Next Article in Journal
Multilayered Faith and Interreligious Dialogue: A Case of Religious Hybridity in Korea and Its Implications for Formation
Previous Article in Journal
Ngytarma and Ngamteru: Concepts of the Dead and (Non)Interactions with Them in Northern Siberia
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

God, Philosophers and Theologians in Africa

by
Patrick O. Aleke
1,2
1
Philosophy Department, St Joseph’s Theological Institute, Hilton 3245, South Africa
2
School of Religion, Philosophy and Classics, University of KwaZulu-Natal, Durban 4041, South Africa
Religions 2024, 15(6), 739; https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15060739
Submission received: 15 May 2024 / Revised: 14 June 2024 / Accepted: 15 June 2024 / Published: 18 June 2024

Abstract

:
There is renewed interest in philosophical and theological investigations about God, religions and the implications of religious beliefs among philosophers and theologians in Africa. This development is itself profitable because the question or the problem of God is a relevant discourse in Africa where the majority of people are theists. However, unlike the exploration of the first-generation African scholars—philosophers and theologians—whose primary objective was to show the symmetry between Christianity and African Traditional Religions (ATR), contemporary discourses arise within the clamour for decoloniality. The investigations, with varied emphasis, advocate the decolonisation of the concept of God, epistemic decolonisation, decolonisation of Christianity and African Christian theology, etc. In this essay, I critically examine the contemporary decolonial discourse about God, divine attributes, religious belief, and the relationship between African Christian theology and ATR. I argue that most of the contemporary literature is entangled in conceptual convolution and as such, there is a lack of clarity about what needs to be decolonised. Put differently, most works do not clearly distinguish between reality (the person or phenomenon “God”), thought (the concept “God”), and conceptions of God (language, that is, the terms and images used in making assertions about God). Further, I argue that when conceptual clarifications are adequately attended to, there is no need for decolonisation of discourses about God, divine nature, divine attributes, and the relationship between Christianity and ATR.

1. Introduction

The renewed interest among philosophers in the problem of God and the relevance of religions and religious beliefs might prima facie seem strange, especially in this age. Philosophical naturalism and atheism are ideologies that are promoted to an extent that suggests naturalism and atheism are the default position (Flew 1976). However, a critical analysis of the situation would readily admit that the revival of philosophical and theological discourses about God, religion, and the relationship between Christianity and African traditional religions can be expected. This is the case because the problem of God is a perennial problem that is at the foundation of human questioning. What is meant by God, in this paper, is the Supreme Being, the Necessary Being, the Uncaused Cause or what monotheists call the Creator. Put differently, “God is the ultimate, ungrounded Ground of all reality that sustains and moves everything” (Kasper 1983, p. 4). So understood, it is problematic to talk of gods because it would simply be an equivocation. Consequently, talking of the Christian God, or the African God (gods), etc., does not imply a plurality of Gods but describes different conceptions of God, shaped by a variety of contextual and creedal differences.
The problem of God and the relevance of religion are human problems that neither atheism nor naturalism can eliminate. Whenever the questions of origin, meaning, and destiny of the human person are raised, the problem of God surfaces, whether explicitly or implicitly. The renewed interest in philosophy of religion, the quest for a robust African Christian theology and a Christian theology of African Traditional Religions are corollaries of the African worldview in which God is not an addendum but a fundamental element.
However, unlike the first-generation African scholars—philosophers and theologians—whose primary objective was to articulate the intelligibility and reasonableness of African cultures and religious traditions and thereby counter “any Western scholar who describes African culture and regions in disparaging terms” (p’Bitek 1970, p. 41), contemporary interest in the question of God is rooted in the decoloniality project. The quest for decolonisation, that is, the elimination of colonial residues that tend to stifle the flourishing of Africans whether epistemically, religiously, culturally or linguistically, is more complicated than it seems at first instance. In fact, the complexity is intrinsic to the concept of decolonisation itself. For instance, one might ask whether it is possible for a scholar who is trained in the “colonial tradition” to decolonise, since the method one employs and one’s thought pattern are coloured by colonial vestiges. Secondly, it is arguable that the use of a European language in the decolonization project is a contradiction or at least a paradox. Since my objective here is neither to defend nor oppose the decoloniality project generically in contemporary scholarship, I will not engage with these considerations in this paper.
Despite the favourable acceptance that the quest for decolonisation enjoys in the fields of philosophy and theology, it is not clear what the proponents of the decoloniality project want to be decolonised when it comes to the question of God and religion. Most works that argue for decolonisation do not clearly distinguish between reality (the person or phenomenon “God”), thought (the concept “God” or the conceptions of “God”) or language (terms and images used in making assertions about God). My claim is that when conceptual clarification is adequately addressed, the quest for decolonisation is solved because there is then no longer a need for decolonisation when regarding discourses about God, divine nature, divine attributes and relations between Christianity and African Traditional Religions (ATR). This is because if God exists, then there is only one God regardless of the various conceptions of God. The different conceptions arise only because of various contextual and creedal differences. To defend my position, in the first section I critically explore and examine contemporary philosophical discourses on God while in the second section I explore the quest for the decolonisation of African Christianity and the Christian conception of God among theologians.

2. God and Philosophers in Africa

As a point of departure in this section, I would like to state that I have deliberately chosen to designate this section “God and Philosophers in Africa” rather than “God in African Philosophy” because the adjectives that are placed before “philosophy” only qualify the substantive, which is philosophy. The role of the adjectives, in this context, is to highlight the context of philosophising or the space from where one philosophises.
Contemporary philosophical discourses about God are carried within the decolonial project. They seek to know whether “African gods”, or rather African conceptions of God, can be captured within the traditional monotheistic conception of God, especially the conception of God in Christianity. Or whether Okot p’Bitek’s (1970) claim that the early African nationalists and scholars, Jomo Kenyatta, Leopold Sedar Senghor, J. B. Danquah, K. A. Busia and John Mbiti, in their works “dress up African deities with Hellenic robes and parade them before the Western world” (p’Bitek 1970, p. 41) is cogent or not. Hence, issues in contemporary philosophy of religion in Africa focus on the traditional problem of evil, and the nature and attributes of God (Mbiti 1969, 1975; Bewaji 1998; Gyekye 1998; Wiredu 1998; Fayemi 2012; Agada 2022a, 2022b; Cordeiro-Rodrigues and Agada 2022; Majeed 2022; Aleke 2023). Philosophy of Religion within the decolonisation project in Africa is a continuation of the quest for the legitimacy of African philosophy and African epistemic heritage in the face of rejection and/or criticism by the “so-called Western philosophers”.
Situating contemporary discourse on philosophy of religion in Africa within the decolonisation project and the quest for the legitimisation of African philosophy, Cordeiro-Rodrigues and Agada (2022, p. 5) assert: “The debate in African Philosophy of Religion is therefore shaped by questions about decolonisation and liberation. These questions are grounded in the project of reconstructing an authentic African identity which can be both autonomous and sophisticated, dispensing with the need for it to be driven by European concepts”. While such a project seems noble, it is doubtful that it is attainable. Put differently, one wonders whether it is possible to reconstruct pure pre-colonial African experience that is not influenced and affected by colonisation and the intellectual exchange that has taken place between Africans and Westerners. Secondly, an exaggerated decolonisation project seems to overvalue philosophical space and context while subtly undermining the fact that philosophising is a human phenomenon and enterprise. Thirdly, a decolonisation project that seeks unadulterated African experiences and “authentic African identity” runs the risk of being irrelevant to Africans because it gradually turns into an intellectual jamboree among scholars who, ultimately, are seeking the endorsement of European and North American scholars.
Of course, decolonisation could also mean critical reflection and appraisal as espoused by Kwasi Wiredu (1998). Such an understanding of decolonisation does not entail an a priori rejection of non-African conceptual frameworks and categories. According to Wiredu (1998, p. 17), decolonisation is the “divesting of African philosophical thinking of undue influences emanating from our colonial past”. This conception of decolonisation does not begin by envisaging African and non-African conceptual frameworks and systems as being contrary or essentially contradictory. This conception of decolonisation is essentially a common feature of philosophy as a critical reflective discipline. What this entails is that critical engagement on God and religion in Africa should not be confined to purely descriptive, phenomenological or linguistic analysis.
Contemporary philosophical discourses on God in Africa tend to be descriptive. In other words, they outline the cultural practices among different ethnic groups and the languages that different African traditions use in discussions about God in myths, proverbs, legends, songs and ritual practices, and tend to draw conclusions from them without critical engagement with the reasons for the use of such language. Such discussions tend to ignore the fact that all human language about God and the divine is analogous and not univocal. Wiredu (1998) in his particularistic approach contends that decolonisation of African philosophy and religion should be based on an analysis of African languages and customs in order to disentangle conceptual imposition. The danger with this approach that places emphasis on analysis of language is that it tends to underestimate the inherent limitations of language. Consequently, conceptions of God by different ethnic groups or African traditions are equated with the person of God and thereby they fail to distinguish between language and reality. This lack of distinction leads to infelicitous expressions like African God(s), Christian God, Muslim God, etc. I call these expressions infelicitous because while the expression “African God(s)” is in essence a short-hand for African conceptions of God, it can be interpreted to mean that there are various Gods in reality. Conceptual convolution between African conceptions of God and the person “God” is common in contemporary discourses on the problem of evil in Africa. For instance, John Bewaji (1998) and Ademola Fayemi (2012) from their analyses of Yoruba religious texts reach the conclusion that God is both good and evil and so is limited and not perfect or omnipotent. This, in their view, implies that the Yoruba God is different from the Christian God or traditional monotheistic God and, in so doing, they agree with p’Bitek (1970) who argues that African deities are different to the Christian God. A question that imposes itself immediately when one reads such decolonisation discourses is, are there different Gods or are there different conceptions of the same God? Clearly if God is taken to be the Ultimate Ground of all reality or the Uncaused Cause or Supreme Being, then there is only one God, but there are different conceptions of God. The different conceptions of God arise because of contextual differences, plurality of religious experiences, and different models of revelation. Cognisant of the conceptual confusion between God and conceptions of God, E. Bolaji Idowu (1973, p. 146) asserts:
There is no being like “the African God” except in the imagination of those who use the term, be they Africans or Europeans… there is only one God, and while there may be various concepts of God, according to each people’s spiritual perception, it is wrong to limit God with an adjective formed from the name of any race.
While some scholars like (p’Bitek 1970; Wiredu 1998; Bewaji 1998; Fayemi 2012) would disagree with Idowu, a non-parochial philosophical approach would readily agree with him. As I have already mentioned, if God exists and is the Supreme Being or a necessary being, then there cannot be more than one God. Pius Mosima (2022, p. 159) who holds a similar view, asserts that “images are just ways human beings try to describe God but none of them adequately captures who God is”. No analysis of language, no matter how rigorous it might be, can equate the conceptions of God with the person “God”. Therefore, any attempt to claim that the African God is different from the Christian God just because the African conception of God is different from the Christian conception of God is a category mistake.
Such category mistakes have given rise to some contentious questions such as the limited God thesis and the quest for a material God. The limited God thesis is based on the fact that there is evil in the world and, since there is evil in the world, God is not perfect and, consequently, is neither omnipotent nor omnibenevolent. Bewaji (1998) and Fayemi (2012) argue that some Yoruba religious texts attest to the fact that Olodumare, the Yoruba God, is both good and evil, and sometimes seeks knowledge from other deities. Another reason for the defence of a limited God is the rejection of the doctrine of creation ex nihilo by Wiredu (1998, p. 30) because the Akan word bo which is normally translated as “to create” excludes the possibility of creating out of nothing. In his view, bo means to make or to fashion out of pre-existing materials. Consequently, he argues that in the Akan worldview, God as Oboade is a cosmic architect and not a creator. This interpretation resonates with Immanuel Kant’s (1999) position in his contention against the physico-theological argument for the existence of God. It is important to mention that Wiredu’s interpretation of bo and boade is contested by Hasskei Majeed (2022, pp. 62–63) who argues that the Akan terms bo and boade do not presuppose pre-existing material out of which one creates. In line with this position, Kwame Gyekye argues that Onyame is the Creator who creates the universe ex nihilo.
Apart from the contestation of the meaning of bo and boade by Akan scholars, a crucial question that one needs to ask is this: “Does the existence of evil and rejection of creatio ex nihilo warrant the affirmation of a limited rather than perfect God?” My answer is that the affirmation of a limited God is not warranted. The conclusion that because there is evil in the world, God is limited, is based on the dubious assumption that African conceptions of God are a perfect description of God. However, no conceptions of God, whether African or non-African, are a perfect description of God. All conceptions of God that are mainly descriptive suffer from phenomenological limitations. In fact, any religious or theological language is analogous and not univocal. That means that when the same attribute is ascribed to God and humans, there is both similarity and difference because divine nature is different from human nature. Besides, the transition from outlining African conceptions of God, be they Akan, Yoruba, Luo, Órring, Zulu, Igbo, to the conclusion that an “African God(s)” who is (are) limited does not take into consideration the overwhelming anthropomorphism in African religious texts, whether written or oral. The use of anthropomorphism was probably designed to facilitate easy remembrance and to underline their existential import since African religious traditions were originally conserved orally in myths, legends, proverbs and riddles. Therefore, the primary objective of African conceptions of God was not to articulate a coherent philosophical or theological argument but to encourage adherents of religious traditions to live a virtuous life. Consequently, while I agree that African conceptions of God are different from non-African conceptions of God, I contend that God is one. And if God exists, there is only one God who, if God is to be considered as the Ground of all things that exist, must be understood as being ontologically perfect.
The presence of evil in the world does not justify the claim that God is limited. I have argued elsewhere that God’s omni-attributes (omnipotence, omniscience and omnibenevolence) are not contradictory to the reality of evil in the world because while it can be argued that God is capable of doing everything, it does not follow that God must do everything to satisfy the preferences of human beings (Aleke 2023). Those who claim that there is a logical necessity between the two implicitly claim to have a God’s-eye view of reality. The reality of evil in the world is just a manifestation of the fact that the world is not perfect. And it is contradictory to expect a created or caused universe to be perfect. Perfection, in the ontological sense, means being absolutely independent. Being created or caused implies being dependent. Of course, it could be objected that even if humans are not ontologically perfect, they can be morally perfect. Nonetheless, I contend that an ontologically imperfect being cannot be morally perfect because moral perfection is founded on ontological perfection.
As I have already mentioned, another reason why a limited God rather than an unlimited God, that is, a perfect God, is postulated in contemporary philosophy of religion in Africa is the rejection of the doctrine of creation ex nihilo in some African conceptions of God, e.g., the Akan conception of God (Wiredu 1998). Wiredu’s argument is based on his analysis of the Akan terms bo and boade, which he claims presuppose pre-existing material out of which one creates. Hence if God is Oboade (Creator) then it does not make sense to opine that God creates out of nothing. Wiredu’s position does not go unopposed by Akan scholars who are philosophers. From his analysis of Akan language and religious tradition, Gyekye (1998) defends the doctrine of creation ex nihilo. Majeed (2022, pp. 62–63) illustrates with examples that the Akan terms bo and boade do not presuppose pre-existing materials out of which one can make things. Nonetheless, he agrees with Wiredu “that the idea of nothingness, creating out of nothing, requires proper formulation in Akan philosophy” (Majeed 2022, p. 63).
In the spirit of decolonisation, understood as critical reflection, which Wiredu (1998) advances, the inevitable questions that arise are: What does the doctrine of creatio ex nihilo really mean? Does it make sense to argue that God created the universe and the things in it from pre-existing materials? The doctrine of creatio ex nihilo is founded on an interpretation of the biblical account of creation in Genesis 1:1-2:4a. It alludes to the relationship between God and the universe, the Creator and the creation or the created. According to that account (unlike the second account in Genesis 2:4b-25), God did not use any raw material or pre-existing matter to create the universe and all the things that are in it. He only used his words and things came to be. That is why the expression “God said” is very crucial in the first creation account in the book of Genesis. When interpreted in the light of the first creation account, the expression creatio ex nihilo is a shorthand for “God created the universe and everything in it out of nothing but His words”. What is emphasised is not absolute nothingness but that there were no pre-existing material things prior to creation by God. In fact, it would be philosophically uninspiring to allude to the idea that there were pre-existing material things out of which God created the universe, if by material things is meant extended reality, that is, things that occupy space. This is because prior to the creation of the universe or the world, there was no space and hence, there would not be pre-existing material things. Therefore, the doctrine of creatio ex nihilo emphasises the nature of God as the Supreme Being or Uncaused Cause who was able to bring the universe into being through His powerful word. The objective of the doctrine of creatio ex nihilo is not to juxtapose being and nothingness but to highlight the nature of God, whose attributes include omnipotence. If one acknowledges that the universe and all material things (even the so-called pre-existing materials) are contingent, that is, that they are not necessary beings but beings that began to exist, then it is philosophically more illuminating to defend the doctrine of creatio ex nihilo than to argue that God created the universe out of pre-existing material things. Paul Cogan and William Lane Craig emphasise what creatio ex nihilo means by quoting Thomas Torrance:
The creation of the universe out of nothing does not mean the creation of the universe out of something that is nothing, but out of nothing at all. It is not created out of anything—it came into being through the absolute fiat of God’s Word in such a way that whereas previously there was nothing, the whole universe came into being.
To avoid ambiguity about the correct understanding of creation out of nothing, Cogan and Craig pointed out that as used by Torrance “whereas previously there was nothing” is an incorrect expression. They comment as a footnote:
Technically, however, this is incorrect. Torrance needs to say that “it was not the case that there was anything previously.” To say “previously there was nothing” implies that there was a moment of time prior to creation at which nothing existed; whereas, to say “it was not the case that there was anything previously” is to deny even the existence of the prior moment as well as anything else before creation.
To advance the notion of a limited God by opining that God created out of pre-existing materials demands an explanation of the origin of the pre-existing materials. Consequently, the fact that the expression creatio ex nihilo cannot be articulated meaningfully in the Akan language or any other African language for that matter, does not undermine the explanatory power of the doctrine. In fact, the issue in question is not whether creatio ex nihilo is meaningful and coherent. Rather, the issue in contention is whether some languages, e.g., the Akan language, have an adequate conceptual framework to articulate some abstract philosophical thinking. Put differently, the question that is raised by Wiredu (1998) is not primarily the problem about the doctrine of creatio ex nihilo. It is a problem about the limitation of the Akan language. One could argue that the reason for such limitation is that religious language and discourses on God in traditional African societies were symbolic in nature as they are relayed in myths and proverbs. Hence, philosophical discourse about God in Africa should not rely mainly on the analysis of language. It is incumbent on philosophers of African descent to widen the conceptual framework of African languages about God to enable abstract philosophical thinking that goes beyond analysis of symbolic expressions. To move from the analysis of African languages about God to the affirmation of a limited God in Africa is, at best, a disservice to the philosophical enterprise.
Having argued that the affirmation of a limited God is problematic, the possibility of a material God must be examined. Among the important questions to which answers, whether explicit or implicit, need to be provided before one can reasonably affirm or negate the existence of a material God, are these: What exactly would a material God be? What does the adjective “material” mean in this case? Can a material God be the First Cause, the Uncaused Cause, the Supreme Being or the Absolute Ground for the existence of the universe and all the things in it? From a superficial analysis of some African conceptions of God it could be argued that the affirmation of a material God is plausible. This plausibility is based on the fact that (1) there is overwhelming anthropomorphism in African religious texts, (2) material things like trees, rocks, rivers, et cetera are used to represent God in African traditional religions, and (3) God has the capacity to impress Himself on human consciousness (Attoe 2022). Are these reasons sufficient for the affirmation of a material God? I contend that these three reasons, whether individually or collectively, are not sufficient.
Aribiah David Attoe claims that the third reason given above is sufficient. His conclusion is based on his understanding of materiality. According to him, God is a material entity not because human beings are capable of perceiving God with their sense of sight, but because of God’s capacity to impress Godself on the conscious mind, whether directly or indirectly (Attoe 2022, p. 33; Mokoena 2022, p. 148). Attoe’s claim about the materiality of God is problematic for two reasons. First, his understanding of materiality is not the same as the classical understanding of materiality in the history of philosophy. To say that God is immaterial, non-material or spiritual means that God is not a composite being but simple, that is, not composed of matter and form. Put differently, this contention argues that there is no Aristotelian hylomorphic structure in God.
Aristotelian hylomorphism holds that material entities are composed of two co-principles, matter and form (Aristotle 1998). Material or composite beings are beings that both occupy space and have beginning in time, whereas non-material or immaterial beings do not occupy space because they are not composed. In ascribing materiality to God, Attoe deviates from the understanding of materiality for those who argue that God is not a material being. Nevertheless, arguing that God is immaterial or spiritual does not imply that God does not have influence in God’s world. Besides, arguing that God is an immaterial or a spiritual being does not mean that God’s presence is not felt by humans. It is because God’s presence is inevitably felt by human beings that God is said to be glorious. This is what is implied when it is said that God reveals Godself in nature.
The second problem with Attoe’s position is that in claiming that materiality means God’s capacity to impress Godself on the conscious mind, it is not clear what he means by God impressing Godself. It seems obvious that such capacity to impress does not arise out of perception by sight or hearing. How then does that the impression occur? Is it an automatic act by God or does it (also) necessitate a human act? I argue that human experience and questioning of one’s experience is essential for affirmation of God’s influence on human beings. Hence, it is not just a question of God impressing Godself on a conscious mind as Attoe seems to imply, but a matter of the human inquiry and critical attitude or spirit at work (Lonergan 1971, 1992)1. Consequently, claiming that God is a material entity because God has the capacity to impress Godself on a conscious mind is not philosophically illuminating. It is more illuminating to hold that in the quest for God, human beings make a reasonable affirmation based on their experience of God’s revelation and their understanding of this personal experience.
If Attoe’s main reason to claim that God is a material entity is to legitimize his assertion that God is a-thing-in-the-world, then questions with regard to what he means by ‘being in the world’ in relation to God need to be answered. God, according to him, is “regressively eternal and necessarily so”, and “the first cause from which other things-in-the-world emanate”. If God is regressively eternal as Attoe claims, then it would mean that non-existence cannot be ascribed to God since one cannot reasonably claim that there was a time God was not. The regressive argument for the existence of God goes back to Aristotle who referred to God as the Unmoved Mover, and more importantly to St Thomas Aquinas’s (1963) argument for God’s existence where, in the first and second ways, God is described as Unmoved Mover and Uncaused Cause, respectively. In this sense, God as the first cause cannot be on the same causal chain with secondary causes (caused causes). In addition, God as first cause cannot be a material thing-in-the-world since if God is regressively eternal then it must be explained whether there was God before the world or the universe came to be. Arguing that there exists a God who is a material God and regressively eternal is at best contraditio in terminus.
In this section, I have explored some issues in the contemporary discourses in philosophy of religion in Africa. I contended that the quest for decolonisation of God in Africa arises from conceptual confusion and category mistakes. This is because there is no clarity between the being God, the concept God, and the conceptions of God. In other words, there is a tendency of not distinguishing clearly between reality, thought, and language. In addition, I argue that the quest for a limited God or a material God is problematic because the proponents rely on descriptive methodology but their expositions are lacking explanatory clarity and precision. In the next section, I will engage with theological discourse within the decolonial paradigm in Africa.

3. God and Theologians in Africa

In general, contemporary theological discourses in Africa within the decolonisation paradigm are basically centred on the possible relationship held between African Traditional Religions (ATR) and Christianity. The positions that scholars mostly defend are that of continuity or discontinuity between ATR and Christianity/Christian Theology. A new position that is defended by Anné Verhoef (2021) is that of deconstruction. The early African religious scholars and theologians—for instance, E. Bolaji Idowu and John S. Mbiti—are considered as the proponents of the continuity approach. They argue that there is not an irreconcilable discontinuity between African Traditional Religions and Christianity. Nonetheless, they acknowledge that there are some differences in the conceptions of God but that ultimately the God of Jesus Christ and the Supreme Being of African Religion is one and the same God. Hence, the traditional attributes of God—omnipotence, omniscience, omnibenevolence—can be ascribed to God in African religious traditions (Mbiti 1969, 1975; Idowu 1973). It is important to note that the symmetry between African Traditional Religions and the Christian Religion that is defended by Mbiti and Idowu is the being “God” and not necessarily about the conceptions of God, that is, the manner in which God is understood and described in the two religious traditions.
Their scholarship is not founded on the decolonisation paradigm, as Teddy Chalwe Sakupapa (2019) claims. Mbiti (1969, p. 277) refers to African Traditional Religions as praeparatio evangelica. Such a depiction of the ATR is not decolonial in outlook. It highlights a symbiotic relationship between the Gospel and culture, Christianity and ATR. Therefore, the position of the pioneer scholars is better captured as adaptation, or what is called inculturation in Catholic theology. In fact, a critical analysis shows that the main objective of the early African scholars is to show that it is compatible to be both African and Christian as most of them were first generation Christians who probably were previously practitioners of African Traditional Religions. Theirs is a quest for articulation of African Christian identity (Bediako 1999).
Idowu’s exploration of African traditional religion, especially the Yoruba religious tradition, heritage and practices, is not aimed at the decolonisation of Christianity but at encouraging the establishment of an authentic African Christian identity so as to address a situation that was developing in Nigerian society, that of a proliferation of nominal Christians. A similar argument can be made of Mbiti’s theological project. His appreciation of African traditional religious heritage and spirituality is aimed at a genuine encounter between the Gospel or Christian faith, and African pre-Christian religious tradition and culture. Hence, the theological project of the early scholars was not decolonial but aimed at an authentic “incarnation of Jesus Christ” in African cultures and societies and in this way contributing to the emergence of a true African Christian identity. An indication that Mbiti’s theological enterprise is not a decolonial project is his insistence that Christianity is both traditional and African (Mbiti 1969, p. 277; Bediako 1999, p. 319). It is not only that Mbiti’s theological outlook is not a decolonial project but that he does not advocate for the decolonisation of God and the Gospel in African Christianity. He aptly captures his view in his comment on John W Kinney’s position where he observes that:
God the Father of our Lord Jesus Christ is the same God who for thousands of years has been known and worshipped in various ways within the religious life of African peoples, ‘and who, therefore’, was not a stranger in Africa prior to the coming of missionaries.
It is not an exaggeration to assert that the theological enterprise of the early scholars is not a decolonisation project. It is an attempt at the incarnation of the Gospel of Jesus Christ in the African context. It is from this standpoint that Mulago gwa Cikala Musharamina’s quest for the adaptation of Christianity in Africa and his insistence on the development of African Christian theology is properly understood (See Bediako 1999, pp. 347–85).
The position of the scholars who have a positive evaluation of African traditional religious beliefs and practices, and the proponents of African Christian theology, is sometimes referred to as the continuity approach between African Traditional Religions and Christianity. However, a critical consideration would readily admit that what the defenders of this view advocate is not strictly continuity between African Traditional Religions and Christianity. Rather, their position highlights that there is not a radical a priori anti-Christian element in African Traditional Religion. Their position is better understood as underscoring that Africans who were raised in African Traditional Religions can be truly Christian after conversion, and that their previous religious experience would not inhibit their new identity as African Christians. This is the case because the Gospel of Jesus Christ can be incarnated in any religious and cultural traditions. It would be a hermeneutical error to conclude that theologians and religious scholars in this group defend the continuity between the conceptions of God in both African Traditional Religions and Christianity.
Because of the importance of revelation and its understanding in various religious traditions, and different contextual experiences, conceptions of God are different in different religions and religious traditions, but the “concept” of God and the reality “God” is one and the same. Liborie Kagabo’s (2006, p. 30) view is similar to the one expressed here. While exploring the ‘correspondence between terms that designate the Supreme Being in African religions and the Christian one’, he affirms:
What is really decisive, primary and fundamental, is not the concept of a Supreme Being as crystallized at a certain moment in dogma: this is a result. What is decisive, primary and fundamental is the infinite number of individual and collective experiences endlessly repeated and that end up in giving place to a certain doctrine. They are the same questions that people of all places and time have asked themselves about their existence, the existence of the world, their origin and their destiny, with the different answers they give.
Kagabo’s thought as quoted can be interpreted as asserting that, despite different conceptions and expressions of God in different religions and socio-cultural contexts, the Being to whom reference is being made is one and the same. Hence, if the concept of “continuity” is to be used at all to identify the position of those who argue that there is a positive relation between African Traditional Religions and Christianity, then it should be restricted to meaning the continuity of the reality called God in the two religious traditions and the continuity in the identity of the person who converts from one religion to another. However, continuity simpliciter between African Traditional Religions and Christianity cannot be ascribed to the scholars of religions and theologians in this group.
In the same vein, the works of the early African scholars of religions and theologians cannot strictly be called decolonial or a proto-decolonisation project. Their works are attempts at articulating the incarnation of the Gospel of Jesus Christ in the African religious and cultural contexts. Put differently, the works of the early scholar can be situated within inculturation projects rather than decoloniality. It is not an exaggeration to claim that every theological project is incarnational in nature. In that light, “Western Christianity” is an incarnation of the Gospel in Western religious and cultural contexts, while “Western” theology is a contextual articulation of the incarnation of the Gospel of Jesus Christ. Hence, it is the Gospel as incarnated in the Western context that the Western missionaries brought to Africa, and that was all they could have done. The role of African theologians is not decolonial but inculturational, that is, the articulation of the incarnation of the Gospel of Jesus Christ in the African religious, social and cultural context. Highlighting the inevitability of Inculturation in the proclamation of the Gospel and Christian evangelisation in different cultural contexts, Liboire Kagabo asserts:
The main aim of Inculturation is double: evangelizing the culture on the one hand and inculturating the Gospel on the other. To begin with, the two paths respond to two different but complementary challenges. Starting from the first, the main question is to know how one can evangelize a culture at the same time drawing from its riches, even at the risk of somewhat compromising with it. As to the second, the question is to know how to inculturate the Gospel while remaining faithful to it. Doubtless it is a question of priority: it is the Gospel that ought to be announced as best as one can. But the two paths are complementary: it is not possible to evangelize the culture without at the same time inculturating the Gospel and it is not possible to inculturate the Gospel without evangelizing the culture.
It is because the incarnation of the Gospel of Jesus Christ in Africa is deemed to need some kind of symbiotic relationship that African theologians in the Catholic theological tradition emphasise inculturation theology rather than the decolonisation of Christianity (Nyamiti 1984; Magesa 1998, 2004; Bujo 2003; Bujo and Muya 2006; Orobator 2009, 2018). It is worth noting that the preference for inculturation theology by African Catholic theologians does not imply an uncritical acceptance of African traditional, cultural and religious practices. Neither does it mean a canonisation of elements of European or American Christianity that is stifling. Cognisant of the fact that Christianity in every age, place and time is always inculturated, theologians underscore that the proclamation of the Gospel is a cultural encounter. Magesa (2004, p. 17) expresses the critical and symbiotic elements that are indispensable in inculturation thus:
From the Christian theological perspective, inculturation is understood to be the process whereby the faith already embodied in one culture encounters another culture. In this encounter, faith becomes part and parcel of this new culture. It fuses with the new culture and simultaneously transforms it into a novel religious-cultural reality. In practical terms, this process involves the interaction of mutual critique and affirmation. It entails acceptance or rejection of thought forms, symbolic and linguistic expressions and attitudes between the faith-cultures in question.
What is highlighted by the quoted text is that inculturation is not an appendage to evangelisation and propagation of the Christian faith. Rather, it is an essential aspect of evangelisation since both the evangeliser and the evangelised are neither decultural nor noncultural. In the African context, the Christian is not a Christian in a vacuum. She or he is always a contextualised Christian, that is, an African Christian. Hence neither of the two aspects of her or his identity can be eliminated. Be that as it may, inculturation does not entail blind continuity between African Traditional Religions and Christianity. Without using the term “inculturation”, Agbonkhianmeghe Orobator in the postscript to his Theology Brewed in an African Pot aptly captures the view that all theology is indeed inculturated thus:
Theology develops in context. Our encounter with God happens in time and space. Revelation, or God’s self-communication, is immersed in history. Our deep and probing questions about the meaning of human existence arise from our experiences. Relating to God, self, and others happens within a concrete space and a defined time. Detached from our human experience and context, theology comprehends little if anything at all of who we really are or who we are called to be as disciples of Jesus Christ.
When inculturation theology is adequately understood, the quest for the decolonisation of God or the decolonisation of Christianity does not arise.
I have so far explored the position of the early scholars who gave a positive evaluation of African traditional religious practices, and inculturation as emphasised by African Catholic theologians. I will now explore the discontinuity position.
Contrary to the position that the African traditional religious and cultural context is vital in the articulation of African Christian experience, the discontinuity position holds that the African pre-Christian religious and cultural context has nothing to do with Christian living and proclamation of the Gospel. Those who defend this position view Christianity and African Traditional Religions/cultures as opposing entities. This means that the acceptance of Christianity entails the rejection of African traditional religions and cultures. This position is mainly championed by Evangelicals who see the Bible as a compendium of answers to all human problems. Bediako (1999) identifies Byang Henry Kato, an evangelical theologian from Nigeria, as one of the principal defenders of the discontinuity thesis. Kato (1975) is very critical of African theologians and religious scholars like Idowu and Mbiti for their insistence on the relevance of the African religious and cultural context to the quest for authentic African Christian Identity. While Kato agrees that the search for African identity is vital considering Africa’s terrible background (transatlantic slave trade and colonialism), he insists that such a quest for identity should not “fail to appreciate the uniqueness of Christianity” (Kato 1975, p. 13).
In Kato’s view, to be an authentic Christian, an African must divest herself or himself of her or his African traditional religious and cultural heritage. Kato’s rejection of a positive appreciation of African Traditional Religions by African religious scholars and theologians is based on his conviction that such an enterprise is rooted in the belief in universalism, the doctrine that opines that, ultimately, all people “will be saved whether they believe in Christ now or not” (Kato 1975, p. 11). To drive home his point, Kato (1975, p. 14) asserts: “The new garb that African traditional religions are putting on promotes universalism. The respectability of these religions makes them appear to have equal standing with Christianity. They appear to give promise of a future life of happiness”. The inevitable questions that arise in view of Kato’s position are these: Is the appreciation of the positive element of African religious heritage and the inculturation of the Gospel of Christ in Africa a defence of universalism? Do the proponents of African theology undermine the uniqueness of Christianity? A critical approach to the questions would show that there is no correlation between inculturation and the doctrine of universalism. In addition, rather than undermining the uniqueness of Christianity, the goal of the proponents of African theology is to make the uniqueness of Christianity meaningful to Africans. Nonetheless, Kato would not agree with this position. In his view, any theology or expression of Christianity that deviates from Biblical Christianity is an implicit or explicit defence of universalism. In his critique of Mbiti’s theology Kato (1975, p. 57) writes:
But contradiction is not the worst problem of Mbiti’s theology. It is his universalism that poses a threat to Biblical Christianity in Africa. His great enthusiasm in “Africanizing” Christianity, while done in good faith, poses a threat to “the faith which was once for all delivered to the saints”.
(Jude 3)
Commenting on the irreconcilable dichotomy that Kato places between African traditional religious heritage and Christianity, Bediako (1999, pp. 389–90) asserts:
What Byang Kato’s understanding of the relationship between the African heritage in religion and the Christian faith amounted to, was that the two constituted quite distinct and discontinuous entities, different religious systems with little or no common ground between them. From Kato’s standpoint, therefore, there was no theological validity for the very basis on which the African theological enterprise was being constructed, namely, that the “perennial religions and spiritualities of Africa” were the chief realities with which the African Christian scholar needs in the first place, to come to terms, and interpret.
From the quotation, one can infer that Kato’s position is that of radical discontinuity between the African religious heritage and the Christian faith. Put differently, one could say that in Kato’s view, to be a Christian, one needs to completely divest oneself of one’s African traditional heritage and culture. It is doubtful if such a quest is attainable. There is no such thing as a de-contextualised Christian. To be a Christian, is to be a Christian in space and time. So contextual influences are unavoidable. To think of a “pure Christian” is at best utopic. At best, a radical discontinuity can only be an initial phase immediately after one’s conversion to Christianity when there is no clear distinction between the reality, God, the concept of God, and the conceptions of God. Put differently, radical discontinuity between African traditional religions and Christianity is a manifestation of the pre-critical stage in the life of an African Christian. The words of Orobator, a Nigerian Jesuit priest and theologian who is a convert from African traditional religion are instructive, especially since Kato (1975) claims that one of Mbiti’s limitations is “the fact that he was born and brought up in a Christian home”. Orobator writes:
There was a time when I was not a Christian. My faith journey divides into three distinct but overlapping phases. In the beginning, I was born into African Religion and later converted to Christianity. Christianity taught me a strong disdain for all things fetishist and animist, for that was how good Christians were catechized to perceive African Religion. The transition from African Religion to Christianity was a clean break—or at least such was the expectation—judging by the vehemence with which the catechism rejected any traditional religious practice and all those Africans who in their blindness persisted in following that way of life. Fortunately for me, a radical break with a past that was deemed cursed and diabolical never quite materialized. Over time, I have learned to adopt a critical yet respectful and appreciative distance vis-à-vis these two phases of my religious experience. This standpoint of critique, respect and appreciation constitutes a third distinct phase, and it is driven by a passionate quest to integrate, converge and harmonize seemingly disparate and conflictual claims and contestations among the religious traditions that dominate the African landscape.
Kato would claim that Orobator’s position is that of a liberal Christian and not that of a conservative evangelical Christian. However, without proper integration between different religious experiences, African Christians would be religious schizophrenics.
From the foregoing, it is reasonable to conclude that a radical discontinuity between African traditional religions and Christianity is unattainable. In so far as Africans are Christians, they must be African Christians. This presupposes that there are influences of African cultural heritage in their lives since the Gospel as proclaimed is incarnated in space and time.
Since I have argued that both continuity and discontinuity theses simpliciter between African traditional religions and the Christian faith are indefensible, a question that arises is this: is there any other position other than inculturation or incarnation of the Gospel in the African context? Verhoef (2021) proposes deconstruction in order to avoid the extremes of the proponents of the continuity and discontinuity theses. Although he advances his position while considering the possibility of decolonising the concept of the Trinity in Africa, mutatis mutandi, the position can be applied to the continuity and discontinuity between African traditional religions and Christianity. While advancing his preference for deconstruction rather than decolonisation, Verhoef (2021, p. 5) writes:
The motivation for this deconstruction of the concept of the Trinity is not only to allow for decolonisation but it is also motivated by the need for religious freedom, openness and tolerance. Furthermore, it wants to avoid the critique, which Conradie and Sakupapa’s ‘Trinity as decolonising’ may receive, namely that it is too similar to the Evangelical position of complete discontinuity with ATRs and the position where the concept of the Trinity remains the dominant one.
A question that becomes inevitable is, how does deconstruction enhance religious freedom, openness and tolerance? Verhoef would argue that deconstruction is a better approach because deconstruction is rooted in the acknowledgement of the limitation of language. In other words, there is no finality in the use of language, religious language inclusive, as “language is not a transparent medium that connects one directly with a ‘truth’ or ‘reality’ outside language, but that we remain in language as a structure or code” (Verhoef 2021, p. 6). In his view, the implication of advancing deconstruction rather than mere decolonisation in the continuity and discontinuity debate is that deconstruction eliminates rigidity and dogmatism in religious discourse. Such an approach, he argues, “promotes an openness and playfulness within religious discussion, without trying to reject religion’s effort to find hope, love and meaning in life” (Verhoef 2021, p. 7).
Does Verhoef’s deconstruction approach resolve the continuity and discontinuity debate between African traditional religions and Christianity? In my view, it does not resolve the issue, for at least two reasons. Firstly, since the foundation of deconstruction theory is the limitation of language, the limitation applies to the term “deconstruction” itself, and so it cannot have a final say in the debate. Besides, considering that every religious and theological discourse is based on analogy, the limitation of human language is acknowledged but that per se does not undermine the veracity of religious discourse. Secondly, an approach that champions “playfulness within religious discussion” does not necessarily enhance freedom, openness and religious tolerance. Adherents of religious belief would consider an emphasis on playfulness as undermining their religious belief and the source of meaning in their life. Put differently, the deconstruction approach, in my view, is self-defeating. If no term is apt enough to capture completely the reality or phenomenon that it refers to, because of the limitation of human language, it means that deconstruction itself also, both as a concept and term, cannot be exempted from the limitation of linguistic expression, and so cannot be the vehicle through which other terms and concepts can be “purified”. Secondly, if the essence of deconstructing the concept of the Trinity is to make Christianity more playful, then it could be claimed that this approach leads to a watering down of Christian religious experience and the fundamental role that revelation plays in religion. Besides, “finding life, hope and meaning in mundane, corporal and immanent level” is not contrary to finding life, hope and meaning in revealed truths.

4. Conclusions

In this paper, I have explored the contemporary interest in the philosophy of religion in Africa and the theological discourse about the possible relationship between African traditional religion(s) and Christianity. I pointed out that most contemporary philosophical and theological discourses are carried out within the decolonisation project. I argued that the clamour for the decolonisation of God and Christianity by philosophers and theologians is founded on conceptual convolution, that is, a lack of proper distinction between reality, thought, and language. Put differently, the quest for the decolonisation of God in Africa arises because scholars do not clearly distinguish between the person or phenomenon “God”, the concept of God, and the conceptions of God. Irrespective of the plurality of religious experiences, and the fact that conceptions of God differ from one religious tradition to another, God is one. The implication of this is that God cannot be decolonised. On the other hand, it does not make much sense to clamour for the decolonisation of the conceptions of God because there are various conceptions of God precisely because there are various religious experiences and traditions with different understandings of revelation. Christianity, for instance, cannot be decolonised; rather, it can be and ought to be inculturated because the proclamation of the Gospel of Jesus Christ always entails encounter with a religious, cultural and social context. When the message of Christ is announced, there is an incarnation of the Gospel and the Christian faith.
Furthermore, I have engaged with the contemporary quest for an affirmation of a limited and material God rather than a perfect and immaterial God. I argued that both theses are philosophically incoherent and arise from a descriptive rather than an explanatory approach. The proponents of a limited God move from an analysis of religious texts from some African religious traditions and analysis of African languages to an affirmation that God is limited because of the presence of evil in the world (Bewaji 1998; Fayemi 2012) or a rejection of the doctrine of creatio ex nihilo (Wiredu 1998). I contended that the presence of evil in the world does not warrant the affirmation of a limited God. Regarding Wiredu’s position, I argued that the doctrine of creatio ex nihilo is more philosophically illuminating than to claim that God created out of pre-existing materials. Regarding the possibility of a material God as proposed by Attoe, I argued that this conclusion is based on an incorrect understanding of materiality and that a material God is at best a contradiction in terms.

Funding

This research received no external funding.

Institutional Review Board Statement

Not applicable.

Informed Consent Statement

Not applicable.

Data Availability Statement

No new data were created or analyzed in this study. Data sharing is not applicable to this article.

Conflicts of Interest

The author declares no conflict of interest.

Note

1
For a detailed account of the three levels of consciousness according to Bernard Lonergan, see chapters nine and eleven of his work Insight, and also chapter one of Method in Theology.

References

  1. Agada, Ada. 2022a. Bewaji and Fayemi on God, Omnipotence and Evil. Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions 11: 41–56. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  2. Agada, Ada. 2022b. Rethinking the Concept of God and the Problem of Evil from the Perspective of African Thought. Religious Studies 59: 1–17. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  3. Aleke, Patrick O. 2023. God and suffering in Africa. An exploration in natural theology and philosophy of religion. South African Journal of Philosophy 42: 348–60. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  4. Aquinas, Thomas. 1963. Summa Theologiae. London: Eyre & Spottiswoode. [Google Scholar]
  5. Aristotle. 1998. Metaphysics. Translated by Hugh Lawson-Tancred. London and New York: Penguins Books. [Google Scholar]
  6. Attoe, Aribiah. 2022. Groundwork for a New Kind of African Metaphysics. The Idea of Predeterministic Historicity. Berlin: Springer Nature. [Google Scholar]
  7. Bediako, Kwame. 1999. Theology and Identity. The Impact of Culture upon Christian Thought in the Second Century and in Modern Africa. Oxford: Regnum Books. [Google Scholar]
  8. Bewaji, John Ayorunde Isola. 1998. Olodumare: God in Yoruba Belief and the Theistic Problem of Evil. African Philosophical Quarterly 2: 1–17. [Google Scholar]
  9. Bujo, Bénézet. 2003. Foundations of an African Ethic: Beyond the Universal Claims of the Western Morality. Nairobi: Paulines Publications Africa. [Google Scholar]
  10. Bujo, Bénézet, and Juvénal I. Muya, eds. 2006. African Theology. The Contribution of the Pioneers. Nairobi: Pauline Publications Africa, vol. 2. [Google Scholar]
  11. Cogan, Paul, and William Craig. 2004. Creation Out of Nothing: A Biblical, Philosophical and Scientific Explanations. Grand Rapids: Baker Academic. [Google Scholar]
  12. Cordeiro-Rodrigues, Luís, and Ada Agada. 2022. African Philosophy of Religion: Concepts of God, Ancestors, and the Problem of Evil. Philosophy Compass 17: e12864. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  13. Fayemi, Ademola K. 2012. Philosophical Problem of Evil: Response to E. O. Oduwole. Philosophia 41: 1–15. [Google Scholar]
  14. Flew, Antony. 1976. The Presumption of Atheism and Other Essays. New York: Barnes & Nobles. [Google Scholar]
  15. Gyekye, Kwame. 1998. The Problem of Evil: An Akan Perspective. In African Philosophy: An Anthology. Edited by Emmanuel Chukwudi Eze. Malden and Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, pp. 468–71. [Google Scholar]
  16. Idowu, E. Bolaji. 1973. African Traditional Religion: A Definition. London: SCM Press Ltd. [Google Scholar]
  17. Kagabo, Liboire. 2006. Alexis Kagame: The Trail of an African Theology. In African Theology. The Contribution of the Pioneers. Edited by Bénézet Bujo and Juvénal Ilunga Muya. Nairobi: Pauline Publications Africa, vol. 2. [Google Scholar]
  18. Kant, Immanuel. 1999. Critique of Pure Reason. Translated and Edited by Paul Guyer, and Allen W. Wood. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  19. Kasper, Walter. 1983. The God of Jesus Christ. London: SCM Press. [Google Scholar]
  20. Kato, Byang H. 1975. Theological Pitfalls in Africa. Kisumu: Evangel Publishing House. [Google Scholar]
  21. Lonergan, Bernard. 1971. Method in Theology. London: Darton, Longman & Todd. [Google Scholar]
  22. Lonergan, Bernard J. F. 1992. Insight: A Study of Human Understanding. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. [Google Scholar]
  23. Magesa, Laurenti. 1998. African Religion: The Moral Traditions of Abundant Life. Nairobi: Pauline Publications Africa. [Google Scholar]
  24. Magesa, Laurenti. 2004. Anatomy of Inculturation: Transforming the Church in Africa. Nairobi: Paulines Publications Africa. [Google Scholar]
  25. Majeed, Hasskei. 2022. Evil, Death and Some African Conception of God. Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions 11: 53–69. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  26. Mbiti, John. 1969. African Religions and Philosophy. London, Ibadan and Nairobi: Heinemann. [Google Scholar]
  27. Mbiti, John. 1975. Concepts of God in Africa. London: S.P.C.K. [Google Scholar]
  28. Mokoena, Lerato L. 2022. The Ontological Status of Yahweh and the Existence of the Thing we call God. Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions 11: 141–50. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  29. Mosima, Pius. 2022. African Approaches to God, Death and the Problem of Evil: Some Anthropological lessons towards an Intercultural Philosophy of Religion. Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions 11: 151–65. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  30. Nyamiti, Charles. 1984. Christ as Our Ancestor: Christology from an African Perspective. Gweru: Mambo Press. [Google Scholar]
  31. Orobator, Agbonkhianmeghe E. 2009. Theology Brewed in an African Pot. Nairobi: Pauline Publications Africa. [Google Scholar]
  32. Orobator, Agbonkhianmeghe E. 2018. Religion and Faith in Africa: Confessions of an Animist. Maryknoll and New York: Orbis Books. [Google Scholar]
  33. p’Bitek, Okot. 1970. African Religions in Western Scholarship. Nairobi: Kenya Literature Bureau. [Google Scholar]
  34. Sakupapa, Teddy C. 2019. Decolonising Content of African Theology and the Decolonisation of African Theology: Reflections on a Decolonial future for African Theology. Missionalia 46: 406–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  35. Verhoef, Anné. 2021. Decolonising the concept of the Trinity to decolonise the religious education curriculum. HTS Teologiese Studies/Theological Studies 77: a6313. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  36. Wiredu, Kwasi. 1998. Toward Decolonising African Philosophy and Religion. African Studies Quarterly 1: 17–46. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Aleke, P.O. God, Philosophers and Theologians in Africa. Religions 2024, 15, 739. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15060739

AMA Style

Aleke PO. God, Philosophers and Theologians in Africa. Religions. 2024; 15(6):739. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15060739

Chicago/Turabian Style

Aleke, Patrick O. 2024. "God, Philosophers and Theologians in Africa" Religions 15, no. 6: 739. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15060739

APA Style

Aleke, P. O. (2024). God, Philosophers and Theologians in Africa. Religions, 15(6), 739. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15060739

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop