding Ourselves after Darwin: Conversations on the Image of God, Original Sin, and the Problem of Evil. Edited by Stanley P. Rosenberg, Michael Burdett, Michael Lloyd and Benno van den Toren. Grand Rapids: Baker Academic, pp. 160–72. [Google Scholar]
- McFarland, Ian A. 2010. In Adam’s Fall: A Meditation on the Christian Doctrine of Original Sin. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Muller, Camille. 1951. L’Encyclique ‘Humani Generis’ et Les Problèmes Scientifiques. Synthèses; Revue Mensuelle International 5: 296–312. [Google Scholar]
- NABRE: New American Bible Revised Edition. 2011. Charlottesville: Saint Benedict Press.
- Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1996. The Nature and Destiny of Man: A Christian Interpretation, 2 Vols. Louisville: Westminster John Knox. [Google Scholar]
- O’Callaghan, Paul. 2022. God’s Gift of the Universe: An Introduction to Creation Theology. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
- Pannenberg, Wolfhart. 1994. Systematic Theology. Translated by Geoffrey W. Bromiley. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans. [Google Scholar]
- Perry, John, and Joanna Leidenhag. 2023. Science-Engaged Theology. Cambridge, NY: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Pigliucci, Massimo, and Gerd B. Muller, eds. 2010. Evolution, the Extended Synthesis. New edition. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
- Pius XII. 1950a. Humani Generis. Rome. Available online: https://www.vatican.va/content/pius-xii/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_p-xii_enc_12081950_humani-generis.html (accessed on 5 May 2025).
- Pius XII. 1950b. Munificentissimus Deus. Rome. Available online: https://www.vatican.va/content/pius-xii/en/apost_constitutions/documents/hf_p-xii_apc_19501101_munificentissimus-deus.html (accessed on 5 May 2025).
- Pontifical Biblical Commission. 2014. The Inspiration and Truth of Sacred Scripture. Collegeville: The Liturgical Press. [Google Scholar]
- Pontificia Commissione Biblica. 1909. Sul Carattere Storico dei Primi tre Capitoli Della Genesi. Available online: https://www.vatican.va/roman_curia/congregations/cfaith/pcb_documents/rc_con_cfaith_doc_19090630_genesi_it.html (accessed on 5 May 2025).
- Rahner, Karl. 1961. Theological Reflections on Monogenism. In Theological Investigations. Vol. I. Translated by Cornelius Ernst. Baltimore: Helicon, pp. 229–96. [Google Scholar]
- Rahner, Karl. 1967. Evolution and Original Sin. Concilium 26: 61–73. [Google Scholar]
- Rahner, Karl. 1978. Foundations of Christian Faith: An Introduction to the Idea of Christianity. New York: Crossroad. [Google Scholar]
- Ramage, Matthew J. 2022. From the Dust of the Earth: Benedict XVI, the Bible, and the Theory of Evolution. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ratzinger, Joseph. 1964. Schöpfungslehre, Lecture notes from course on the doctrine of creation taught at Bonn University (1964). After Santiago Sanz Sánchez, Joseph Ratzinger y La Doctrina de La Creación: Los Apuntes de Münster de 1964 (y III). Algunos Temas Debatidos, Revista Española de Teología 74 (2016): 453–96. Translated into English by Matthew Ramage. In From the Dust of the Earth: Benedict XVI, the Bible, and the Theory of Evolution. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 2022. [Google Scholar]
- Ratzinger, Joseph. 1969. The Dignity of the Human Person. In Commentary on the Documents of Vatican II. Edited by Herbert Vorgrimler. New York: Herder and Herder, vol. V, pp. 115–64. [Google Scholar]
- Ratzinger, Joseph. 1995. In the Beginning…: A Catholic Understanding of the Story of Creation and the Fall. Translated by Boniface Ramsey. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans. [Google Scholar]
- Ratzinger, Joseph. 2002. God and the World. A Conversation with Peter Seewald. San Francisco: Ignatius Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ratzinger, Joseph. 2008. Benedict XVI. General Audience: The Apostle’s Teaching on the Relation between Adam and Christ. December 3. Available online: https://www.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/audiences/2008/documents/hf_ben-xvi_aud_20081203.html (accessed on 5 May 2025).
- Ratzinger, Joseph. 2013. Concerning the Notion of Person in Theology. In Oseph Ratzinger in Communio, Vol. 2: Anthropology and Culture. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, pp. 103–18. [Google Scholar]
- Ratzinger, Joseph, and Vittorio Messori. 1985. The Ratzinger Report. San Francisco: Ignatius Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ricoeur, Paul. 1988. La symbolique du mal. Philosophie de la volonte. II. Finitude et culpabilite. Paris: Aubier. [Google Scholar]
- Rondet, Henri. 1972. Original Sin: The Patristic and Theological Background. Staten Island: Alba House. [Google Scholar]
- Rosenberg, Stanley P., Michael Burdett, Michael Lloyd, and Benno van den Toren, eds. 2018. Finding Ourselves after Darwin: Conversations on the Image of God, Original Sin, and the Problem of Evil. Grand Rapids: Baker Academic. [Google Scholar]
- Roszak, Piotr. 2020. Thomas Aquinas on Life in Paradise and Its Anthropological Significance. Archa Verbi 17: 65–88. [Google Scholar]
- Sanz Sánchez, Santiago. 2016. Joseph Ratzinger y La Doctrina de La Creación: Los Apuntes de Münster de 1964 (y III). Algunos Temas Debatidos, Revista Española de Teología 74: 453–96. [Google Scholar]
- Sanz Sánchez, Santiago. 2018. Joseph Ratzinger e il peccato originale: Riflessioni a proposito di un libro mancato. Revista Española de Teología 78: 439–57. [Google Scholar]
- Schleiermacher, Friedrich. 1928. The Christian Faith. Translated by Hugh R. Mackintosh, and James S. Steward. Edinburgh: T&T Clark. [Google Scholar]
- Schoonenberg, Piet. 1965. Man and Sin: A Theological View. Translated by Joseph Donceel. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. [Google Scholar]
- Schoonenberg, Piet. 1975. Sin and Guilt. In Encyclopedia of Theology: The Concise Sacramentum Mundi. Edited by Karl Rahner. New York: Seabury Press, pp. 1579–86. [Google Scholar]
- Schwager, Raymund. 2006. Banished from Eden: Original Sin and Evolutionary Theory in the Drama of Salvation. Herefordshire: Gracewing Publishing. [Google Scholar]
- Steenberg, Matthew C. 2004. Children in Paradise: Adam and Eve as ‘Infants’ in Irenaeus of Lyons. Journal of Early Christian Studies 12: 1–22. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Suarez, Antoine. 2015. Can We Give up the Origin of Humanity from a Primal Couple without Giving up the Teaching of Original Sin and Atonement? Science & Christian Belief 27: 59–83. [Google Scholar]
- Suarez, Antoine. 2016. ‘Transmission at Generation’: Could Original Sin Have Happened at the Time When Homo Sapiens Already Had a Large Population Size? Scientia et Fides 4: 253–94. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Swinburne, Richard. 2018. An Irenaean Approach to Evil. In Finding Ourselves after Darwin: Conversations on the Image of God, Original Sin, and the Problem of Evil. Edited by Stanley P. Rosenberg, Michael Burdett, Michael Lloyd and Benno van den Toren. Grand Rapids: Baker Academic, pp. 280–92. [Google Scholar]
- Tabaczek, Mariusz. 2024a. Is Pain Metaphysically Evil (Malum Simpliciter)?: Some Thoughts from a Thomistic Perspective. Scientia et Fides 12: 143–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tabaczek, Mariusz. 2024b. Theistic Evolution: A Contemporary Aristotelian-Thomistic Perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Taylor, Alfred Edward. 1930. The Faith of a Moralist. Series I. London: Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- te Velde, Rudi A. 2005. Evil, Sin, and Death: Thomas Aquinas on Original Sin. In The Theology of Thomas Aquinas. Edited by Rik Nieuwenhove Van and Joseph Wawrykow. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 143–66. [Google Scholar]
- Tennant, Frederick Robert. 1902. The Origin and Propagation of Sin. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Theophilus of Antioch. 1885. Theophilus to Autolycus. Translated by Marcus Dods. In Ante-Nicene Fathers, Vol. 2. Edited by Alexander Roberts, James Donaldson and Arthur Cleveland Coxe. Buffalo: Christian Literature Publishing Co. [Google Scholar]
- Trueman, Carl R. 2014. Original Sin in Modern Theology. In Adam, the Fall, and Original Sin: Theological, Biblical, and Scientific Perspectives. Edited by Hans Madueme and Michael Reeves. Grand Rapids: Baker Academic, pp. 166–86. [Google Scholar]
- Vanneste, Alfred. 1967. Toward a Theology of Original Sin. Theology Digest 15: 209–14. [Google Scholar]
- Vanneste, Alfred. 1975. The Dogma of Original Sin. Translated by Edward Callens. Louvain: Vander. [Google Scholar]
- Vanzini, Marco. 2023. The Human Condition Before the Fall: Man as the Object of God’s Paternal and Providential Care. Scientia et Fides 11: 213–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- von Salomé, Jenny, Ulf Gyllensten, and Tomas F. Bergström. 2007. Full-Length Sequence Analysis of the HLA-DRB1 Locus Suggests a Recent Origin of Alleles. Immunogenetics 59: 261–71. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wiedenhofer, Siegfried. 1991. The Main Forms of Contemporary Theology of Original Sin. Communio 18: 514–29. [Google Scholar]
- Williams, Norman Powell. 1927. The Ideas of the Fall and of Original Sin: A Historical and Critical Study. London: Longmans, Green and co. [Google Scholar]
- Wood, Bernard. 2006. Human Evolution: A Very Short Introduction, 1st ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Yarnold, Edward. 1971. The Theology of Original Sin. Notre Dame: Fides. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Tabaczek, M. Anthropogenesis, the Original State of Human Nature, and the Classical Model of Original Sin: The Challenge from Natural Science. Religions 2025, 16, 598. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16050598
Tabaczek M. Anthropogenesis, the Original State of Human Nature, and the Classical Model of Original Sin: The Challenge from Natural Science. Religions. 2025; 16(5):598. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16050598
Chicago/Turabian StyleTabaczek, Mariusz. 2025. "Anthropogenesis, the Original State of Human Nature, and the Classical Model of Original Sin: The Challenge from Natural Science" Religions 16, no. 5: 598. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16050598
APA StyleTabaczek, M. (2025). Anthropogenesis, the Original State of Human Nature, and the Classical Model of Original Sin: The Challenge from Natural Science. Religions, 16(5), 598. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16050598