St. Thomas Aquinas on God as Ipsum Esse Subsistens
Abstract
:1. What Is Esse?
Thomas’s understanding of esse remains pretty consistent throughout his career. For Thomas, esse is, in the first place, an act (actus). Thus, he tells us that “esse is simply said of anything according as it is in act” (unumquodque enim simpliciter esse dicitur secundum quod est in actus) (S. th., I-II, q. 6, a. 6.).2 Moreover, he holds that esse is the most fundamental act of a thing: Esse is that which is innermost in each thing and what is most fundamentally inherent in all things since it is formal in respect to whatever is in a thing (formale respectu omnium quae in re sunt).(S. th., I, q. 8, a. 1)3
[J]ust as we can say of he who runs or of the runner that “he runs” because he is the subject of running and participates in it, so we can say that an ens, or that which is (id quod est), “is” because it participates in the actum essendi.(In De ebdom., l. 2)8
2. Pure Esse
3. Esse and Subsistence
Subsisting can mean two things, namely, existing (esse) and existing in a determinate way (determinatum modum essendi); and to exist simply speaking only pertains to individuals, but existing in a determinate way is from the nature or quiddity of the genus or the species [of the ens].(I, d. 23, q. 1, a. 1, ad 2)31
But “subsisting” is said of something inasmuch as it is under (sub) its own esse, not because it has esse in something else as in a subject.(I, d. 23, q. 1, a. 1, ad 3)32
4. Getting to God as Ipsum Esse Subsistens
5. The Kretzmann–Hughes Interpretation
Now it can’t be the case that what explains the existing of everything that exists is itself just another thing that exists, even just something that uniquely exists necessarily through itself. As Aquinas says elsewhere in the chapter … “[The word] ‘existing’ names a kind of actualization (actum quendam), since something is said to exist not because it is potentially but because it is actually”. That is the way “existing” is used, all right, but for just that reason it can’t be quite right to say regarding whatever is at the basis of all existing simply that it exists. That standard way of talking suggests an instantiated nature, even if it should be a nature that entails its own instantiation.
But exactly which identity is at issue? It may seem more elegant for [God’s] nature to be finally identified simply with being. Aquinas himself sometimes puts the identification that way in these chapters and elsewhere: God, or God’s nature, is “being itself (ipsum esse)”. However, that way of putting it suggests that God is nothing but existence, and, as one recent critic puts it, “nothing subsistent could be just existence: a merely existent substance is too thin to be possible” (Hughes 1989, p. 21). The identification Aquinas seems to prefer is this: God, or God’s nature, is “his own being (suum esse)” that is, the uniquely necessary being of the kind that ultimately explains all existing.
For Aquinas … there is nothing more to God than His existence. In that case, it looks as though God will just exist, because there will not be anything else in Him over and above His existence, by virtue of which He could be anything over and above existent. Since there will not be anything in God but existence, and the existence of a thing does not make it anything but existent, God will be nothing more than existent. But it seems clear that nothing subsistent could be just existent: a merely existent substance is too thin to be possible. Moreover, even if some substance could be simply existent, God could not be, since He is any number of other ways than just existent—good, wise, and just, as well as omnipotent, omniscient, and the like.
If what God has according to its full power is not, say, being white, or being square, vel cetera, but just being, then it would seem that what God has according to its full power is just existence. And if there is any intelligible content to the idea that there is a difference between having existence according to its full power, and having existence according to something less than its full power, I cannot grasp it. […] I think I can understand the difference between having whiteness according to its full power and having whiteness according to something less than its full power, because, I take it, it is the difference between being less than perfectly white and being perfectly white. By contrast, there does not seem to be a difference between being perfectly existent and being less than perfectly existent. Existence is an on/off property: either you’re there or you’re not. Because existence is on/off, it would seem, either you have it according to its full power or you don’t have it [at] all. In short, although Aquinas holds that esse or existence fails to include every perfection only insofar as it is “filtered”, the distinction this presupposes—between having filtered existence, and having “the entire fullness of existence” (DSC I, responsio50)—is on the face of it unintelligible.
6. Conclusions
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Kenny endorses the Kretzmann–Hughes interpretation but also makes his own case against Thomas’s doctrine. See (Kenny 2002, p. 105, n. 28). |
2 | Leonina, vol. VI, p. 61. |
3 | Leonina, vol. IV, p. 82. |
4 | “Any form makes a being act” (In V Phys., l. 2, n. 6 [Leonina, vol. II, p. 233]). |
5 | H.D. Gardeil notes that although it can be misleading, it is not incorrect to say that esse is “formal”. See (Gardeil 1958, p. 121). Thomas is not saying that esse is a form. As Lawrence Dewan stresses, in regard to created entia Thomas almost always distinguishes esse from form. See (Dewan 2006). I agree with Étienne Gilson that when Thomas speaks of esse as formal, he is not asserting that esse is form but very likely proposing an analogy between the two. Esse relates to entia as form relates to matter, namely, as an intrinsic principle of act. More precisely, as I will explain below, esse relates in this way to the essence of entia. See (Gilson 1952, pp. 170–71). James Anderson concurs with Gilson’s interpretation. See (Anderson 1952, pp. 113–14). |
6 | Kevin White says that the term actus essendi “seems to be an appositional genitive, meaning the act that is being” (White 2014, p. 289). Perhaps this way of understanding it gets us closer to what Thomas has in mind. |
7 | Leonina, vol. XXIV/2, p. 118. See also In IX Metaph., l. 7, n. 3 (Marietti, 2nd ed., p. 443): “Potency can only be defined by act”. |
8 | Leonina, vol. L, p. 271. |
9 | More precisely, it is like a formal cause. See note 5 above. |
10 | See Quodl., X, q. 3, a. 1 (Marietti, 8th ed., p. 201). As Thomas explains in that text, this difference between esse and operations holds for creatures only; it does not hold for God. See also Cont. gent., II, c. 54 (Leonina, vol. XIII, p. 392). |
11 | It is partly because of its constitutional relation to entia that Domingo Báñez calls esse the “first act” (primus actus) or “first actuality” (prima actualitas) of entia. See (Báñez 1934, pp. 143 ff). There is some precedence for this in Thomas. In In II Sent., d. 27, q. 1, a. 1, ad 3 (Lethielleux, vol. II, p. 696), he tells us that “act is twofold, namely, first act, as esse is the act of form … and second act, which is operation”. And, in S. th., I, q. 4, a. 1, ad 3 (Leonina, vol. IV, p. 50), he says that “esse itself is the act of all things and even of their forms.” When it comes to matter–form composites, Thomas seems more typically to speak of form as the first act rather than esse. But I suspect that this is only because of its relationship to esse, for he holds that it is through the mediation of form (per formam) that the composite has esse. See Cont. gent., II, c. 50 (Leonina, vol. XIII, p. 384). |
12 | “Pourquoi il y a plutót quelque chose que rien?” (Leibniz 1900, §7, p. 727). |
13 | Leonina, vol. IV, p. 42; Leonina, vol. XXIV/1, p. 51. |
14 | Leonina, vol. XLIII, p. 370. |
15 | Leonina, vol. IV, p. 293. Since essence relates to esse as potency to act, we can think of it as being ordered to esse as potency is ordered to act. Báñez notes that “essential principles are the material cause of esse since they themselves are receptive of the very esse by which they are first actualized: indeed, they are understood only inasmuch as they are ordered to esse” (Scholastica commentaria, p. 141). |
16 | As Norberto del Prado puts it: “[C]ette distinction est réelle, c’est-à-dire indépendante de notre esprit et antérieure à la connaissance que nous en avons” (Del Prado 1910, p. 213). The term distinctio realis used in connection with esse/essence can be found in Cajetan, Báñez, and John of Saint Thomas, among the more prominent Thomists. |
17 | These considerations tell us that an ens is an ens not necessarily because esse is what an ens is but because esse is its fundamental act. Rather than being what an ens is, esse is what an ens “does”, so to speak. Analogously, running is not what a runner is but what a runner does. On this point, see Thomas’s remarks in In I Sent., d. 8, q. 1, a. 1 (Lethielleux, vol. I, p. 195). |
18 | Leonina, vol. XXII, p. 791. In matter–form composites it is, more specifically, through the formal component of the essence that it is mediated. See note 11 above. |
19 | Thomas himself speaks of essence “contracting” (contrahendo) esse. See De spiritualibus creaturis, a. 1 (Leonina, vol. XXIV/2, p. 13). |
20 | Lethielleux, vol. I, p. 557. |
21 | Marietti, 9th ed., vol. II, p. 56. |
22 | Leonina, vol. I, p. 36. |
23 | Thomas would (rightly) reject Nietzsche’s claim that “it is only by the seduction of language (der Verführung der Sprache)” that we come to believe that reality consists of subjects with attributes. See (Nietzsche 1887, I, 13). Nietzsche (perhaps under the direct or indirect influence of British empiricism) would have us believe that there are actions without actors or qualities without things possessing those qualities. On this view, there would be running but no runners and squareness but no square things. If Nietzsche is consistent, then he cannot suppose that the running or the squareness themselves have attributes of which they are the subjects. But then there would be nothing to distinguish different instances of running or squareness and we would end up with pure running and pure squareness. In short, we would have something a lot like Platonic forms, but, unlike the originals, which had attributes (for Plato held that they participate in each other), these would be entirely lacking in attributes. It seems unlikely that Nietzsche the anti-Platonist thought through the logical implications of his rejection of a subject–attribute ontology. |
24 | Lethielleux, vol. I, p. 555. |
25 | “But substance is an ens simply and through itself whereas all genera other than substance [i.e., accidents] are entia only in some respect and depend on substance” (In VII Metaph., l. 1 [Marietti, 2nd ed., p. 375]). To be more exact, this is what is true of what Thomas and Aristotle call “first substance” (substantia prima, οὐσία πρώτη), which is an individual thing. They distinguish it from “second substance” (substantia secunda, οὐσία δεύτερα), which is the essence or nature of a thing (In VII Metaph., l. 2 [Marietti, 2nd ed., p. 382]); Categories, 2a11-19). |
26 | If we do not make this qualification (and many interpreters do not), then it would be hard to distinguish between Thomas’s understanding of substance and Spinoza’s. For Spinoza, only God can be a substance because only God exists in absolute independence. This is not at all Thomas’s view. On this question, see (Pasnau 2008, pp. 69–70). As Pasnau points out, in Thomas’s understanding of it, “substancehood” involves “something less than strict and complete independence” (p. 69). I said above that substances are the ultimate support of accidents. If we bring God into the picture and regard him as what ultimately sustains substances themselves in existence, then I should qualify my claim. We should say that substances are the ultimate finite or created support of accidents. |
27 | On completeness and incompleteness as the respective characteristics of substances and accidents, see In II De anima, l. 1, n. 3 (Leonina, vol. XLV, p. 68). |
28 | “Things differ inasmuch as they have different natures, acquiring esse in different ways” (Cont. gent., I, c. 26 [Leonina, vol. XIII, p. 81]). |
29 | Marietti, 9th ed., vol. II, p. 61. |
30 | Leonina, vol. 43, p. 377. |
31 | Lethielleux, vol. I, p. 557. I quoted this last part of the text earlier in what I said about essence specifying esse but in a way that fit better with the rest of the paragraph. |
32 | Lethielleux, vol. I, p. 558. |
33 | Except in the case of the miraculous, as Thomas notes in Cont. gent., IV, c. 66 (Leonina, vol. XV, p. 214). |
34 | Leonina, vol. XV, p. 214. |
35 | Thomas explains in De pot., q. 7, a. 3, ad 7 (Marietti, 9th ed., vol. II, p. 58): “Although God does not belong to the genus of substance as contained in the genus—as a species or an individual—nevertheless, we may say that he is in the genus of substance by reduction, as the principle (per reductionem, sicut principium), as a point is in the genus of continuous quantity, and unity in the genus of number; and in this way he is the measure of all substances, as unity is the measure of all numbers.” I believe that Cajetan correctly interprets Thomas’s meaning here. According to Cajetan, when Thomas says that God is in the genus of substance “by reduction, as the principle”, he is not saying that God is reduced to the genus but that the genus itself is reduced to God, who contains the genus and, indeed, contains all genera as the principle of all genera (S. th., I, q. 3, a. 5 [Leonina, vol. IV, p. 45]). Cajetan uses In I Sent., d. 8, q. 4, a. 2, ad 3 (Lethielleux, vol. I, p. 223) as his hermeneutic key for interpreting De pot., q. 7, a. 3, ad 7. Bearing in mind Cajetan’s interpretation, I see no real conflict between the De potentia text and S. th., I, q. 3, a. 5, where Thomas reformulates his position on God’s relationship to the genus of substance. In both texts, Thomas wishes to stress that God is not a member of the genus. Now, Thomas does occasionally refer to God as a substance. He does this, for instance, in the prologue to his commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics (cf. Marietti, 2nd ed., pp. 1–2). In this particular case, it should be pointed out that Thomas is likely following the usage of Aristotle who speaks of God as a substance in Book XII of the Metaphysics. When Thomas deals with the question of God and substance ex professo he denies that God is an individual substance, as I have said. If Thomas elsewhere refers to God as a substance, it is reasonable to assume that he is speaking loosely and not formaliter. Here, I should mention that one of the anonymous reviewers of this paper expressed surprise that I did not discuss Thomas’s views on subsistence in the Trinity or the persons of the Trinity as substances. My initial thought was that this would be beyond the scope of the paper since Thomas keeps his treatments of the divine nature and the Trinity formally distinct—the first can be known by reason and the second can only be known by revelation (although reason can be employed to analyze what revelation teaches). I still think that it is mostly beyond the scope of the paper, but I do also see that one might worry about Thomas’s consistency. He does say in several places that the persons of the Trinity are substances. But here again he is using “substance” in a loose way. We see this, for instance, in S. th., I, q. 29, a. 3, ad 4 (Leonina, vol. IV, p. 332). There he explains that “substance,” when predicated of the divine persons, is only intended to mean “existing through itself” (existere per se). |
36 | Some interpreters seem not to see this disconnect between subsistence and substance (in the strict sense). Paul Thom, for example, appears to think that, in Thomas’s view, God is a substance because he subsists. See (Thom 2012, p. 130). Hughes does not seem to see the disconnect either, as we will find out. |
37 | Leonina, vol. IV, p. 455. |
38 | Leonina, vol. IV, p. 464. |
39 | See note 37 above. |
40 | Leonina, vol. IV, p. 40. The italics are mine. |
41 | Leonina, vol. IV, pp. 31–32. |
42 | Leonina, vol. IV, p. 42. |
43 | This he proves in the fourth way, where he shows that God is the first efficient cause of all perfections in entia, and expressly mentions esse as one of these perfections. Granted, Thomas does not say in the fourth way that God is an efficient cause but only that he is a cause. However, there can be no doubt that Thomas has efficient causality in mind. In q. 4, a. 2, he does clearly say that God is the efficient cause of all perfections in entia (Leonina, vol. IV, pp. 51–52). A corollary of the fourth way is that everything that has esse is either God or caused by God. That means that there cannot be some ens apart from God from which God himself gets his esse. For an excellent analysis of the fourth way that supports my interpretation, see (Elders 1990, pp. 110–17). |
44 | As Thomas says in S. th., I, q. 4, a. 2, ad 3 (Leonina, vol. IV, p. 52), “no perfection could be lacking in him who is ipsum esse subsistens”. Ferarriensis (Francesco Silvestri) agrees in his commentary on Cont. gent., I, c. 15 (Leonina, vol. XIII, p. 44): “ipsum esse subsistens includes all perfections and can in no way be defective,” he says. This does not mean that in God the perfections that are peculiar to some finite ens (say, the perfections peculiar to a horse) are identical with God’s essence. God’s essence is identical with whatever is an absolute perfection in the sense of a perfection that is not tied to any finite mode of esse. However, it can be said that he possesses the latter perfections in virtute or “virtually” in the sense that he is able to cause them. See, De pot., q. 3, a. 16, ad 24 (Marietti, 9th ed., vol. II, p. 30). |
45 | Leonina, vol. XIII, p. 68. |
46 | (Kretzmann 1997, p. 125). According to the editors of the Leonine edition of the Contra gentiles, Thomas shows this in c. 13 (Leonina, vol. XIII, p. 68). I think Kretzmann is right to locate it rather in c. 15. One could find it implied in c. 13 but it is never expressly argued for. Thomas does expressly argue for it in c. 15 (Leonina, vol. XIII, p. 42). |
47 | In fact, as Thomas observes, because God alone is essentially ipsum esse, he alone is ens per essentiam. See Cont. gent., II, c. 15 (Leonina, vol. XIII, p. 295); III, c. 66 (Leonina, vol. XIV, p. 189); S. th., I, q. 4, a. 3, ad 3 (Leonina, vol. IV, p. 54); q. 104, a. 1 (Leonina, vol. V, p. 464). |
48 | It seems also to be the reason that Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange contends that when Thomas reaches God as ipsum esse subsistens he arrives at le terme de a métaphysique ascendante (Garrigou-Lagrange 1914, p. 359). |
49 | Leonina, vol. IV, p. 52. |
50 | DSC I, responsio = De spirit. creat., a. 1. |
51 | Leonina, vol. XIII, p. 86. |
52 | It is correct to say that God is more esse than all other entia. But we must add that God’s difference from other entia is not only a difference of degree. As ipsum esse subsistens, his nature itself is radically different from the nature of all other entia. |
References
- Anderson, James F. 1952. The Cause of Being: The Philosophy of Creation in St. Thomas. St. Louis: Herder. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, Thomas. 2001. Expositio libri De ebdomadibus: An Exposition of the “On the Hebdomads” of Boethius. Translated by Janice L. Schultz, and Edward A. Synan. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
- Báñez, Domingo. 1934. Scholastica commentaria in primam partem Summae Theologicae S. Thomae Aquinatis, Vol. 1, De Deo Uno. Madrid-Valencia: F.E.D.A. [Google Scholar]
- Bonino, Serge-Thomas. 2016. Dieu, “Celui que est”. Les Plans-sur-Bex: Editions Parole et Silence. [Google Scholar]
- Del Prado, Norberto. 1910. La verité fondamentale de la philosophie chrétienne selon saint Thomas. Revue thomiste 18: 213. [Google Scholar]
- Dewan, Lawrence. 2006. St. Thomas and the Distinction between Form and Esse in Caused Things. In Form and Being: Studies in Thomistic Metaphysics. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, pp. 188–90. [Google Scholar]
- Elders, Leo. 1990. The Philosophical Theology of St. Thomas Aquinas. Leiden: E.J. Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Gardeil, H. D. 1958. Initiation à la philosophie de S. Thomas d’Aquin. Métaphysique, IV, 3rd ed. Paris: Éditions du Cerf. [Google Scholar]
- Garrigou-Lagrange, Réginald. 1914. Dieu, son existence et sa nature: Solution thomiste des antinomies agnostiques, 1st ed. Paris: Beauchesne. [Google Scholar]
- Gilson, Etienne. 1952. Being and Some Philosophers, 2nd ed. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies. [Google Scholar]
- Hughes, Christopher. 1989. On a Complex Theory of a Simple God: An Investigation in Aquinas’ Philosophical Theology. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kenny, Anthony. 2002. Aquinas on Being. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kerr, Gaven. 2015. Aquinas’s Way to God: The Proof in De Ente et Essentia. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Klima, Gyula. 2004. On Kenny on Aquinas on Being: A Critical Review of Aquinas on Being by Anthony Kenny. International Philosophical Quarterly 44: 567–80. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kretzmann, Norman. 1997. The Metaphysics of Theism: Aquinas’s Natural Theology in Summa contra gentiles I. Oxford: University of Oxford Press. [Google Scholar]
- Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1900. Principes de la nature et de la Grâce fondés en raison. In Œuvres philosophiques de Leibniz, 2nd ed. Edited by P. Janet. Paris: F. Alcan, vol. I. [Google Scholar]
- Long, Steven A. 2005. Aquinas on Being and Logicism. New Blackfriars 86: 323–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1887. Zur Genealogie der Moral. Available online: http://www.nietzschesource.org/#eKGWB/GM-I-13 (accessed on 9 November 2023).
- Pasnau, Robert. 2008. Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature: A Philosophical Study of Summa theologiae, Ia 75-89. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Thom, Paul. 2012. The Logic of the Trinity: Augustine to Ockham. New York: Fordham University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ventimiglia, Giovanni. 2018. Is the Thomistic Doctrine of God as Ipsum Esse Subsistens Consistent? European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 10: 161–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- White, Kevin. 2014. Act and Fact: On a Disputed Question in Recent Thomistic Metaphysics. The Review of Metaphysics 68: 287–312. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Trabbic, J.G. St. Thomas Aquinas on God as Ipsum Esse Subsistens. Religions 2025, 16, 140. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16020140
Trabbic JG. St. Thomas Aquinas on God as Ipsum Esse Subsistens. Religions. 2025; 16(2):140. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16020140
Chicago/Turabian StyleTrabbic, Joseph G. 2025. "St. Thomas Aquinas on God as Ipsum Esse Subsistens" Religions 16, no. 2: 140. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16020140
APA StyleTrabbic, J. G. (2025). St. Thomas Aquinas on God as Ipsum Esse Subsistens. Religions, 16(2), 140. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16020140