Philosophical Reflection on Beauty in the Late Middle Ages: The Case of Jean Gerson
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. The Pulchrum as Transcendental
“Let us observe that the beauty of a painting or picture refers to the tablet itself which, for that reason, is called ‘beautiful.’ Let us add, moreover, that beauty refers above all to the model if the image or copy is entirely in conformity with its model, even if the model is very ugly. Thus, for example, we say that the image of a jester, an owl or a bat is beautiful. That is why people say that the jester has been beautifully painted.”4
“Natural beauty can be described as numerical equality born and resulting from unity, truth, and goodness; or from measure, number, and weight; or from mode, species, and order. Thus, the properties of being are unity, truth, and goodness, so that being and truth, being and goodness are interchangeable. It is not possible to be any being to which these three [proprieties] do not suit. [Such properties] are not distinguished in reality but only in the meaning of signification. This also what happens with mode, species, and order; and with measure, number, and weight.”6
“Creatures are the effect of the creative Trinity by a threefold kind of causality: efficient causality, from which creatures receive unity, mode and measure; exemplary causality, from which creatures receive truth, species and number; final causality, from which creatures receive goodness, order and weight.”7
3. The Classification of Beauty
“Since there are substantial and accidental forms, in addition to uncreated beauty there is a double beauty, that is, an essential and an accidental one. Likewise, each of these beauties is double, because essential beauty is either spiritual (as the soul is animal beauty, or intellectual [beauty], as the beauty of the angel) or corporeal (as nature or natural form is the beauty of matter). Similarly, the accidental form is either spiritual (as science, grace and virtues are the beauty of the soul and ignorance or sins are its deformities) or it is corporeal.”15
- Uncreated beauty;
- Created beauty;
- Essential (i.e., substantial) beauty;
- Spiritual essential beauty;
- Animal spiritual essential beauty;
- Intellectual spiritual essential beauty;
- Corporeal essential beauty;
- Accidental beauty;
- Spiritual accidental beauty;
- Corporeal accidental beauty;
“Beauty, which is a numerical equality, is divided, according to its first division, into a natural and an artificial beauty. Natural beauty is manifold, for there is an intellectual, a rational and an animal beauty. Moreover, there is one, which is only vital, another one, which is only substantial, and another one, which is only accidental. Finally, artificial beauty is introduced by the art of reason into natural beauty, and it is either per se or accidental.”17
- Uncreated beauty;
- Created beauty;
- Natural beauty;
- Natural intellectual beauty;
- Natural rational beauty;
- Natural animal beauty;
- Natural vital beauty;
- Natural substantial beauty;
- Natural accidental beauty;
- Artificial beauty;
- Per se artificial beauty;
- Accidental artificial beauty;
“[i] There is the intellectual being, and this exists in two ways: either it exists by itself, or it is connaturally united to another, like the human intellect. [ii] There is, furthermore, the rational being according to its two parts. [iii] There is, moreover, the animal being, and this in two ways: either it is united to reason, as is the case with human beings, or it exists by itself, as is the case with brutes. [iv] There is also the vital or vegetable being, and this in two ways: either with sense or without sense. [v] There is also the only substantial being, such as the elements or prime matter, which is nothing by way of principle since it is part of the substantial compound. Now, [matter] considered without its form, is not a formal act and is called ‘formless’ or ‘ugly,’ and it tends to form as something beautiful. [vi] Lastly, there is the analogous being which we call accident, to which it corresponds ‘being in another,’ but not ‘being,’ as the philosophers say; nevertheless, faith asserts that it can exist by itself without a subject of inherence.”18
“All writing of letters and names is contained, not potentially but actually, before the gaze of God who beholds such numbers, letters, and figures. A sign of this taken from an image can be applied to other cases: for example, the maker of a statue can form a very beautiful image by merely removing some parts of a log of wood which existed before the artist and to which he has added nothing.”20
4. Conclusions
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | “[…] corporis pulchritudo est partium congruentia cura quadam coloris suavitate” (Augustinus, De civitate Dei, XXII, 19, 2; Dombart and Kalb 1955, p. 838, ll. 41–42). Somewhat later Augustin also talks of a “congruentia numerosa” (Augustinus, De civitate Dei, XXII, 24, 4; Dombart and Kalb 1955, p. 850, l. 135). |
2 | Albertus Magnus, Super de div. nom., c. 4; (Simon 1972, p. 182, l. 39). |
3 | “[…] pulcrum proprie ex specie dici sive forma” (Alexander de Hales, Summa theologica, inq. 1, tr. 2, q. 3, c. 2; De Hales 1924–1948, vol. 2, p. 100, §76). |
4 | “Notemus ultra quod pulchritudo picturae vel imaginis refertur ad ipsam tabulam, quae proinde pulchra nominatur. Addamus praeterea quod pulchritudo maxime refertur ad exemplar si per omnia conformis est imago vel exemplatum suo exemplari, sit licet exemplar illud turpissimum; sic dicimus buffonis imaginem inde pulchram, sic bubonis et vespertilionis; ecce inquiunt buffonem pulchre pictum” (Gerson 1971, p. 199). These words recall Aristotle’s idea that art succeeds in pleasing even when it depicts the ugly (Poet., 1448b11–12). |
5 | See Alexander de Hales, Summa Theologica, inq. 1, tr. 2, q. 3, c. 1 (De Hales 1924–1948, vol. 2, p. 99, §75) and Costarelli Brandi (2020, p. 1399). |
6 | “Pulchritudo autem naturalis describi potest quod est aequalitas numerosa consurgens et resultans ex unitate, veritate, et bonitate; vel ex mensura numero et pondere, vel ex modo, specie et ordine. Itaque proprietates entis sunt unum et verum et bonum, sic quod ens et verum, ens et bonum convertuntur. Nec est possibile quod ens aliquod sit quin haec tria sibi conveniant, quae non re distinguuntur sed sola significandi ratione. Sic de modo, specie et ordine; sic de mensura, numero et pondere” (Gerson 1971, p. 205). |
7 | “[…] creatura est effectus Trinitatis creantis sub triplici genere causalitatis: efficientis, a quo est in creatura unitas, modus et mensura; exemplaris, a quo est in creatura veritas, species et numerus; finalis, a quo est in creatura bonitas, ordo et pondus” (Bonaventura, Breviloquium, II, 1, 2; Bonaventura 1883–1902, vol. 5, p. 219a). On the importance of this text for the understanding of beauty in Bonaventure, see Salvador-González (2021, p. 281; 2022, pp. 55–56). |
8 | “Pulchritudo igitur naturalis non habet aliquod ens positive contrarium quod sit positive turpitudo naturalis […]. Pulchrum similiter cum ente convertitur tamquam proprietas resultans ex tribus prioribus” (Gerson 1971, p. 205). Later, in this work, Gerson (1971, p. 214) insists again on the merely negative character of ugliness, which cannot cancel the natural beauty infused into the creatures by God. There are also other passages in his earlier works, neglected by Calma, in which Gerson includes pulchrum among the transcendentals, with a truly remarkable systematisation: “[…] ens et bonum et pulchrum convertuntur; propterea tantumdem habet quaelibet res, sit substantia, sit accidens, de bono et pulchro quantum de ente nec habere potest malum contrarium” (Jean Gerson, De passionibus animae; Gerson 1973, p. 6): this work was composed at 1408 or 1409 (Palémon Glorieux apud Gerson 1973, p. viii). “Conceptus simplex entis recipitur multipliciter in se et in passionibus suis primis quae sunt unum, verum, bonum, pulchrum; nedum in intellectualibus et rationalibus et cognitivis; sed suo modo generaliter in omnibus creaturis” (Jean Gerson, Centilogium de conceptis; Gerson 1973, p. 506): this work was composed at 1424 (Palémon Glorieux apud Gerson 1973, p. xv). |
9 | “[…] circulus triangulatus et triangulus circulatus” (Gerson 1971, p. 205). |
10 | “[…] pulchrum sicut et bonum convertitur cum ente” (Ulrich von Strassburg, De summo bono, II, tr. 3, c. 4; De Libera 1987, p. 57, l. 3). Although he did not take this text into account when he wrote his book on transcendentals, Aertsen (2006, p. 430) did mention it in his article on beauty. |
11 | Cf. Henricus de Gandavo, Summae Quaestionum ordinariarum, a. 1, q. 2 (Wilson 2005, pp. 66, 716–20); a. 48, q. 1 (Führer 2007, p. 35, 7–p. 36, 12); a. 14, q. 6 (Gandavo 1520, vol. 1, f. 142rQ). |
12 | “Itaque, secundum B. Dionysii commentatores, quemadmodum bonum et verum ac unum convertuntur cum ente, ita et pulchrum: ita quod omne ens est pulchrum, sicut omne ens dicitur bonum et verum ac unum” (Dionysius, De venustate mundi, c. 1; Dionysius 1907, p. 227a). |
13 | “Convertibilia entis, videlicet bonum, verum, pulchrum, reale nil superaddunt enti, sed solum aliquam rationis considerationem ac proprietatem” (Dionysius, De venustate mundi, c. 3; Dionysius 1907, p. 229a). |
14 | “Univocatio entis transcendentis ad Deum et creaturam cum suis propriis seu proprietatibus transcendentibus, quae sunt unum, verum, bonum, plurimum confert viris contemplativis et intelligentibus” (Jean Gerson, De modis significandi; Gerson 1973, p. 639). Here the term univocatio is under the influence of Scotus’ thought. However, due to Gerson’s severe view of Scotism (Hoenen 2003, pp. 343–44), it is accepted by him only with nuances (Bauer 1973, p. 382; Vial 2006, p. 135). Another passage from De modis significandi by Gerson (1973, p. 633) should also be considered. |
15 | “Cum autem sint formae substantiales et accidentales, praeter increatam pulchritudinem est duplex pulchritudo, scilicet essentialis et accidentalis. Et harum pulchritudinum utraque est duplex. Nam essentialis est spiritualis, ut anima est pulchritudo animalis, vel intellectualis, ut est pulchritudo angeli, vel est corporalis, ut natura sive forma naturalis est pulchritudo materiae. Similiter forma accidentalis vel est spiritualis, ut scientia et gratia et virtutes sunt pulchritudo animae et ignorantia vel peccata sunt eius deformitates, vel est corporalis” (Ulrich von Strassburg, De summo bono, II, tr. 3, c. 4; De Libera 1987, p. 56, ll. 63–70). |
16 | “[…] pulchritudo prima” (Gerson 1971, p. 202). The referral to divine beauty is central to Gerson’s approach, which, like all medieval, understands created beauty in referral to divine beauty (Pradier 2022). |
17 | “Pulchritudo quae est aequalitas numerosa, dividitur prima sui divisione quod quaedam est naturalis, quaedam artificialis. Naturalis multiplex est: quaedam intellectualis altera rationalis, dehinc animalis. Rursus aliqua est solum vitalis, altera solum substantialis, altera accidentalis. Artificialis vero quaedam est per se, quaedam per accidens per rationis industriam superinducta pulchritudine naturali” (Gerson 1971, p. 205). |
18 | “Invenitur autem ens intellectuale et hoc dupliciter: vel per se existens, vel ut alteri natum uniri, ut humanus intellectus. Invenitur rursus ens rationale secundum duplicem portionem. Invenitur praeterea ens animale, et hoc dupliciter; vel conjunctum rationi, ut in hominibus, vel per se stans, ut in brutis. Proinde invenitur ens vitale seu vegetabile, et hoc dupliciter: vel cum sensu vel sine sensu. Amplius est ens solum substantiale, ut elementa vel materia prima quae de se non est principaliter nihil, cum sit pars substantialis compositi; sed considerata sine forma non est actus formalis, et informis dicitur, aut turpis, appetens formam sicut aliquid pulchrum. Tandem est ens analogum, quod appellamus accidens, cujus est inesse non esse secundum philosophos, cum tamen ponat fides ea posse sine subjecto per se esse” (Gerson 1971, p. 206). |
19 | “[…] ars prima dedit et indidit tam hominibus quam ceteris animantibus artes innumeras unde prodeunt artificiales pulchritudines” (Gerson 1971, p. 212). This conception of art as a divine gift is reminiscent of Plato’s ideas on artistic inspiration (Tirado San Juan 2013, pp. 94–98). |
20 | Omnis insuper scriptura, litterarum et nominum, continetur nedum potentialiter sed actualiter in aspectu Dei videntis numeros hujusmodi, litteras et figuras. Cujus signum accipito de una imagine qualiter inferre licebit de ceteris. Potest itaque statuae factor per solam partium ablationem formare pulcherrimam imaginem ex uno trunco ligni qualis utique prius illic erat, cum nihil addiderit” (Gerson 1971, p. 213). |
References
- Aertsen, Jan A. 1996. Medieval Philosophy and the Transcendentals. The Case of Thomas Aquinas. Leiden, New York and Köln: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Aertsen, Jan A. 2006. The Triad “True-Good-Beautiful”. The Place of Beauty in the Middle Ages. In Intellect et Imagination dans la Philosophie Médiévale. Edited by Maria C. Pacheco and José Francisco Meirinhos. Turnhout: Brepols, vol. 1, pp. 415–35. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Assunto, Rosario. 1982. Die Theorie des Schönen im Mittelalter. Köln: DuMont. [Google Scholar]
- Bauer, Martin. 1973. Die Erkenntnislehre und der Conceptus entis nach vier Spätschriften des Johannes Gerson. Meisenheim am Glan: A. Hain. [Google Scholar]
- Bonaventura, Sanctus. 1883–1902. Opera omnia. Quaracchi: Collegium S. Bonaventurae. [Google Scholar]
- Brown, Jerome V. 1975. Intellect and Knowing in Henry of Ghent. Tijdschrift voor Filosofie 37: 490–512. [Google Scholar]
- Calma, Monica. 2007. Témoignage sur le beau comme propriété de l’être: Jean Gerson et Denys le Chartreux. Freiburger Zeitschrift für Philosophie und Theologie 54: 464–82. [Google Scholar]
- Costarelli Brandi, Hugo. 2020. La Summa Halensis: Tradición y renovación en torno al problema de la belleza. Pensamiento 76: 1389–407. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- De Bruyne, Edgar. 1955. Geschiedenis van de aesthetica. Antwerpen and Amsterdam: Standaard-Boekhandel. [Google Scholar]
- De Hales, Alexander. 1924–1948. Summa theologica. Quaracchi: Collegium S. Bonaventurae. [Google Scholar]
- De Libera, Alain. 1987. Ulrich von Strassburg. De summo bono. Liber II, Tractatus 1–4. Hamburg: Meiner. [Google Scholar]
- Dionysius, Cartusianus. 1907. Opera omnia. Tornaci: Cartusiae S. M. de Pratis, vol. 34. [Google Scholar]
- Dombart, Bernard, and Alphonse Kalb, eds. 1955. Sancti Aurelii Augustini De Civitate Dei. CCSL 48. Turnholti: Brepols. [Google Scholar]
- Eco, Umberto. 1987. Arte e Bellezza Nell’Estetica Medievale. Milano: Bompiani. [Google Scholar]
- Emery, Kent, Jr. 2003. Denys the Cartusian on the Cognition of Divine Attributes and the Principal Name of God: A propos the Unity of a Philosophical Experience. In Die Logik des Transzendentalen: Festschrift für Jan A. Aertsen zum 65. Geburtstag. Edited by Martin Pickavé. Berlin and New York: Walter de Gruyter, pp. 454–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Emery, Kent, Jr., ed. 1996. Fondements théoriques de la réception de la beauté sensible dans les écrits de Denys le Chartreux (1402–1471). In Monastic, Scholastic and Mystical Theologies from the Later Middle Ages. Aldershot: Variorum, pp. 307–24. [Google Scholar]
- Führer, Markus, ed. 2007. Henrici de Gandavo Quaestiones Ordinariae (Summa). art. XLVII–LII. Leuven: Leuven University Press. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gandavo, Henricus de. 1520. Summae Quaestionum Ordinariarum. Paris: I. Badius. [Google Scholar]
- Gerson, Jean. 1971. Œuvres Complètes. Paris: Desclée & Cie, vol. 8. [Google Scholar]
- Gerson, Jean. 1973. Œuvres Complètes. Paris: Desclée & Cie, vol. 9. [Google Scholar]
- Halcour, Dieter. 1959. Tractatus de transcendentalibus entis conditionibus (Assisi, Biblioteca Comunale, Codex 186). Franziskanische Studien 41: 41–106. [Google Scholar]
- Hoenen, Maarten J. F. M. 2003. Formalitates phantasticae. Bewertungen des Skotismus im Mittelalter. In Die Logik der Transzendentalen. Festschrift für Jan A. Aertsen zum 65. Geburtstag. Edited by Martin Pickavé. Berlin and Boston: Walter de Gruyter, pp. 337–57. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jacobsson, Martin, ed. 2017. Augustinus: De Musica. CSEL 102. Berlin and Boston: Walter de Gruyter. [Google Scholar]
- Maritain, Jacques. 1920. Art et Scolastique. Paris: Art catholique. [Google Scholar]
- Mazour-Matusevich, Yelena. 2006. Gerson’s Legacy. In A Companion to Jean Gerson. Edited by Brian Patrick McGuire. Leiden and Boston: Brill, pp. 357–99. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McGuire, Brian Patrick. 2006. In Search of Jean Gerson: Chronology of His Life and Works. In A Companion to Jean Gerson. Edited by Brian Patrick McGuire. Leiden and Boston: Brill, pp. 1–39. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Panofsky, Erwin. 1951. Gothic Architecture and Scholasticism. Latrobe: Archabbey. [Google Scholar]
- Pradier, Adrián. 2022. San Basilio frente al mar. La variante estética del argumento del diseño. Cauriensia 17: 403–30. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Salvador-González, José María. 2021. The first level of St. Bonaventure’s transcendent Aesthetics: Contemplating God as the pure, primary Being. Biblica et Patristica Thoruniensia 14: 273–85. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Salvador-González, José María. 2022. La estética de San Buenaventura y su Influencia en la Iconografía de los Siglos XIV–XV. Madrid: Sindéresis. [Google Scholar]
- Simon, Pulus, ed. 1972. Alberti Magni Super Dionysium de Divinibus Nominibus. Monasterii Westfalorum: Aschendorff. [Google Scholar]
- Stoelen, Anselme. 1954. Denys le Chartreux. In Dictionnaire de Spiritualité ascétique et Mystique, Doctrine et Histoire. Edited by Marcel Viller, Ferdinand Cavallera and Joseph de Guibert. Paris: Beauchesne, vol. 3, col. 430–49. [Google Scholar]
- Tatarkiewicz, Władysław. 1962. Estetyka średniowieczna. Warszawa: Ossolineum. [Google Scholar]
- Tirado San Juan, Víctor M. 2013. Teoría del Arte y Belleza en Platón y Aristóteles. La Idea de la Estética. Madrid: Ediciones San Dámaso. [Google Scholar]
- Torrijos-Castrillejo, David. 2020. San Alberto Magno y las bellas artes. De Medio Aevo 14: 117–29. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vasiliu, Anca. 1997. Du diaphane: Image, Milieu, Lumière dans la Pensée Antique et médiévale. Paris: Vrin. [Google Scholar]
- Vial, Marc. 2006. Jean Gerson: Théoricien de la théologie Mystique. Paris: Vrin. [Google Scholar]
- Wilson, Gordon A., ed. 2005. Henrici de Gandavo Quaestiones Ordinariae (Summa). art. I–V. Leuven: Leuven University Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Torrijos-Castrillejo, D. Philosophical Reflection on Beauty in the Late Middle Ages: The Case of Jean Gerson. Religions 2024, 15, 434. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15040434
Torrijos-Castrillejo D. Philosophical Reflection on Beauty in the Late Middle Ages: The Case of Jean Gerson. Religions. 2024; 15(4):434. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15040434
Chicago/Turabian StyleTorrijos-Castrillejo, David. 2024. "Philosophical Reflection on Beauty in the Late Middle Ages: The Case of Jean Gerson" Religions 15, no. 4: 434. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15040434
APA StyleTorrijos-Castrillejo, D. (2024). Philosophical Reflection on Beauty in the Late Middle Ages: The Case of Jean Gerson. Religions, 15(4), 434. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15040434