Pantheism, Omnisubjectivity, and the Feeling of Temporal Passage
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Assumptions
2.1. Fundamental Ontology and the Mental
2.2. God
If pantheism is the metaphysics of the divine on which God is identical with the totality of all existents and the only existents are constituents of the physical universe, then we get the following definition of “pantheism” that I am assuming.(OntNat) A theory T is ontologically naturalistic if and only if T does not countenance the existence of any entities that are not constituents of the universe.
This definition allows us to have a clear way of distinguishing pantheism from versions of panentheism.7Pantheism = df. God is identical with the totality of existents constitutive of the universe.
Any putative version of pantheism that rejects cosmopsychism and does not offer an alternative account of what sort of unity the universe would exhibit that is sufficient to describe it as divine is perhaps better described as panultimism (see Buckareff 2022b, pp. 19–22).(CU) For any system S, S exhibits cognitive unity if and only if (1) S can be described as a functionally integrated information processor; (2) the processing of information by S, for reasons of S, is directed at producing outputs that may be either an intentional state in S or some purposive behavior of S; (3) the various states of S at any time can be individuated by their functional role in S; and (4) at least some of the different states and processes of S qua system must be phenomenally conscious.
2.3. Time and Temporal Passage
Eternalist Ontological Thesis (EOT): Past, present, and future times and events exist.(ibid., p. 347)
While we experience temporal change, robust temporal passage is an illusion if we live in a block universe and eternalism is true. That temporal passage of some sort is real is not in question here. Tim Maudlin offers the following about temporal passage.Eternalist Semantic Thesis (EST): “Present” is an indexical like “here”, picking out the location of use.
What Maudlin identifies is a minimal commitment of all parties to the debates over temporal passage in the metaphysics of time.The passage of time is an intrinsic asymmetry in the temporal structure of the world, an asymmetry that has no spatial counterpart. It is the asymmetry that grounds the distinction between sequences which run from past to future and sequences which run from future to past.
For instance, as I type these words, I am standing at my desk in my home office. Less than one minute ago, I was sitting. The kind of change from sitting less than a minute ago to standing at the time I started typing would constitute anemic change. Nothing about anemic change requires that there be a metaphysically complete statement describing the totality state of affairs that is the universe that is true now but was false a minute ago.(AC) Something is changing if and only if (i) it is currently one way, and (ii) it was (not long ago) some other, incompatible way.
We have robust change when I go from sitting to standing if it is true that I am standing, and it is not just true relative to the time at which I am standing and false relative to the time at which I was seated. Rather, the state of affairs of my standing simply did not exist anywhen else when I was seated. A new, novel state of affairs came to be in the universe when I stood up. What is not present is not equally real, unlike what is not here where I am in space. Manhattan is still 100 km south of here, where I am typing. However, my being seated a few minutes ago is no longer real. The universe, if there were robust temporal change, would be full of novelty. With what was the case no longer having any being to speak of, and what will be the case not lying temporally ahead of us.(RC) Something is changing if and only if there is some metaphysically complete sentence S about it such that (i) S is true (absolutely), and (ii) S was (not long ago) false.(ibid., p. 26)
3. An Argument: Pantheism, Omnisubjectivity, and the Phenomenology of Temporal Passage
- God is omniscient
- If God is omniscient, then God knows what it is like for us to experience robust temporal passage
- If God knows what it is like to experience robust temporal passage, then God does not have a unified experience of the spatiotemporal continuum
- But, God does have a unified experience of the spatiotemporal continuum
- Therefore, God is not omniscient.
4. Personal Pantheism versus Non-Personal Pantheism
I will not worry about (ii) and (iii) here. I will only focus on (i) and how God as characterized by pantheism could satisfy (i). But, notice that to make good on whether a tenable version of personal pantheism can be offered will rest not only on satisfying (i) but also (ii) and (iii). However, given my concerns in this article, I will take for granted that if we have a pantheistic conception of God on which (i) is satisfied, that conception will also satisfy (ii) and (iii). An account and defense of how a pantheistic conception of God might satisfy (ii) and (iii) is a task I plan on taking up elsewhere.S is a person if and only if (i) S has the capacity for having a robust first-person perspective, (ii) S has the capacity to evaluate and respond to reasons (both theoretical and practical), and (iii) S has the capacity for exercising agency in pursuit of goals represented in plans.
5. How Personal Pantheism Preserves Omnisubjectivity
Qua holes in the divine, we are not ontologically other. The same stuff comprises the divine person and the persons that are subsystems in the divine mind. We are functional holes in the divine mind. Forrest has not developed the account. What follows is my own personal pantheist model of God inspired by Forrest’s remarks about the status of the “holes” in God that are conscious subsystems.I now hold that where there are two or more agents with prima facie power over a region, the one that has the greater unity [in that region] has the greater power in that region. This results in the paradoxical power of creatures, because we have great unity than God in the region of our brain-states represented to us as a body-image.(correspondence qtd. in Buckareff 2022b, p. 53)
Additionally, the directionality of powers (whether manifesting or not) can be viewed as the source of the information about how powers will manifest which is transmitted in causal processes (see Bauer 2022, p. 146ff; N. Williams 2019, p. 92ff).Physical information provides an opportunity for […] causal effects. Two billiard balls on a table represent a certain information state, with specifiable differences based on billiard ball location, mass, and so on. These information states with their attendant differences partially generate the possibility of one billiard ball causing the other to move. So, physical information supports causal production. Turning to the connection between causation and powers, where and when powers are at work, causation occurs. In defense of this premise, causation arguably requires the manifestation of powers. If effects are the product of manifesting powers […], then causality depends on the action of powers. Where there is a causal effect, there is the manifestation of a power. Therefore, causation metaphysically links information and powers: where and when powers are at work, information transmission occurs.
We can now consider how this would work with respect to a region of spacetime that is a conscious hole in the divine.Weak Emergence: What it is for token feature S to be Weakly emergent from token feature P on a given occasion is for it to be the case, on that occasion, (i) that S cotemporally materially depends on P, and (ii) that S has a non-empty proper subset of the token powers had by P.
6. Objections
The relevant temporal intervals to which we may index the duration of any moment of the specious present can vary. What is important is that these experiences exhibit a unity that allows us to distinguish them one from the other. One way we may measure this (at least, in those whose capacity for visual perception is intact) is in terms of the length of time it takes for a visual signal to be transmitted from the retina to the primary visual cortex and result in an integrated visual experience. Experiments on non-human primates show that signal latencies from the retina to V5, the middle-temporal visual area of the visual cortex, are ~25–30 milliseconds, but the integration of neural activity in V5 takes ~50–125 milliseconds (Piper 2019, pp. 5–6). V5 realizes experiences of visual motion. The total time to integrate information involving feedforward and feedback signals from V5 to V1 (the primary visual cortex) on one model of apparent motion is ~235 milliseconds (ibid., p. 8). I cannot discuss the neurophysiology of the visual dimension of experiences of temporal passage in any detail here. However, suffice it to say that these data provide us with some parameters for what qualifies as a moment for my purposes.[T]he practically cognized present is no knife-edge, but a saddle-back, with a certain breadth of its own on which we sit perched, and from which we look in two directions into time. The unit of compositions of our perception of time is a duration, with a bow and a stern, as it were—a rearward- and a forward-looking end. It is only as parts of this duration-block that the relation of succession of one end to the other is perceived. We do not first feel one end and then feel the other after it, and from the perception of the succession infer an interval of time between, but we seem to feel the interval of time as a whole, with its two ends embedded in it. The experience is from the outset a synthetic datum, not a simple one; and to sensible perception its elements are inseparable, although attention looking back may easily decompose the experience, and distinguish its beginning from its end.
7. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | See (Zagzebski 2008) for a defense of this assumption. |
2 | For a defense of properties as immanent/in rebus universals, see (Armstrong 1978, 1989, 1997). Representative trope-theoretic accounts are offered in (Campbell 1981, 1990; Heil 2003, 2012; Martin 2007; Molnar 2003; D. Williams 1953). There are important differences between Campbell and Williams, on the one hand, and Heil, Martin, and Molnar, on the other. Specifically, Campbell and Williams assume a one-category ontology with objects being bundles of tropes. Heil, Martin, and Molnar include irreducible objects in their ontologies, with tropes as modes or ways objects are. Given the two-category ontology being assumed in this paper, if I were to assume trope-theory, the view endorsed would be closer to the views of Heil, Martin, and Molnar. |
3 | For defenses of this view, see (Heil 2003, 2012; Ingthorsson 2013; Jacobs 2011; Martin 2007; Mumford 1998; N. Williams 2019). |
4 | For more on the relation between powers and disposition-ascriptions, see (Buckareff 2022a). |
5 | For more on this sort of view of powers in causal processes, see (Buckareff 2017; Chakravartty 2005; Corry 2019; Heil 2012; Marmodoro 2017; Molnar 2003; Mumford and Anjum 2011). |
6 | Martin and Pfeifer (1986) argue that many standard accounts of intentionality fail to distinguish intentional mental properties from allegedly non-intentional dispositional physical properties. See also (Borghini 2009; Heil 2003, 2012, 2016; Martin 2007; Molnar 2003, chp. 3; Place 1996). |
7 | See (Buckareff 2022b) for discussion of pantheism and how to distinguish it from other accounts of God and God’s relationship to the universe, such as panentheism and theistic internalism. |
8 | Skow has the following schemas as numbered. I have changed them to the initials for “anemic change” and “robust change”. |
9 | See (Forrest 2016b; Jantzen 1978, 1984; Lancaster-Thomas 2020). While they do not label their versions of pantheism as versions of personal pantheism, I take (Bauer 2019; Pfeifer 2016) to also be presenting what is best described as personal pantheist conceptions of God. |
10 | Forrest (2004) rejects eternalism, having defended a very unique version of a growing block metaphysic of time. However, I am not asserting that any theory of time is correct here. Rather, I am solely interested in whether any version of pantheism can preserve omnisubjectivity IF eternalism is true. So I am not concerned about whether Forrest would approve of the line of inquiry taken up in this article. Where I expect he will part company with me is with respect to how I fill in the account. |
11 | The model of conscious processing of information I find most tenable is one that is delivered by combining integrated information theory with a metaphysics of properties as powerful qualities. See (Tononi and Koch 2015; Owen 2019). |
12 | This objection was raised by Gorazd Andrejč. |
References
- Armstrong, David. 1978. A Theory of Universals. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Armstrong, David. 1989. Universals: An Opinionated Introduction. Boulder: Westview Press. [Google Scholar]
- Armstrong, David. 1997. A World of States of Affairs. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Baker, Lynne Rudder. 2013. Naturalism and The First-Person Perspective. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bauer, William. 2019. Powers and the pantheistic problem of unity. Sophia 58: 563–80. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bauer, William. 2022. Causal Powers and the Intentionality Continuum. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Borghini, Andrea. 2009. Dispositions and their intentions. In Debating Dispositions: Issues in Metaphysics, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Mind. Edited by Gregor Damschen, Robert Schnepf and Karsten Stüber. Berlin: DeGruyter, pp. 204–19. [Google Scholar]
- Buckareff, Andrei A. 2012. Omniscience, the incarnation, and knowledge de se. European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 4: 59–71. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Buckareff, Andrei A. 2017. A Critique of Substance Causation. Philosophia 45: 1019–26. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Buckareff, Andrei A. 2018. Theistic consubstantialism and omniscience. Religious Studies: An International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion 54: 233–45. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Buckareff, Andrei A. 2019. Unity, ontology, and the divine mind. International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion 85: 319–33. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Buckareff, Andrei A. 2022a. Disentangling dispositions from powers. Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review 61: 107–21. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Buckareff, Andrei A. 2022b. Pantheism. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Campbell, Keith. 1981. The metaphysic of abstract particulars. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 6: 477–88. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Campbell, Keith. 1990. Abstract Particulars. Malden: Basil Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Chakravartty, Anjan. 2005. Causal realism: Events and processes. Erkenntnis 63: 7–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Corry, Richard. 2019. Power and Influence: The Metaphysics of Reductive Explanation. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Forrest, Peter. 2004. The real but dead past: A reply to Braddon-Mitchell. Analysis 64: 358–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Forrest, Peter. 2007. Developmental Theism: From Pure Will to Unbounded Love. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Forrest, Peter. 2016a. Pantheism. Roczniki Filozoficzne 64: 67–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Forrest, Peter. 2016b. The personal pantheistic conception of God. In Alternative Concepts of God: Essays on the Metaphysics of the Divine. Edited by Andrei A. Buckareff and Yujin Nagasawa. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 21–40. [Google Scholar]
- Heil, John. 2003. From an Ontological Point of View. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Heil, John. 2012. The universe as We Find It. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Heil, John. 2016. Causal relations. In The Metaphysics of Relations. Edited by Anna Marmodoro and David Yates. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 127–37. [Google Scholar]
- Hewitt, Simon. 2019. God is not a person (an argument via pantheism). International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 85: 281–96. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Ingthorsson, Rognvaldur D. 2013. Properties: Qualities, powers, or both? Dialectica 67: 55–80. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jacobs, Jonathan. 2011. Powerful qualities, not pure powers. The Monist 94: 81–102. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- James, William. 1918. The Principles of Psychology. New York: Henry Holt and Company, vol. 1. [Google Scholar]
- Jantzen, Grace. 1978. On worshipping an embodied God. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8: 511–19. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jantzen, Grace. 1984. God’s World, God’s Body. Philadelphia: The Westminster Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lancaster-Thomas, Asha. 2020. The coherence of naturalistic personal pantheism. European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 12: 75–89. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Marmodoro, Anna. 2017. Aristotelian powers at work: Reciprocity without symmetry in causation. In Causal Powers. Edited by Jonathan Jacobs. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 57–76. [Google Scholar]
- Martin, Charles Burton. 2007. The Mind in Nature. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Martin, Charles Burton, and Karl Pfeifer. 1986. Intentionality and the non-psychological. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 46: 531–54. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Maudlin, Tim. 2007. The Metaphysics within Physics. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Miller, Kristie. 2013. Presentism, eternalism, and the growing block. In A Companion to the Philosophy of Time. Edited by Heather Dyke and Adrian Bardon. Malden: Wiley, pp. 345–64. [Google Scholar]
- Miller, Kristie. Forthcoming. Against passage illusionism. Ergo 9: 45.
- Molnar, George. 2003. Powers: A Study in Metaphysics. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mumford, Stephen. 1998. Dispositions. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mumford, Stephen, and Rani Anjum. 2011. Getting Causes from Powers. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Nagel, Thomas. 1974. What is it like to be a bat? The Philosophical Review 83: 435–50. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Owen, Matthew. 2019. Exploring common ground between integrated information theory and Aristotelian metaphysics. Journal of Consciousness Studies 26: 163–87. [Google Scholar]
- Place, Ullin T. 1996. Intentionality as a mark of the dispositional. Dialectica 50: 91–120. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Page, Ben. 2019. Wherein lies the debate? Concerning whether God is a person. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 85: 297–317. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Pfeifer, Karl. 2016. Pantheism as panpsychism. In Alternative Concepts of God: Essays on the Metaphysics of the Divine. Edited by Andrei A. Buckareff and Yujin Nagasawa. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 41–49. [Google Scholar]
- Piper, Matthew. 2019. Neurodynamics of time consciousness: An extentionalist explanation of apparent motion and the specious present via reentrant oscillatory multiplexing. Consciousness and Cognition 73: 1–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Skow, Brad. 2015. Objective Becoming. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Tononi, Giulio, and Christof Koch. 2015. Consciousness: Here, there, and everywhere? Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 370: 1–18. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Williams, Donald. 1953. On the elements of being. The Review of Metaphysics 7: 171–92. [Google Scholar]
- Williams, Donald, ed. 2018. The myth of passage. In The Elements and Patterns of Being: Essays in Metaphysics. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 159–72. [Google Scholar]
- Williams, Neil. 2019. The Powers Metaphysic. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wilson, Jessica. 2021. Metaphysical Emergence. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Zagzebski, Linda. 2008. Omnisubjectivity. Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion 1: 231–47. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Buckareff, A.A. Pantheism, Omnisubjectivity, and the Feeling of Temporal Passage. Religions 2023, 14, 758. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14060758
Buckareff AA. Pantheism, Omnisubjectivity, and the Feeling of Temporal Passage. Religions. 2023; 14(6):758. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14060758
Chicago/Turabian StyleBuckareff, Andrei A. 2023. "Pantheism, Omnisubjectivity, and the Feeling of Temporal Passage" Religions 14, no. 6: 758. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14060758
APA StyleBuckareff, A. A. (2023). Pantheism, Omnisubjectivity, and the Feeling of Temporal Passage. Religions, 14(6), 758. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14060758