The Reality of the Invisible: The Phenomenology of Invisibility in H. Conrad-Martius’s Metaphysical Realism
Abstract
1. Introduction
2. Nothingness
How does such a “burden of being” (Seinsballast) enter the midst of Nothingness?! What a paradox, even an impossibility: this nothingness—can it be explained through a descriptive word? It is impossible!—and in the midst of it, suddenly and without any possibility of transition, this something? … How can nothingness “bear” this something (Etwas)? …Without reason, without beginning, without end, or perhaps starting and ending in Nothingness, in a state of isolated, transitionless, unfathomable, bare factuality? Where does it derive the strength, the possibility to exist within non-being? How does it gain this “place” (Ort) of its being? Or how can there even be a “place” of being within the immeasurability of non-being (Nichtseins)?
3. Selfness
By being nothing in itself, it is capable of being everything. Since nothing falls back upon it, it is capable of grasping everything and constantly new things. Because it can never be burdened, enclosed, or locked by the fullness it grasps, it remains open to the possibility, choice, and freedom toward all things.
It is evident that our position is precisely this: the situation inherently comprises both aspects, and only together do they constitute the single, concrete ontic unity that finite existence (Dasein) represents. This is not a dialectical opposition to be reconciled. Rather, the autonomy of Being (Seinsautonomie) and the decay of Being (Seinshinfälligkeit) each occupy their ontic stance at entirely distinct points—or planes—within the totality of existence (Daseinstotalität).
4. Transcendence
Real transcendence does not denote a factual separateness (Auseinander)—such as the spatial distance between two material objects, which can be undone at any moment by contact—but rather an essential separateness grounded in a difference of spheres (Sphärenverschiedenheit) that, in principle, cannot be overturned (unaufhebbare). [An object is] truly transcendent in relation to another when it possesses a distinctive ‘inner structure’ (inneren Gestalt) and occupies an existence-position (Daseinsstelle) that is, in principle, unreachable by the other (where ‘reachability’ [Erreichbarkeit] must be understood in a strictly defined sense that inherently includes the possibility of an ontological intervention [Seinseingriff]).
What is ‘closed’ can only be accessed by something internally akin at the point of its closed existence. However, what is ‘open’—that is, capable of entering into an objective relationship with any and all beings—lies beyond the possibility of any genuine relation with the truly existent; it is, in reality, transcendent to it (realiter transzendent).
5. Discussion
Where no transition is possible, a transition nonetheless occurs. Where no beginning can be made, a beginning is nonetheless present. Where there is no ground of Being (Seinsgrund), but only an abyss—or rather, the groundlessness of Nonbeing (Ungrund des Nichtseins)—something rises toward Being and toward itself, as if it were its own ground of Being. Where there is groundless and measureless blindness to Being and powerlessness of Being (Seinsohnmacht)—and even such designations are far too positive to express what “Nothing” (Nichts) contains in contrast to “Being”—there is sudden openness to Being (Seinsoffenheit) and potency of Being (Seinsmächtigkeit).
…something attempts to creep in here, something that does not remove the Nothingness underlying Being (Seinsnichtigkeit) but, on the contrary, only makes it more glaring (krasser)! As we have already seen, in the initial elevation toward Being—as characterized by the I in its openness to Being—the Nothingness from which this wondrous inception arises is overcome yet remains unconquered. That is why our gaze turns away from this origin in Nothingness, from this mere elevation toward Being, and instead is drawn toward the immeasurably and infinitely filled abyss and groundlessness of Being. Yet even this fullness of Being does not carry us beyond the boundaries of Nothingness (Nichtigkeitsgrenzen).
6. Epilogue: The Invisible Depth Amidst Reality
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Recent scholarship has foregrounded the nexus between phenomenology’s constitutive task of manifestation and the broader question of revelation. Notably, see Gschwandtner (2024). Likewise, James G. Hart explores this nexus in Hedwig Conrad-Martius’ Ontological Phenomenology (Hart 2020, p. 22 ff). Drawing on this view, he discusses HCM’s understanding of appearances as the medium through which the “in itself” is revealed (p. 146) and elaborates on its imprint in HCM’s philosophy of nature (p. 158). |
2 | In his early Freiburg lectures, Heidegger characterizes the word “given” (gegeben) as the “magic word (Zauberwort) of phenomenology” (Heidegger 1992, GA 58, §1 5). Husserl established that the “phenomenological sphere” reaches no farther than self-givenness (selbstgegebenheit) reaches (Husserl 1950, Hua II, 10/Idea 8). For further reading, see Spiegelberg 1984b. |
3 | For further reading, see Heidegger’s references to the verb phainesthai, in (Heidegger 2004, GA 64:4; 2005, GA 15, pp. 333–34). |
4 | See also Bulhof (2012, pp. 67–68). Husserl also assumed an invisible inner element tied to the “eidos” or the constant, necessary, and unchanging essence, residing in the ideal and invisible interiority of phenomena. See Husserl [1901] 1984a, Hua XIX/1, I §2 31–32, and also: Husserl [1913] 1952, Hua III/1, § 1 10–11. |
5 | This method was meant to study the lawfulness of essences that are operative in worldly phenomena. See Husserl [1901] 1984a, Hua XIX/1, 10. Husserl first introduced the method of “essence intuition” in Logical Investigations as a means of overcoming various forms of reductionism. See in particular: Husserl [1901] 1984a, Hua XIX/1 §23, §31, “The Theory of Whole and Parts” (Husserl [1913] 1952, Hua III/1, §1–17 10–38; [1901] 1984a, Hua XIX/1 III, 227–300). For an outstanding presentation of this method, see Reinach [1914] 1989. |
6 | Among the leading members of the circle: Alexander Pfänder, Johannes Daubert, Moritz Geiger, Theodor Conrad, Adolf Reinach, Maximilien Beck, Max Scheler, and Jean Hering. The younger members of the group were: Hans Lipps, Dietrich von Hildebrand, Alexandre Koyré, Roman Ingarden, Edith Stein, and Hedwig Conrad-Martius. For a detailed discussion of the background of the Munich-Göttingen Circle, see Miron 2023, pp. 22–48. See also Rosenward 1989. |
7 | See Seifert’s analysis of the uniqueness of Munich phenomenology as a philosophical phenomenon unparalleled in the history of modern thought (Seifert 1971, p. 97). |
8 | Edmund Husserl’s turn to transcendental idealism first surfaced in his 1906–1907 Göttingen lectures (published posthumously as Husserl 1950, Hua II) and was formally announced with the 1913 publication of Ideas I (Husserl [1913] 1952, Hua III/1). Hedwig Conrad-Martius referred to Ideen in her 1916 manuscript “Über Ontologie” (published in: Parker 2020). Edith Stein noted that Ideen “included some expressions which sounded very much as though their master wished to return to idealism” (ESGA 1, 200). However, Husserl’s crisis over the direction of his work actually began in 1905, culminating in his pivotal 1906 reflection on its significance (Biemel 1950, vii). Conrad-Martius asserted that “Husserl’s incomprehensible retreat to transcendentalism, to subjectivism, if not to psychologism, occurred already in volume 2 of the Logical Investigations” (Husserl [1901] 1984a, Hua XIX/1; Conrad-Martius [1958] 1965a, p. 395). |
9 | “HCM” was Conrad-Martius’s nickname among her pupils at the University of Munich. See Avé-Lallemant 1959, p. 24. |
10 | Conrad-Martius arrived in Göttingen in autumn 1911 and studied with Husserl and Reinach until summer 1912 (Ferrarello 2015, p. 52). For her leadership of the Munich–Göttingen circle, see Avé-Lallemant 1975b, p. 193; Hart 2020, p. 1–4. |
11 | Local phenomenologists even dubbed the episode the “Munich Invasion of Göttingen.” Cf. Baring (2019, p. 78). Regarding the importance of Logical Investigations for the Munich phenomenologists, see Spiegelberg 1959, p. 60. |
12 | For further reading see Spiegelberg 1984a, pp. 679–81; Ströker 1993, pp. 3–12; Farber 2009, pp. 99–136. |
13 | Spiegelberg asserted that “Husserl’s Logical Investigations was the bible” for the Munich-Göttingen Circle (Spiegelberg 1959, p. 60). See also (Miron 2023, p. 27). Hart notes that, for Conrad-Martius, Husserl’s influence is most clearly seen in the Prolegomena (Hua XVIII), whereas “the impact of the six investigations is not nearly so evident” (Hart 2020, p. 19). See also Spiegelberg 1959. |
14 | See here also Conrad-Martius [1912] 1920, p. 107; Stein 2002 (ESGA 1), 200; (Geiger 1933, p. 13; Miron 2023, pp. 35–43). |
15 | The reference to Pfänder derives from a handwritten note in Theodor Conrad’s Nachlass—where Conrad quotes Pfänder—in ANA 378, A VI 5, p. 8. This citation is given in Avé-Lallemant and Schuhmann (1992, p. 87). |
16 | |
17 | For Conrad-Martius, the capacity to discern essences in things hinges on the very identity and stance of the phenomenologist (Conrad-Martius [1958] 2015, p. 61; Pfeiffer 2008, p. 448), since essences do not disclose themselves to the ordinary gaze. |
18 | The method of epoché was introduced in his lecture courses prior its appearance in print in Ideas I (Husserl [1913] 1952, Hua III.1 §31–§32), see Husserl 1950, Hua II, pp. 29, 43; 1984b, Hua XXIV, §33–§35. |
19 | Celms, a student of Husserl in Freiburg, examined in detail the distinction between the phenomenological epoché and the phenomenological reduction (Celms 1993, pp. 117–55). He argued that Husserl, by failing to draw this distinction clearly, ultimately arrived at a form of “metaphysical spiritualism.” From a phenomenological perspective, Celms held that only the epoché is justifiable—understood as a suspension of judgment that entails no ontological commitment regarding the reality of the world (Celms 1993, pp. 188–96). Avé-Lallemant notes that Conrad-Martius was familiar with Celms’s writings (Avé-Lallemant 1971, p. 229). For further discussion, see Parker 2021 for the broader debate on realism and idealism, and Miron (2021) for a focused account of Conrad-Martius’s position within it. |
20 | Likewise, she elsewhere poses the rhetorical question of whether “this noematic world that is also really real (wirklich wirklich) [is] entirely left open” (Conrad-Martius [1958] 1965a, p. 396). For HCM’s explicit rejection of Husserl’s phenomenological reduction, see Conrad-Martius [1931] 1963e, pp. 19–24, 228–30; [1930] 1963f, p. 43; [1958] 1965a, pp. 394–402. For further discussion, see Pfeiffer (2005, pp. 31–32). Husserl criticized Conrad-Martius’s metaphysical approach (Husserl 1994, p. 20) and accused the Munich phenomenologists of “half-measures (Halbheiten)” for rejecting the phenomenological reduction, denying them the status of genuine phenomenologists or philosophers (Husserl 1959, p. 285; Avé-Lallemant 1975a, p. 28). He likewise labeled other works, including those of his Jahrbuch co-editors, as “pseudo-phenomenologies” and “essentially different” from his own; on Geiger and Pfänder, see Schuhmann (1990, pp. 23–24); on Scheler as a “fake phenomenologist” (Talmiphänomenologe), see Spiegelberg (1959, p. 59). |
21 | In this context, Conrad-Martius’s reference to Peter Wust’s observation, which identified an interest in mystery at the very inception of the phenomenological movement, is noteworthy. “From the very beginning,” he said, “there must have been hidden in the intention of that new philosophical direction something entirely mysterious: a longing to return to the objective, to the holiness of being, to the purity and chastity of things, to the ‘things themselves.’” (Conrad-Martius 1960, p. 62). Cited also in: (Hart 2020, p. 19). The aspect of mystery plays a significant role in Conrad-Martius’s conception of the “soul”; see Conrad-Martius [1921] 2023. In addition, this aspect encompasses the Christian dimensions of her thought. For further reading, see Gschwandtner 2022, pp. 85–103; Betschart 2022, pp. 29–40. |
22 | This article continues, in a basic sense, a discussion from my 2016 study on the internality of being—an internality that, as such, is invisible (see Miron 2016, 2023, pp. 345–72). More importantly, the present article goes several steps further by articulating the topos of invisibility within being. It nevertheless stands on its own and does not require prior familiarity with the 2016 article. |
23 | Elsewhere, the element of “Transcendence” is discussed as playing a key role in within the phenomenology of externality. See Miron 2023, pp. 123–39. |
24 | Realontologie—Conrad-Martius’s magnum opus—survives in two drafts (Erste Fassung 1915–1919, Conrad-Martius 1919–1922, N). The version published in Husserl’s Jahrbuch derives from the mature second draft (Conrad-Martius 1924) and unfolds in three parts: Realität (§159–190), Materialität (§191–245), and Konkrete Stoffgestaltung (§246–333), the latter subdivided into Materiale Konstitution (§246–282), Ton und Geräusch (§283–295), Temperatur (§296–303), and Licht (§304–333). The Licht section was later extended in two Jahrbuch contributions: “Farben—Ein Kapitel aus Realontologie” (Conrad-Martius 1929a, §251–289) and “Geruch und Geschmack” (Conrad-Martius 1929b, N, §290–309), with portions overlapping material from both drafts. An unpublished “Historisch-metaphysische Anmerkung,” intended to conclude Realität, also appears in the archive (without archival reference). |
25 | Elsewhere, Conrad-Martius speaks of “an unmediated and immediate wedding (Vermählung) of substantial fullness with abyss (μῆον/meonic)” (Conrad-Martius 1924, p. 225). The Greek term μῆον denotes a form of void or nothingness that—unlike an absolute blank—can be transformed into material reality |
26 | This positive role of the abyss in explicating material being is explored at length in Realontologie (Conrad-Martius 1924, pp. 191–246); see also Miron 2023, p. 228. |
27 | In her 1913 dissertation—slightly revised in the 1916 publication—Conrad-Martius introduces the term “self” to ground the autonomy of the real against the “I” and consciousness. External objects are characterized by various facets of selfhood: unveiled self-emerging (Selbsthervortreten), self-announcement (Selbstkundgabe), self-existence (Selbstdasein) (Conrad-Martius 1916, p. 371), corporeal self (leibhaftiges Selbst), self-performance (Selbstdarbietungseigenschaft) (Conrad-Martius 1916, pp. 411, 494), and self-presentation (Conrad-Martius 1916, p. 413), among others (Conrad-Martius 1916, pp. 430–55, 464–65, 471, 474, 514). |
28 | For further reading on the dual structure of the I, see Miron 2019. |
29 | Conrad-Martius was among the first women to complete a dissertation and obtain academic promotion at a German university (Stein 2013, 7 n. 10). The dissertation expanded the opening chapter of her 1912 essay (Conrad-Martius [1912] 1920, pp. 10–24), which had won the University of Göttingen prize and was designated The Prize Essay (Die Preisschrift) (Conrad-Martius [1912] 1920, pp. 10–24). For further discussion, see Miron 2023, pp. 3–6. |
30 | Conrad-Martius attributes to the real being a distinctive potency, stating: “Whatever by itself ‘cannot’ is also incapable of anything else, whereas the real alone is such that by itself ‘can’ (Könnende)” (Conrad-Martius 1924, p. 177). In the context of invisibility, this property of real being is evident in its refusal to appear and as a barrier to conscious accessibility. |
31 | In the Doctrine of Appearance (Conrad-Martius 1916), Conrad-Martius sought to “rescue” the epistemological dimension through an ontological investigation of consciousness, ensuring its relation both to external objects and to transcendence (Miron 2023, pp. 133–36). This approach opposed her earlier critique of positivism. In Seinsphilosophie (1955), she later extended her critique to transcendental idealism, arguing: “We must examine consciousness itself ontologically… and we would find that, thus examined, pure consciousness radically points beyond itself and therefore ceases to be the measure of all beings and being” (Conrad-Martius [1931] 1963e, pp. 22–23). |
32 | Conrad-Martius argues that positivist approaches conflate “the independence of existences from consciousness” with “the real external world” (Conrad-Martius 1916, p. 391). For her, anything whose being is dependent cannot truly present itself as independent (Conrad-Martius 1916, p. 413). Spiegelberg adds that the subject’s independence is not an ontological essence of reality, but “a fundamental and essential result of reality,” distinct from the subject’s own real acts, which necessarily depend on the subject (Spiegelberg 1975, p. 132). |
33 | The term wirkliche Wirklichkeit first appears in Theodor Lipps’s 1899 lecture (Schuhmann and Smith 1985, p. 792) and in Johannes Daubert’s 1904 manuscript (ibid., p. 792). Husserl ([1913] 1952, Hua III/1 §18 55) uses it for the objective material thing transcending individual subjectivity and inaugurating the intersubjective sphere—thus, “actual reality.” Avé-Lallemant notes that for Husserl, this reality is an intentional unity of sensory appearances, whereas for Conrad-Martius, “real reality” means the independent, in-itself existence of the real being, prerequisite for any spatio-temporal fulfillment (Avé-Lallemant 1975a, p. 33). Kuhn adds that Conrad-Martius’s tautological phrasing stresses the real’s autonomy, not merely as a phenomenon for the I (Kuhn 1971, p. 2), though this may risk duplicating the “problem of reality” (ibid., p. 5). |
34 | Here I again draw on Fink’s notion of the “operative concept,” which he also refers to as “the shadow of philosophy.” See Fink 1957, p. 325. |
References
- Avé-Lallemant, Eberhard. 1959. Über Hedwig Conrad-Martius, zu ihrem 70 Geburtstage am 27. Februar 1958. In Spektrum des Geistes. Ein Quershnitt durch das Geistesschaffen der Gegenwart, Literaturkalender. 8 Jahrgang 1959. Edited by Voss Hartfrid. München: Hartfrid Voss Verlag, pp. 24–25. [Google Scholar]
- Avé-Lallemant, Eberhard. 1971. Phänomenologie und Realität: Vergleichende Untersuchungen zur ‘München-Göttinger’ und ‘Freiburger’ Phänomenologie (Habilitationsschrift). München. [Google Scholar]
- Avé-Lallemant, Eberhard. 1975a. Die Antithese Freiburg-München in der Geschichte der Phänomenologie. In Die Münchener Phänomenologie, Vorträge des Internationalen Kongresses in München 13–18 April 1971. Edited by Helmut Kuhn, Eberhard Avé-Lallemant and Reinhold Gladiator. (Phaenomenologica 65). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, pp. 19–38. [Google Scholar]
- Avé-Lallemant, Eberhard. 1975b. Die Nachlässe der Münchener Phänomenologen in der Bayrischen Staatsbibliothek, Catalogus Codicum manuscriptorum Bibliothecae Monacensis, Tomus (vol) X, part (pars) I. Wiesbaden: Otto Harrassowitz. [Google Scholar]
- Avé-Lallemant, Eberhard, and Karl Schuhmann. 1992. Ein Zeitzeuge über die Anfänge der phänomenologischen Bewegung: Theodor Conrad—Bericht aus dem Jahre 1954. Husserl Studies 9: 77–90. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Baring, Edward. 2019. Converts to the Real: Catholicism and the Making of Continental Philosophy. Cambridge and London: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Betschart, Christof. 2022. The Influence of Hedwig Conrad-Martius’s Early Conception of the Soul on Edith Stein’s “Individual and Community”. Hedwig Conrad-Martius and Edith Stein: Philosophical Encounters and Divides. Cham: Springer International Publishing. [Google Scholar]
- Biemel, W. 1950. Einleitung des Herausgegebers. In Edmund Husserl, Die Idee der Phänomenologie, Fünf Vorlesungen. Edited by W. Biemel. Husserliana II. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, pp. vii–xi. [Google Scholar]
- Bulhof, Ilse Nina. 2012. Wilhelm Dilthey: A Hermeneutic Approach to the Study of History and Culture. Cham: Springer Science & Business Media, vol. 2. [Google Scholar]
- Celms, Theodor. 1993. Der Phaenomenologische Idealismus Husserls Und Andere Schriften 1928–1943. Edited by Juris Rozenvalds. Frankfurt am Main, Berlin, New York and Paris: Peter Lang. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1913. Die erkenntnisstheoretischen Grundlagen des Positivismus. Zur Ontologie und Erscheinungslehre der realen Außenwelt, Conrad-Martiusiana, A.I. 2 [Nachlass]. München: Bavarian State Archive (BSM) in Munich. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1916. Zur Ontologie und Erscheinungslehre der realen Außenwelt: Verbunden mit einer Kritik positivistischer Theorien. In Jahrbuch für Phänomenologie und philosophische Forschung III. Halle: Max Niemeyer, pp. 345–542. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1919–1922. Realontologie II, Buch. (zweite Fassung). Conrad-Martiusiana, A.I.5, (§32–§48) 21 p. [Nachlass]. München: Bavarian State Archive (BSM) in Munich. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1920. Die erkenntnisstheoretischen Grundlagen des Positivismus. Bergzabern: Heinrich Müller. (Private print). First published 1912. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1921. Einleitung. In A. Reinach, Gesammelte Schriften. Halle: Max Niemeyer, pp. V–XXXVII. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1924. Realontologie. In Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung VI. Edited by I. Buch. Halle: Max Niemeyer, pp. 159–333. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1929a. Farben. Ein Kapitel aus der Realontologie. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, Festschrift für Edmund Husserl zum 70. Geburtstag gewidmet, Special Issue X. Halle: Max Niemeyer, pp. 339–70. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1929b. Geruch und Geschmack [§185–§206 299–257]. Conrad-Martiusiana, A.I. 6, 25 p. + 3 p. [Nachlass]. München: Bavarian State Archive (BSM) in Munich. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1931a. Entwurf zu einer universalen Schematik realen Seins, Conrad-Martiusiana, A.II. 2, 10 p. [Nachlass]. München: Bavarian State Archive (BSM) in Munich. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1931b. Skizze über den Sensualizmus, Phänomenalismus, Idealismus, Subjektivismus, Rationalizmus, Pantheismus einerseits und einer teleologischen, Kategorialen, realistischen, kosmischen Weltauffassung un dem Theismus enderseits, Conrad-Martiusiana, A.III. 4, 3 p. [Nachlass]. München: Bavarian State Archive (BSM) in Munich. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1951. Vorwort. In A. Reinach, Was ist Phänomenologie? Mit einem Vorwort von Hedwig Conrad-Martius. München: Kösel, pp. 5–17. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1957. Das Sein. München: Kösel. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, H. 1960. Edith Stein. In Edith Stein. 1960. Briefe an Hedwig Conrad-Martius. München: Kösel, pp. 59–83. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1963a. Dasein, Substantialität, Seele. Schriften zur Philosophie I: 194–227. First published 1932. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1963b. Die aktuelle Krisis des idealistischen Denkens. Schriften zur Philosophie I: 32–37. First published 1932. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1963c. Existentielle Tiefe und Untiefe von Dasein und Ich. Schriften zur Philosophie I: 228–44. First published 1934. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1963d. Sein und Nichts. Schriften zur Philosophie I: 89–100. First published 1931. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1963e. Seinsphilosophie. Schriften zur Philosophie I: 15–31. First published 1931. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, H. 1963f. Was ist Metaphysik? Schriften zur Philosophie I: 38–48. First published 1930. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1965a. Die transzendentale und die ontologische Phänomenologie. Schriften zur Philosophie III: 393–402. First published 1958. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, H. 1965b. Phänomenologie und Spekulation. In Schriften zur Philosophie. München: Kösel, vol. III, pp. 370–84. First published 1956. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, H. 1965c. Über das Wesen des Wesens. In Schriften zur Philosophie. München: Kösel, vol. III, pp. 335–56. First published 1956. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1965d. Wirkender und empfangender Geist. Schriften zur Philosophie III: 295–314. First published 1956. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 2015. Order of Merit of the Federal Republic of Germany, Acceptance Speech. Studia Phenomenologica XV: 60–63. First published 1958. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 2023. Die Seele. In Metaphysical Conversations and Phenomenological Essays. Edited, Translated, and with an Introduction by Christina M. Gschwandtner. Berlin and Boston: de Gruyter GmbH & Co KG, pp. 192–221. First published 1921. [Google Scholar]
- Dilthey, Wilhelm. 1968. Der Aufbau der geschichtlichen Welt in den Geisteswissenschaften; Gesammelte Schriften Bd. VII 5Auf. Stuttgart: Teubner. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, GS VII. [Google Scholar]
- Farber, Marvin. 2009. The Foundation of Phenomenology: Edmund Husserl and the Quest for A Rigorous Science of Philosophy. Frankfurt: Ontos. [Google Scholar]
- Ferrarello, Susi. 2015. Introduction, Hedwig Conrad-Martius: “Having and Being Existence”. Studia Phenomenologica XV: 51–55. [Google Scholar]
- Fink, Eugen. 1957. Operative Begriffe in Husserls Phänomenologie. Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung XI/3: 321–37. [Google Scholar]
- Geiger, Moritz. 1933. Alexander Pfänder methodische Stellung. In Neue Münchener philosophische Abhandlungen. Edited by Ernst Heller and Friedrich Löw. Leipzig: Johann Ambrosius Barth, pp. 1–16. [Google Scholar]
- Gschwandtner, Christina M. 2022. Eternal Being and Creaturely Existence: Hedwig Conrad-Martius and Edith Stein on Divine-Human Ontology. In Hedwig Conrad-Martius and Edith Stein: Philosophical Encounters and Divides. Edited by Antonio Calcagno and Ronny Miron. Cham: Springer International Publishing. [Google Scholar]
- Gschwandtner, Christina M. 2024. Phenomenology and Revelation: Introduction to the Special Issue. Journal for Continental Philosophy of Religion 6: 1–29. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hart, James G. 2020. Hedwig Conrad-Martius’ Ontological Phenomenology. In Women in the History of Philosophy and Sciences. Edited by Rodney K. B. Parker. Cham: Springer, vol. 5. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 1992. Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie, (WS 1919/20), Gesamtausgabe 58. Edited by Friedrich-Wilhelm v. Herrmann. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann. (GA 58). [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 2004. Der Begriff der Zeit, Gesamtausgabe 64, Hans-Helmut Gander (Hrsg). Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, (GA 64). [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 2005. Seminaire. Gesamtausgabe 15. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, (GA 15). [Google Scholar]
- Husserl, Edmund. 1950. Die Idee der Phänomenologie, Fünf Vorlesungen. Edited by H. Walter. Biemel II. Husserliana II. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff (Hua II). [Google Scholar]
- Husserl, Edmund. 1952. Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie: Phänomenologische Untersuchungen zur Konstitution. Edited by Zweites Buch and Marly Biemel. Husserliana IV. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. (Hua III/1). First published 1913. [Google Scholar]
- Husserl, Edmund. 1959. A Letter from Husserl [to Dorion Cairns] (21 March 1930). In Edmund Husserl 1859–1959—Recueil Commémoratif Publié A L’occasion De Centenaire De La Naissance Du Philosophe (Phaenomenologica 4). Edited by H. L. van Vreda and J. Taminiaux. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, pp. 283–85. [Google Scholar]
- Husserl, Edmund. 1968. Phänomenologische Psychologie: Vorlesungen Sommersemester 1925, Husserliana IX. Edited by W. Biemel. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, (Hua IX). [Google Scholar]
- Husserl, Edmund. 1984a. Logische Untersuchungen, Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis, Husserliana XIX/1. The Hague, Boston and Lancaster: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers. First published 1901. (Hua XIX/1). [Google Scholar]
- Husserl, Edmund. 1984b. Einleitung in die Logik und Erkenntnistheorie Vorlesungen 1906/07, Husserliana XXIV. Edited by Ullrich Melle. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. (Hua XXIV). [Google Scholar]
- Husserl, Edmund. 1994. Briefwechsel. Husserliana: Edmund Husserl Dokumente. Edited by K. Schuhmann. Band III, Teil 2: Die Münchener Phänomenologen. Dordrecht, Boston and London: Kluwer Academic Publishers. [Google Scholar]
- Kuhn, Helmut. 1971. Phänomenologie und “wirklich Wirklichkeit”. In Die Münchener Phänomenologie, Vorträge des Internationalen Kongresses in München, 13–18 April 1971 (Phaenomenologica 65). Edited by Helmut Kuhn, Eberhard Avé-Lallemant and Reinhold Gladiator. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff, pp. 1–7. [Google Scholar]
- Melle, Ullrich. 1984. Einleitung des Herausgegebers. In Husserl Edmund. Einleitung in die Logik und Erkenntnistheorie Vorlesungen 1906/07, Husserliana XXIV. Edited by Ullrich Melle. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, pp. XIII–LI, (Hua XXIV). [Google Scholar]
- Miron, Ronny. 2014. “The Gate of Reality”: Hedwig Conrad-Martius’ Idea of Reality in Realontologie. Phänomenologische Forschungen, 59–82. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Miron, Ronny. 2015. The Vocabulary of Reality. Human Studies 38: 331–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Miron, Ronny. 2016. In the midst of Being—A Journey into the Internality of Being in Hedwig Conrad-Martius’s Metaphysics. Discipline Filosofiche 26: 217–44. [Google Scholar]
- Miron, Ronny. 2017. The Ontological Exclusivity of the “I”. Phänomenologische Forschungen, 97–116. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Miron, Ronny. 2018. Essence, Abyss, and Self: Hedwig Conrad-Martius on the Non-Spatial Dimensions of Being. In Women Phenomenologists on Social Ontology. Edited by S. Luft and R. Hagengruber. Cham: Springer International Publishers, pp. 147–67. [Google Scholar]
- Miron, Ronny. 2019. The Duality of the I in the Thinking of Hedwig Conrad-Martius. Phänomenologische Forschungen, 71–98. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Miron, Ronny. 2021. The Metaphysical Absolutizing of the Ideal. Hedwig Conrad-Martius’ Criticism of Husserl’s Idealism. In The Idealism-Realism Debate in the Early Phenomenological Movement. Edited by Rodney Parker. Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 193–216. [Google Scholar]
- Miron, Ronny. 2023. Hedwig Conrad-Martius—The Phenomenological Gateway to Reality, 2nd Enlarged and Revised Edition. Cham: Springer Nature. [Google Scholar]
- Parker, Rodney K. B. 2020. “Über Ontologie”, Ein unveröffentlichtes Manuskript von Hedwig Conrad-Martius zu Husserls Ideen I. In Natur und Kosmos, Entwürfe der frühen Phänomenologie. Edited by Hans Rainer Sepp. Nordhausen: Traugott Bautz, pp. 211–16. [Google Scholar]
- Parker, Rodney K. B., ed. 2021. The Idealism-Realism Debate Among Edmund Husserl’s Early Followers and Critics. Cham: Springer. [Google Scholar]
- Pfeiffer, A. E. 2005. Hedwig Conrad-Martius, Eine Phänomenologische Sicht auf Natur und Welt. Würzburg: Orbis Phenomnologicus, Königshausen & Neumann. [Google Scholar]
- Pfeiffer, A. 2008. Ontological Phenomenology: The Philosophical Project of Hedwig Conrad-Martius. Axiomathes 18: 445–60. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Reinach, Adolf. 1989. Über Phänomenologie. In Sämtliche Werke, Textkritische Ausgabe 1. Edited by K. Schuhmann and B. Smith. München: Philosophia, pp. 532–50. First published 1914. [Google Scholar]
- Rosenward, Juris. 1989. The Phenomenological Ontology of the Göttingen Circle. Analecta Husserliana (ANHU) XXVII: 11–35. [Google Scholar]
- Schuhmann, Karl. 1990. Husserl’s Yearbook. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50: 1–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schuhmann, Karl, and B. Smith. 1985. Against Idealism: Johannes Daubert vs. Husserl’s “Ideas” I. Review of Metaphysics, A Philosophical Quarterly 38: 763–93. [Google Scholar]
- Seifert, J. 1971. Über die Möglichkeit einer Metaphysik, Die Antwort der ‘Münchener Phänomenologen’ auf E. Husserl’s Transzendentalphilosophie. In Die Münchener Phänomenologie, Vorträge des Internationalen Kongresses in München, 13–18 April 1971. Edited by H. Kuhn, E. Avé-Lallemant and R. Gladiator. The Hague: Springer, pp. 81–104. [Google Scholar]
- Spiegelberg, Herbert. 1959. Perspektivenwandel: Konstitution eines Husserlbildes. In Edmund Husserl 1859–1959—Recueil Commémoratif Publié A L’occasion De Centenaire De La Naissance Du Philosophe (Phaenomenologica 4). Edited by H. Leo van Vreda and J. Taminiaux. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, pp. 56–63. [Google Scholar]
- Spiegelberg, Herbert. 1975. How Subjective is Phenomenology? In Doing Phenomenology: Essays on and in Phenomenology (Phaenomenologica 63). Edited by Herbert Spiegelberg. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, pp. 72–79. [Google Scholar]
- Spiegelberg, Herbert. 1984a. The Phenomenological Movement: A Historical Introduction. Third revised and enlarged edition with the collaboration of Karl Schuhmann (Phaenomenologica 5/6). The Hague, Boston, MA, and Lancaster: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, Kluwer Academic Publishing. [Google Scholar]
- Spiegelberg, Herbert. 1984b. Three Types of the Given: The Encountered, the Search-Found, and the Striking. Husserl Studies 1: 69–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stein, Edith. 2002. Aus dem Leben einer jüdischen Familie: Und weitere autobiographische Beiträge, Edith Stein Gesamtausgabe. Edited by Neyer Maria Amata OCD [Ordo Carmelitarum Discalceatarum]. Freiburg, Basel and Wien: Herder, (ESGA 1). [Google Scholar]
- Stein, Edith. 2013. Endliches und Ewiges Sein, Versuch eines Aufstiegs zum Sinn des Seins, ESGA 11/12, 2nd Auf., Eingeführt und bearbeitet von Andreas Uwe Müller. Freiburg, Basel, and Vienna: Herder. [Google Scholar]
- Ströker, Elisabeth. 1993. Husserl’s Transcendental Phenomenology. Translated by L. Hardy. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Miron, R. The Reality of the Invisible: The Phenomenology of Invisibility in H. Conrad-Martius’s Metaphysical Realism. Religions 2025, 16, 1240. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16101240
Miron R. The Reality of the Invisible: The Phenomenology of Invisibility in H. Conrad-Martius’s Metaphysical Realism. Religions. 2025; 16(10):1240. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16101240
Chicago/Turabian StyleMiron, Ronny. 2025. "The Reality of the Invisible: The Phenomenology of Invisibility in H. Conrad-Martius’s Metaphysical Realism" Religions 16, no. 10: 1240. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16101240
APA StyleMiron, R. (2025). The Reality of the Invisible: The Phenomenology of Invisibility in H. Conrad-Martius’s Metaphysical Realism. Religions, 16(10), 1240. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16101240