Transcendental Happiness in the Thought of Ibn Sīnā and Ibn ‘Arabī
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Ibn Sīnā’s Exposition of Happiness
2.1. The Influence of Aristotle
On the topic of happiness in particular, Ibn Sīnā is affected by Aristotle’s (1999) Nicomachean Ethics, in which the philosopher begins by rejecting the idea that happiness is a state, as was commonly conceived. If that were the case, argues Aristotle, then a person could be asleep their whole lives, essentially living the same sort of life as a plant, and still be happy, which he does not accept (Aristotle, book 10, chp. 6, p. 162). If it is not a state, then happiness has to be an activity. Now, he continues, there are those activities that we perform in order to gain some other benefit, and then there are those that we do because they are good in themselves; happiness belongs to the latter category (Aristotle, book 10, chp. 6, p. 162). Aristotle then makes the claim that ‘this seems to be the character of actions in accord with virtue; for doing fine and excellent actions is choiceworthy for itself’ (Aristotle, book 10, chp. 6, p. 162). He acknowledges that performing actions that give physical pleasure also seem as though they are ‘choiceworthy in their own right’, but considers that this argument is erroneous since everyone thinks that ‘the things they honor are best’ (Aristotle, book 10, chp. 6, p. 162). Taking his cue from Aristotle, Ibn Sīnā would come to dismiss the commonly accepted primacy of physical pleasures over internal ones, and, especially, over intellectual pleasures, in the Ishārāt:Avicenna derived his conception of the history of philosophy from the late antique tradition of Alexandria, which presented Aristotle as the pinnacle of philosophy, perfecting all the tendencies previous to his time.
The pleasure of victory, which is in the domain of the internal senses, is, thus, privileged over the pleasures of food and sex, which are in the domain of the external senses.It is part of the delusions of common folk (awhām al-‘āmma) that pleasures (ladhdhāt) that are strong and obviously superior (musta‘liya) are [those that are] sensual (ḥissiyya), and the ones besides them are weak pleasures; these being things imagined (khayālāt) that have no reality (ghayr ḥaqīqa). … So it would be said to [someone like] him, ‘Is not the most pleasurable (aladhdh) of that which you describe from this perspective sex, or food, or things like them?’ But you know that someone who has the power (mutamakkin) to win something—even if it is insignificant (khasīs), like chess or backgammon—if food or [the possibility of] sex were put in front of him, would reject them due to the non-sensual pleasure of victory that they would get.1
Ibn Sīnā echoes this sentiment when he writes:to each type of person, the activity that accords with his own proper state is most choiceworthy; hence the activity in accord with virtue is most choiceworthy to the excellent person [and hence is most honorable and pleasant].(Aristotle, book 10, chp. 6, p. 162)
Since the virtue of modesty is ‘most choiceworthy to the excellent person’, it is more pleasurable, and the person then ‘withdraws his hand’ from food or sex in order to act in accordance with that virtue.Indeed, food and [the possibility of] sex could be presented before a person who is virtuous [but] … due to the presence of modesty, he withdraws his hand from them in order to observe modesty (ḥishma).
‘Complete happiness’, then, is found in the activity that is most in accordance with ‘the most divine element in us’, which, he tells us, is understanding. This means that the activity that leads to complete happiness is ‘the activity of study’. Accepting this premise, Ibn Sīnā explains that this is why the pleasures of the internal senses, such as victory, are preferred to those of the external senses, such as food and sex, and that the internal senses themselves are lower than the theoretical intellect that carries out ‘the activity of thinking’. Consequently, after proving that the internal senses trump the external ones, he asks, rhetorically, ‘So if the internal pleasures (al-ladhdhāt al-bāṭina) are greater than the external ones (al-ẓāhira), even though they are not intellectual (‘aqliyya), then what do you think about the intellectual [pleasures]?’ (Ibn Sīnā 1968, book 4, tenet 8, chp. 1, p. 9). Thus, Ibn Sīnā delineates a ‘pecking order’ when it comes to pleasures that is based on Aristotle’s works, with the exercise of contemplation resulting in the greatest happiness and the pleasures of the external senses constituting the least (McGinnis 2010, p. 218). In his Treatise on Happiness (Risāla fi’l-sa‘āda), Ibn Sīnā draws a direct equivalence between the pleasure and joy that a person experiences and the happiness that they feel (Ibn Sīnā n.d.b., pp. 259–80; Khademi 2014).If happiness is activity in accord with virtue, it is reasonable for it to accord with supreme virtue, which will be the virtue of the best thing. The best is understanding … and to understand what is fine and divine, by being itself either divine or the most divine element in us. Hence, complete happiness will be its activity in accord with its proper virtue, and we have said that this activity is the activity of study.(Aristotle, book 10, chp. 6, p. 163)
A thing can have two preparednesses (isti‘dādān), where one overtakes the other, but the thing to which something moves towards with its second preparedness (isti‘dād thānī) cannot be better than the relation it has to its essence (dhāt).
Since the proper perfection for the theoretical soul is the contemplation of the divine, this is what it (1) perceives as good, and, therefore, (2) seeks to attain. Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāzī (d. 606/1209), one of the most influential of the Ash’arite theologians (Griffel 2007), explains in his commentary of this work that:What is proper to each thing’s nature is supremely best and most pleasant for it, and hence, for a human being, the life in accord with understanding will be supremely best and most pleasant.(Aristotle, book 10, chp. 7, p. 165)
The things perceived by the senses (mudrikāt al-ḥawās) are only the particulars like colors, tastes, smells, hotness, and coldness, whereas the things that the intellect perceives are the essence of the Originator (Al-Bārī), the Exalted, His attributes (ṣifātih), and His actions. It is therefore known [from this perception] that there is no relation (nisba) between one and the other in terms of honor. So, if it is proven that … the things that the intellect perceives are more honorable than that which the senses perceive, then [it is known] … that intellectual pleasure (al-ladhdha al-‘aqliyya) is more perfect than sensual pleasure (al-ladhdha al-ḥissiyya).(Al-Rāzī n.d., vol. 2, p. 92)
Thus, the theoretical intellect becomes the locus in which the divine is represented. Ibn Sīnā is careful to attach the proviso that the ‘lucidity’ with which the divine is manifested in the theoretical intellect is commensurate with what is possible. This means that not only is there a hierarchy when it comes to the pleasures, with the intellectual pleasures being at the summit, there is also a hierarchy within the intellectual pleasures, in terms of the lucidity with which the divine is represented. The more lucid the representation of the divine, the greater the pleasure.The perfection of the intellectual substance (al-jawhar al-‘āqil) is such that the lucidity (jaliyya) of the First Truth (Al-Ḥaqq al-awwal) is represented (tatamaththal) in it, so far as it is possible for it to attain the splendor (bahā’) that is particular to it.
While there is no denying that Ibn Sīnā’s major influence in articulating union with the divine is the writings of Plotinus (see below), it would be a little hasty to attribute this notion entirely to Plotinus; even in the Nicomachean Ethics, we find the intimation of some kind of deep association with the divine when Aristotle says:We find that the Aristotelian notion of contemplation is transformed into the notion of union or being with the object. A human is no longer to seek knowledge as such; he is now to seek union or being with the object.
He may not go as far as to assert union with the divine, in the Plotinian sense, but the contemplation of the divine, says Aristotle, does imbue us with ‘pro-immortality’ and takes us beyond our mere humanity to something approaching divinity, which he claims brings us the greatest happiness. Nevertheless, as stated, Ibn Sīnā commits more fully to Plotinian emanationist cosmology.If understanding is something divine in comparison with a human being, so also will the life in accord with understanding be divine in comparison with human life. We ought not to follow the makers of the proverbs and ‘Think human, since you are human’, or ‘Think mortal, since you are mortal’. Rather, as far as we can, we ought to be pro-immortal and go to all lengths to live a life in accord with our supreme element.(Aristotle, book 10, chp. 7, pp. 164–65)
2.2. The Influence of Plotinus
Yet it may be argued that he was unique only in the manner in which he synthesized these myriad trends, for his predecessor, Abū Yūsuf al-Kindī (d. 259/873?), had synthesized Aristotelianism, Neoplatonism, Islamic theology, and Islamic tenets in his own way and to serve his own ends (Al-Kindī 1948; Adamson 2016, pp. 26–32). Ibn Sīnā was, thus, operating in a tradition that was inaugurated by al-Kindī, but he made a highly original contribution to that tradition through his unique mode of synthesis.[…] is unique in comparison to the theology and philosophy that came before him, since he synthesized in a comprehensive fashion Aristotelianism, Islamic theology, and Islamic tenets into his metaphysical scheme.
The Necessary Being is, thus, He Himself for Himself, the greatest Lover and the greatest Beloved, the One who enjoys the greatest bliss and is the greatest object of bliss. His love for his essence is, therefore, the most perfect and the most faithful.
God is the noblest (al-ashraf), says Ibn Sīnā, and existence began with Him and descended to the less noble intellects, which are also not sensible, until it ended up in matter, which is the basest point. As one would expect, he provides more detail about this in the Ilāhiyyāt:Think about how existence (wujūd) began, from the noblest (al-ashraf) to what is noble, until it ended up in matter. Then, it returned from what is basest (al-akhass) to the less base, then to what is nobler to what is noblest, until it reached the rational soul (al-nafs al-nāṭiqa) and the acquired intellect (al-‘aql al-mustafād).
The resultant existents seek to return to the perfection whence they came, which is why, according to Ibn Sīnā, ‘the fundamental principle is that everything that exists desires its perfection; some sort of an ontological love’, as Louis Gardet observes (El-Bizri 2001, pp. 762–63). It is, thus, their ontological love for and need to meet God—the source of perfection—that drives their ascent upward in order to attain transcendental happiness. Thus, ontological love is the force behind the upward creational motion toward God that imbues us with transcendental happiness.Since existence begins from the One, every proceeding existent being from Him is of a lower level (adwan martaba) than the first, and the ranks continue to fall. The first of these is purely spiritual angels (al-malā’ika al-rūḥāniyya al-mujarrada) that are called ‘intellects’ (‘uqūl). Then come the levels of the spiritual angels called the ‘souls’ (nufūs) … then the levels of the heavenly bodies. … Then, after these, begins the existence of matter (al-mādda).
Due to the fact that everything comes from Him by means of the emanative process, it seeks a return to Him, its divine source, and this return constitutes absolute transcendental happiness. Ibn Sīnā precludes intentionality as the impetus for the emanative process when he says:It is proven for us, through that which we have adduced, that the Necessary Existent (Wājib al-wujūd) in itself is one, and that He is not a body (laysa bi-jism), nor in a body (fī jism), and that He cannot be divided in any way. The existence of all existent beings (mawjūdāt), thus, comes from Him.
It is not possible that there is, for Him, a principle (mabda’) in any way, nor a cause (sabab), not in that which comes from Him, and not in that in which something comes to exist in it or by it, or because of it. It is due to this that it is not possible for the being of everything (kawn al-kull) to come from Him through an intention (qaṣd), like our intention for creating everything, and for the existence of everything because, in that case, He would be intending [this] for the sake of something other than Him.
The levels of existence are the corollaries of this self-love, which are numerous before they enter our sensible world in Ibn Sīnā’s ontology. Ibn Sīnā explains that the first product of the emanation from God cannot be sensible and must, therefore, be immaterial:His essence (dhāt) knows that His perfection (kamāl) and His exaltedness (‘uluww) are such that from them emanate goodness, and that this is one of the requisites (lawāzim) of His majesty (jalāl) that the object of love is in itself.
The first of the existent beings (mawjūdāt) that comes from the First Cause (Al-‘Illa al-ūlā) is one, and its essence (dhāt) and quiddity (māhiyya) is one, but its matter (mādda) is not. So nothing of [sensible] bodies (ajsām)—or the forms, which are the perfections of the bodies—is a proximate effect (ma‘lūl qarīb) of God. The first effect (al-ma‘lūl al-awwal) is a pure intellect (‘aql maḥḍ) because it is a form (ṣūra), and it does not have matter.
The essence and quiddity of the first existent to proceed from God, reasons Ibn Sīnā, is immaterial because God, the First Cause of the universe, is a pure intellect and is thus entirely free from matter. Through careful argumentation, Ibn Sīnā proves that if matter were to proceed from God and if it were the first product of the emanative process, this would mean that matter is the cause of further products of emanation, but this cannot be the case since it is only a recipient of emanation and not the cause of it (Ibn Sīnā 1998, book 9, chp. 4, pp. 404–5). This means that ‘it is necessary (wājib) for the first effect [of emanation] to be in a form that is not material (ṣūra ghayr māddiyya): in fact, it is an intellect’ (‘aql) (Ibn Sīnā 1998, book 9, chp. 4, p. 405).The distinction between ‘quiddity’ and ‘existence’ is undoubtedly one of the most basic philosophical theses in Islamic thought. Without exaggeration, the distinction may be said to constitute the first step in ontologico-metaphysical thinking among Muslims.
The three things in existence comprise the celestial intellect (the result of the intellect thinking about God as the cause of its coming into being), the celestial soul (the product of its thinking about its necessity, inasmuch as it is the necessary corollary of God’s thought), and the celestial body (the outcome of its thinking of its intrinsic possibility (imkān)) (Inati 1995, p. 14). These, then, are the intellectual, the spiritual, and the celestial levels of existence, which Ibn Sīnā delineates more concisely in the Ishārāt (Ibn Sīnā 1998, book 10, chp. 1, p. 435). He dubs the first level the ‘purely spiritual angels’ (al-malā’ika al-rūḥāniyya al-mujarrada), which corresponds to Ibn ‘Arabī’s ‘angelic world of determinations’ (Corbin 1997, p. 225). Ibn Sīnā calls the second level the rank of the souls, which correlates with Ibn ‘Arabī’s ‘determinations of the souls’ (ta‘ayyunāt rūḥiyya) (Corbin 1997, p. 225); the third level he calls the ranks of the heavenly bodies, which Ibn ‘Arabī dubs the ‘world of the Idea-Images’ (‘ālam al-mithāl) (Corbin 1997, p. 225). These levels would come to be formalized by his followers as the divine presences (ḥaḍarāt) (Chittick 1982).There is, under every intellect, a celestial sphere—with its matter (mādda) and form (ṣūra)—which is its soul (nafs), and an intellect under it. This means that, under every intellect, there are three things in existence.
This rounds off the levels of existence, according to both scholars. However, because it is so many emanations or differentiations away from the level of divinity, this material realm is the least perfect of the levels of existence, according to both thinkers. Ibn ‘Arabī agrees with Ibn Sīnā that the physical world is the least perfect of all the levels of existence, not only because it is furthest removed from the divine Essence, in the same way as the lower intellects are further removed from the First Cause than the higher ones and the physical world is the product of the most remote intellect from God, but also because the sensible world is dependent on the pre-sensible world, in the same way that lower intellects are dependent on those intellects that are above them. Ibn Sīnā explains that:There is always the necessary [emanation of] an intellect after every intellect until the sphere of the moon (kurrat al-qamar) comes into existence, and then the elements come into existence.
[…] every intellect is higher in level (martaba) [to others] because of a ‘meaning’ (ma‘nā) that it has, which is that because it thinks about the First [Cause], there is necessarily the existence of an intellect under it, and because it thinks about its own essence, there is necessarily a celestial sphere (falak) from it, with its own soul and body (jirm).
2.3. Transcendental Happiness as Union with the Divine
There are many points worthy of note in this passage. First, Ibn Sīnā mentions that God should not be an intermediary but the absolute purpose, and that supreme transcendental happiness only lies in this. Ibn Sīnā then defines what he means by this kind of happiness and says that it is ‘the pleasure of magnificence in Him’. He, therefore, seems to articulate that it can only be union with the divine that can afford a person supreme transcendental happiness. He follows this up by stating that those who make God an intermediary do not ‘seek this attachment’ with God; again, he is intimating that it is an absolute attachment to God that yields transcendental happiness. Furthermore, he chastises those who do not have this conception of pleasure and happiness, describing their view as ‘deficient’ (mukhdaja). It is significant that the term he uses denotes ‘the young one of a camel brought forth imperfectly formed, even if the period of gestation have [sic] been completed’ (Lane 2003, vol. 2, p. 707). What Ibn Sīnā insinuates is that despite having had the same length of time as the philosophers to know what transcendental happiness is, those who do not realize that it is found in union with the divine have an incomplete or deficient understanding of it. This is why they ‘yearn for’ their own deficient conception of happiness and do not seek ‘what is beyond it’.The one who deems it permissible to make God an intermediary is the recipient of mercy (marḥūm) only from a certain perspective (min wajh) because he is not nourished with (yuṭ‘am) the pleasure of magnificence in Him (ladhdhat al-bahja bih), so he can seek this attachment (yata‘ṭafah). His knowledge of pleasure is deficient (mukhdaja), so he yearns for it (ḥanūn ilayh), oblivious to what is beyond it.
After perfecting his spiritual exercises, says Ibn Sīnā, the knower can achieve ‘attainment’ of the divine, whereby his essence becomes a polished mirror in which is reflected the divine. Therefore, he rejoices because the traces of the divine are present in it/them. The pronoun can refer to two things here: either it refers to what flows copiously on him from the exalted pleasures or, as is more fitting, it refers to his soul (nafs). It would, therefore, mean that the traces of the divine are present in the soul of the knower, due to his union with it. Indeed, this is how al-Ṭūsī seems to understand it, writing in his commentary:If he crosses over from spiritual exercise (riyāḍa) to attainment (nayl), his essence [lit. his secret, sirruh] becomes a polished mirror (mir’āt majluwwa), through which he faces the direction (shaṭr) of God, and the exalted pleasures (al-ladhdhāt al-‘alī) flow copiously on him (darrat ‘alayh). So he rejoices within himself due to the traces of God that are in it/them.
The knower (‘ārif), if he has perfected his spiritual exercises, and if he does not need them to arrive (wuṣūl) at what he seeks, which is his permanent conjunction (ittiṣāl) with God, his essence becomes void (khālī) of everything that is not God, like a polished mirror … so the traces of God are represented (yatamaththal) in it.
In this final stage of the knower’s progress, the soul no longer observes itself as being a separate entity from the divine; it observes only the divine and does not even realize that it is ‘bedecked’ with divinity, according to Ibn Sīnā. This represents absolute union with the divine, or complete arrival, which is when the soul experiences supreme transcendental happiness. Al-Ṭūsī draws an equivalence between this stage and the Sufi terms of ‘effacement’ (maḥw) and ‘annihilation’ (fanā’) in God (Ibn Sīnā 1968, book 4, tenet 9, chp. 17, p. 92) when there is absolute union with the divine, according to some Sufi writers (Massignon 1982). Al-Rāzī employs the same term of ‘annihilation’ (fanā’) to describe this stage, writing:[…] withdraws (yaghīb) from his soul, and observes (yalḥaẓ) only the side (jānib) of sacredness (quds). And if he observes his soul, it is only in the sense that he notices [the divine], not in the sense that his soul is bedecked with it. And, at this point, the arrival (wuṣūl) is complete.
According to al-Rāzī, at this stage, everything besides God vanishes, and the only existence that is left for the soul is its subsistence in the divine.It is the first of the stations of ‘absolute arrival’ (al-wuṣūl al-tāmm) to God, and it is the complete annihilation (fanā’) of everything besides God, and the complete subsistence in Him (baqā’ bih).
The perfection that is particular to (khāṣṣ bih) the rational soul is that it becomes an intellectual realm (‘ālam ‘aqliyy) wherein the form of everything (ṣūrat al-kull) is inscribed, as well as the arrangement (niẓām) of everything that is comprehended, and the good (khayr) that pours forth to everything. This starts with the basis of everything (mabda’ al-kull), then goes to the exalted, purely spiritual substances (al-jawāhir al-sharīfa al-muṭlaqa), then to the spiritual substances that are related to bodies in some way (al-muta‘alliqa naw‘ mā bi’l-abdān), then to elevated bodies (al-ajsām al-‘ulwiyya) with their formations and their faculties, then it carries on until it exhausts in itself the formation of all of existence (wujūd). So it turns into an intellectual realm that completely corresponds to the existing realm. It therefore bears witness to absolute excellence (al-ḥusn al-muṭlaq), absolute goodness (al-khayr al-muṭlaq), and the beauty of the absolutely existent Truth (Al-Ḥaqq al-muṭlaq) and is united with it (muttaḥida bih).
3. Ibn ‘Arabī’s Exposition of Happiness
3.1. The Influence of Aristotle
Alchemy is a term for knowledge that relates to [things] … that have the capacity for transformation (istiḥāla), I mean, to change the states (taghayyur al-aḥwāl) of one essence (al-‘ayn al-wāḥida).
‘Goldness’, then, is the full actualization of the potentiality that is present in the essence of all minerals, according to Ibn ‘Arabī; this is their ‘rank of perfection’, which they seek to attain. In the same way, humans seek to attain their own rank of perfection, in which lies their supreme transcendental happiness. However, much as humans face the obstacle of materiality that impedes their path to the perfection of universal intellection, according to Aristotle (Inati 1995, p. 13), minerals encounter similar obstacles because they are a ‘natural affair’ (amr ṭabī‘ī) (Ibn ‘Arabī n.d., vol. 2, p. 270). Ibn ‘Arabī gives examples of the effects of nature, from the ravages of time to the fluctuations of temperature and moisture, etc., which hamper their path to the full actualization of their potentiality of perfection (Ibn ‘Arabī n.d., vol. 2, p. 270). The analogy of alchemy and transcendental happiness, therefore, is an apt one.[…] all minerals (ma‘ādin) come from one base. This base seeks, in its essence (bi dhātih), to attain the rank of perfection (darajat al-kamāl), which is ‘goldness’ (dhahabiyya).
Ibn ‘Arabī explains that the potentiality of humans, as with minerals, is to achieve actuality, which is perfection. However, despite both humans and minerals seeking perfection, not all attain it. He has already mentioned the external impediment to this attainment in the case of minerals, when he spoke of the effects of nature. Likewise, for humans, the external impediments are those causes that prevent them from pursuing contemplation of the divine. Nevertheless, he adds another cause in this passage, which is what is found ‘in the essences themselves’. Whereas Aristotle attributes the desires of the body as a corollary of materiality that impedes full actualization, Ibn ‘Arabī effects a bifurcation in which parts of the essence are one of the obstacles to perfection and transcendental happiness, while the natural effects of the world represent the other. In the characteristic emphasis that he places on homonymy (Lala 2019, 2023a), he states that the ‘causes’ (‘ilal) that negatively affect the minerals during their stages of formation are the same as the ‘deficiencies’ (‘ilal) that afflict the essences of humankind. This, then, is their intrinsic preparedness (isti‘dād), which, in addition to the natural effects of the world, determines whether they can achieve the perfection of transcendental happiness (Lala 2023b).In the same way as the bodies of minerals (ajsād al-ma‘ādin) are [arranged] in levels (marātib) due to causes (‘ilal) that affect them while they are being created—even though they all seek the rank of perfection (darajat al-kamāl), on account of which their essences (a‘yān) are manifest—so, too, is humankind created for perfection. Thus, the only things that can turn it away from that (ṣaraf ‘an dhālik) are the deficiencies (‘ilal) and diseases (amrāḍ) that affect it, either in the essences themselves (aṣl dhawātihim), or because of accidental (‘araḍiy) causes.
Every person, therefore, has a preparedness that is divinely imbued. For Ibn ‘Arabī, as for Aristotle, the preparedness that each person possesses to achieve transcendental happiness is in their contemplation of the divine. Ibn ‘Arabī makes this clear when he writes:Know that souls, in terms of their essence, are made ready (muhayya’) to accept the preparedness (isti‘dād) that emanates for them from what the divine carries out (al-tawqī‘āt al-ilāhiyya). So, among them are those who just obtain the preparedness for carrying out sainthood (isti‘dād tawqī‘ al-wilāya) and do not go past that. And among them are those who are given the preparedness for all or some of the stations (maqāmāt) that we have mentioned.
Ibn ‘Arabī, as does Aristotle, asserts that the practical intellect of the rational soul has the function of managing the body. He argues that the only reason God appointed the rational soul as a vicegerent over the body was so that this would lead to the realization that there must be someone who gave the rational soul this power. The rational soul, thus, alerts the body that it has an Originator who gave it this power and that it is the raison d’être of humankind to seek knowledge of this divine Originator; it is only in this search that its transcendental happiness resides.God has given mastery (mallaka) to particular souls (al-nufūs al-juz’iyya) over conducting the affairs of (tadbīr) the body, and He has appointed them as vicegerents (istkhlaf) of them. He has, therefore, made it apparent to the bodies that they are their vicegerents, in order for them [i.e., the souls] to alert them (tatanabbah) [i.e., the bodies] to the fact that they have an Originator (Mūjid) who has appointed them as vicegerents, so it is their duty (yata‘ayyan ‘alayhā) to seek knowledge about He who appointed them [i.e., the souls] as vicegerents of them [i.e., the bodies].
The role of the prophet-legislator, therefore, is to make clear the path to transcendental happiness, which lies in the contemplation of the divine. Ibn ‘Arabī writes that the prophet-legislator ‘makes clear the path of knowledge (ṭarīqat al-‘ilm) that leads to Him, on which lies their happiness’ (Ibn ‘Arabī n.d., vol. 2, p. 273). This, argue Ibn Sīnā and Ibn ‘Arabī, is why the laws of the prophet-legislator are in conformity with the essential activity of the rational soul. However, not everyone will attain transcendental happiness. Revealing the rationale behind calling the chapter ‘The Alchemy of Happiness’, Ibn ‘Arabī writes:[…] prescribes laws that make apparent the path that allows one to attain the rank of perfection and happiness (darajat al-kamāl wa’l-sa‘āda), in keeping with what contemplation necessitates.
It is on account of there being no happiness except in it. Furthermore, there is nothing that people—from among the people of God (ahl Allāh)—have that is better than it. And it is that He gives you the rank of perfection (darajat al-kamāl) that behooves humankind to attain. This is due to the fact that not every person who is happy (ṣāḥib al-sa‘āda) is given perfection, so that all those who have perfection (ṣāḥib al-kamāl) are happy, and not all who are happy are perfect. Happiness is a term denoting the attainment of a lofty rank (darajat al-‘ulyā), which is imitation (tashabbuh) of the Cause.
Ibn Sīnā says that one requires theoretical and moral perfection in order to achieve supreme transcendental happiness without undergoing any suffering in the hereafter. Those who attain moral perfection, but who do not attain theoretical perfection because they were unaware of what the latter entailed, will only attain relative happiness in the second life (Inati 1996, p. 19). Ibn ‘Arabī, likewise, accords those who achieve moral perfection but who are not aware of the true reality of things a state of relative happiness, but they do not have the supreme transcendental happiness that is the preserve of the spiritual elite. These are the people who have attained the ‘lofty rank (darajat al-‘ulyā), which is imitation (tashabbuh) of the Cause’. It is in this aspect of imitating the Cause, or God, that Ibn ‘Arabī is most influenced by the writings of Plotinus.[…] eternal happiness or eternal suffering … are caused by theoretical perfection and theoretical imperfection, respectively. It is obvious, though, that not all theoretical imperfection leads to suffering, but only that which is accompanied by knowledge of one’s perfection.
3.2. The Influence of Plotinus
Chittick makes it clear that, for Ibn ‘Arabī, everything that exists is a manifestation of the One Being that is God. God is not, as Ibn Sīnā asserts, a type of being. He is all being. As being itself, which is what God is in His absoluteness (Izutsu 1983), God is beyond human understanding, according to Ibn ‘Arabī. However, since Ibn Sīnā views God as a determination of ‘being-qua-being’ (Morewedge 1972, p. 11), he proceeds from a level below that espoused by Ibn ‘Arabī. This means that, unlike Ibn ‘Arabī, Ibn Sīnā believes that the Necessary Being is humanly comprehensible; however, he argues, much like Ibn ‘Arabī, that all existents are nothing but God. There is also a difference in the overall purpose served by emanationism. Ibn Sīnā conscripts the emanatory process as a justification for the denial of creation ex nihilo (Morewedge 2001, p. 79), in opposition to Ibn ‘Arabī, for whom the divine yearning for self-expression does not contradict its temporal unfolding (Ibn ‘Arabī 2002, p. 48).[…] anything that exists is a particular mode, within which the One Being displays Itself. But being is not any thing that exists, for, if it were one thing, it could not be, at the same time, another thing. Being is the ‘thing in every respect’, not in one respect or another.
The cause of this emanation from the divine was the love that God had to see Himself manifested in the Other, or as Ibn ‘Arabī puts it, God wanted to see the essences of ‘His most beautiful Names’ (Al-Asmā’ al-ḥusnā), which are ‘His essence … in a comprehensive creation’ (kawn jāmi‘). Ibn ‘Arabī bases this opinion on a tradition in which God declares, ‘I was a hidden treasure (kanz makhfiyy), and I wished to be known, so I brought forth the creation so that through it they would know Me’ (Ibn ‘Arabī n.d., vol. 2, p. 303). Ibn ‘Arabī offers a commentary on this tradition, in which he says:God, be He exalted, desired to see the essences of His most beautiful Names (Al-Asmā’ al-ḥusnā), which cannot be counted, or, you could say, He wanted to see His essence. So, He chose to do this through a comprehensive creation (kawn jāmi‘) that encapsulates the whole matter through being characterized by existence (wujūd). God’s secret would, thus, be manifest to Him via this creation because seeing something in itself is not the same as seeing it in something else that becomes like a mirror for it.
Ibn ‘Arabī explicitly declares that the ‘cause of the creation of the world’ is God’s self-love, which is the ‘true basis’ for His bringing forth existence. This ontological love results in the existence of the universe as the disparate loci of divine manifestation and imbues them with a love to return to Him. For Ibn ‘Arabī, then, because divine ontological love is a love for self-manifestation in the form of His most beautiful Names (as mentioned in the Qur’an), it is by manifesting these Names most precisely that this proximity to the divine is achieved (Lala 2021; Nettler 1978, pp. 219–29; Nettler 2003, pp. 17–22).So, God wished to be manifested in the forms of existence (ṣuwar al-wujūd), and He wished for Himself to be known to Himself in the mirrors of contingency (marāyā al-mumkināt), just as humans observe their forms in the mirror so as to attain something that they could not attain in themselves without the existence of this form. So that is the love that is the cause (‘illa) of the creation of the world, and it is the true basis (al-asās al-ḥaqīqī) for which He brought forth existence.
Therefore, even though divine self-love brings to pass the emanative process for Ibn Sīnā and Ibn ‘Arabī, the latter’s conception admits of some form of ‘yearning’, whereas the former’s does not. In addition, for Ibn Sīnā, perfection and transcendental happiness can be found in an upward motion in which the rational souls (al-nufūs al-nāṭiqa) become more and more perfect as they acquire perfections. One of these is the perfection of the acquired intellect (al-‘aql al-mustafād), which enables the rational soul to have the intelligibles, so that it can perceive the intelligibles, which are universal concepts, whenever it wishes (Inati 2014, p. 201). At this stage, Ibn Sīnā repeatedly asserts that the rational soul becomes ‘like a polished mirror upon which are reflected the forms’ of things as they are in themselves [i.e., the intelligibles without any distortion]’ (Gutas 2012, p. 424).God does not, and cannot, yearn for anything because … yearning implies some lack, and God does not lack anything. Even if no other beings conceive the presence of His essence and, therefore, love Him, He would still not lack anything.
Considering that one needs to divest oneself of creaturely traits before divine traits are adopted, annihilation precedes subsistence, and subsistence represents a higher level than annihilation. However, there is also another reason why subsistence is superior, as Ibn ‘Arabī explains:Annihilation (fanā’) is when the blameworthy characteristics (al-khiṣāl al-madhmūma) are annihilated from a person. And subsistence (baqā’) is that praiseworthy characteristics (al-khiṣāl al-maḥmūda) are maintained and made firm in a person. So, the seekers on the spiritual path (sālikūn) differ about annihilation and subsistence: some of them annihilate their base desires, that is, what they desire of worldly things, so when their desires are annihilated, their [pure] intention (niyya) and sincerity (ikhlāṣ) in servanthood (‘ubūdiyya) remain. And whoever annihilates their blameworthy traits, like envy, pride, hatred, and others, will be left with magnanimity and sincerity.
The connection (nisba) of subsistence, in our opinion, is more exalted in the spiritual path than the connection of annihilation … for annihilation is that which annihilates in you [creaturely traits] … and subsistence is your connection to God.
3.3. Transcendental Happiness as the Perfect Man
Everything in the universe is a locus of divine manifestation because that was the very purpose for His bringing it into existence. Ibn ‘Arabī states that God is far too exalted for there to be anything besides Him that exists in the universe. Therefore, all that exists is a locus of manifestation of one of His most beautiful Names.For Him is all majesty (kibriyā’) in the heavens and the earth, and that is the essence of God, so it is not possible for His essence not to be a locus because all that is in the heavens and earth is a locus (maḥall) for Him. And His being praised in the universe itself is what ‘majesty’ means, for He is too exalted for anything to be not Him.
Ādam specifically, and humankind more generally, holds a special rank because of being the polish of the mirror in which God sees Himself, in something other than Himself (Sells 1988, pp. 121–49). Ibn ‘Arabī then explains what it means to be the polish of the mirror: ‘All the divine forms that are the [divine] Names are manifest in the formation (nash’a) of humankind, so it has attained the degree (rutba) of completeness and all-inclusiveness’ (Ibn ‘Arabī 2002, p. 50). Thus, humankind has the potential to be the locus of divine manifestation for all of God’s most beautiful Names, which represents its ‘degree of completeness and all-inclusiveness’. However, it is only when humankind fulfills this potentiality that it reaches the rank of the Perfect Man, who has the right to be called the vicegerent (khalīfa) of God, according to Nūr al-Dīn al-Jāmī (d. 898/1492) (Al-Jāmī 2005, p. 79), one of the most important disseminators of Ibn ‘Arabī’s philosophical thought (Rizvi 2006). It is the fulfillment of this potentiality that represents perfection and supreme transcendental happiness, as Ibn ‘Arabī clarifies when he states that happiness is:God, the Exalted, brought forth the whole universe in a form of existence (wujūd) that was vague and undifferentiated, which had no soul; that is why it was like an unpolished mirror (mir’āt ghayr majluwwa). And it is the nature of the divine decree (al-ḥukm al-ilāhī) that it only prepares a locus if it is to receive the divine spirit (rūḥ ilāhī) … so Ādam was the very polish (jalā’) of this mirror and the soul of this form.
[…] the perfection (kamāl) that is sought, which is the reason humankind was created to be a vicegerent, that Ādam, peace be upon him, attained by divine providence (al-‘ināya al-ilāhiyya).
It is only by following the formalistic aspects of religion through the body and by being cognizant of one’s inner reality that one can attain the rank of the Perfect Man, in which one becomes a mirror for the divine and achieves transcendental happiness. God is so named in terms of the manifestation of His actions in the universe, but it is only through these actions that humankind achieves transcendental happiness. The commentators of the Fuṣūṣ are in complete agreement with Ibn ‘Arabī on this issue. The influential early commentator, Mu’ayyid al-Dīn al-Jandī (d. 700/1300?), whose commentary became a model that subsequent generations would emulate (Dagli 2016, pp. 95–104), states in his commentary on this passage:In the same way as your happiness is secured from your actions, likewise, the divine Names (al-asmā’ al-ilāhiyya) are only affirmed through His actions, which are you and are originated. Thus, in terms of His traces (āthār), He is called ‘God’, and in terms of your actions, you are called ‘happy’.
Al-Jandī explains that because humans are merely the loci of manifestation of all the divine Names, their actions are the actions of God. It is in this respect that the actions of God are ‘originated’ because they are nothing but the actions carried out by the manifestation of the divine Names, which are originated in themselves. Therefore, it is only through these acts, and through realizing their true reality, that humans can achieve transcendental happiness.There is no doubt that your following the commands of God are your actions and that in respecting His commands and prohibitions resides your happiness. … So, it is only your actions that lead to your happiness, which are only Him in reality because the actions of God are originated and established by the most beautiful Names.
4. Conclusions
Author Contributions
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | All translations from the Arabic are our own, unless otherwise indicated. |
2 | ‘The Truth’ is commonly used to refer to God by the Sufis (Al-Jurjānī 1845, p. 96). |
3 | A key figure in Shi’ite philosophy, Mullā Ṣadrā (d. 1045/1636), synthesizes the ideas of Ibn Sīnā and Ibn ‘Arabī in his conception of transcendental happiness as the point at which the virtuous soul meets God (Murtada’i 2012). Mullā Ṣadrā underscored the principality of existence (wujūd) over quiddity (māhiyya); he asserted that change in the phenomenal world was not just accidental change but also existential change, which he called ‘trans-substantial motion’ (al-ḥarakat al-jawhariyya) (Nasr 2014). This change is the cause of the gradations of existence. Therefore, just as there are gradations of existence, there are gradations of happiness; indeed, the former is the cause of the latter (Kalin 2010). The lowest level, as Ibn Sīnā and Ibn ‘Arabī delineate, is the happiness that derives from the body, followed by intellectual happiness, and culminating in the transcendental happiness of meeting with the divine (Kalin 2010; Nasr 2014). |
4 | Ibn ‘Arabī clearly had the work of the same name by his predecessor, Abū Ḥāmid al-Ghazālī (d. 505/1111), in mind when he wrote this chapter, which lends credence to the assertion that he viewed himself as someone who was dealing with the issues raised by his forebear, but in a very different way (Ibn ‘Arabī 2017, pp. 1–2). Indeed, Franz Rosenthal suggests that the overall layout of the Futūḥāt, which mimics that of the Iḥyā’—al-Ghazālī’s most popular work—implies that it was offered by Ibn ‘Arabī as an alternative to the former (Rosenthal 1988, p. 35). |
References
- ‘Abd al-Razzāq, Abū Bakr. 1983. Muṣannaf ‘Abd al-Razzāq. Beirut: Al-Maktab al-Islāmī. [Google Scholar]
- Adamson, Peter. 2016. A History of Philosophy without any Gaps: Philosophy in the Islamic World. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Adamson, Peter, and Michael-Sebastian Noble. 2022. Intuition in the Avicennan tradition. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 31: 657–74. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Addas, Claude. 1993. Quest for the Red Sulphur- the Life of Ibn ‘Arabī. Translated by Peter Kingsley. Cambridge: Islamic Texts Society. [Google Scholar]
- Al-Bazzār, Abū Bakr. 1988–2009. Musnad al-Bazzār. Medina: Maktabat al-‘Ulūm wa’l-Ḥikam. [Google Scholar]
- Al-Ḥakīm, Su‘ād. 1981. Al-Mu‘jam al-ṣūfī/ Al-Ḥikma fī ḥudūd al-kalimāt. Beirut: Dandara. [Google Scholar]
- Al-Jāmī, Nūr al-Dīn. 2005. Naqd al-nuṣūṣ fī sharḥ naqsh al-fuṣūṣ. Beirut: Dār al-Kutub al-‘Ilmiyya. [Google Scholar]
- Al-Jāmī, Nūr al-Dīn. 2009. Sharḥ al-Jāmī ‘alā fuṣūṣ al-ḥikam. Beirut: Dār al-Kutub al-‘Ilmiyya. [Google Scholar]
- Al-Jandī, Mu’ayyid al-Dīn. 2007. Sharḥ Mu’ayyid al-Dīn al-Jandī ‘alā fuṣūṣ al-ḥikam. Beirut: Dār al-Kutub al-‘Ilmiyya. [Google Scholar]
- Al-Jīlī, ‘Abd al-Karīm. 1997. Al-Insān al-kāmil fī maʿrifat al-awākhir waʾl-awāʾil. Beirut: Dār al-Kutub al-ʿIlmiyya. [Google Scholar]
- Al-Jurjānī, ‘Alī ibn Muḥammad. 1845. Kitāb al-ta‘rīfāt. Edited by Gustavus Flügel. Leipzig: Typis Guil. Vogelii. [Google Scholar]
- Al-Kindī, Abū Yūsuf. 1948. Kitāb al-Kindī ilā al-Mu‘taṣim bi’llāh fi’l-falsafat al-ūlā. Cairo: Dār Iḥyā’ al-Kutub al-‘Arabiyya. [Google Scholar]
- Al-Nābulusī, ‘Abd al-Ghanī. 2008. Sharḥ jawāhir al-nuṣūṣ fī ḥall kalimāt al-fuṣūṣ. Beirut: Dār al-Kutub al-ʿIlmiyya. [Google Scholar]
- Al-Qāshānī, ‘Abd al-Razzāq. 1951. Sharḥ ‘Abd al-Razzāq al-Qāshānī ‘alā Fuṣūṣ al-ḥikam. Qom: Maktabat Baydār. [Google Scholar]
- Al-Qayṣarī, Dāwūd. 1955. Sharḥ fuṣūṣ al-ḥikam. Iran: Sharika Intishārāt ‘Ilmi wa Farhangī. [Google Scholar]
- Al-Rāzī, Fakhr al-Dīn. n.d. Sharḥ al-Fakhr ‘ala’l-ishārāt. Qom: Mar‘ashī Najafī.
- Al-Samarqandī, Shams al-Dīn. 1979. Bishārāt al-ishārāt fī sharḥ al-ishārāt wa’l-tanbīhāt. Tehran: Peẓūhash Mīrāth. [Google Scholar]
- Anwar, Etin. 2003. Ibn Sīnā’s Philosophical Theology of Love: A Study of the Risālah fī al-‘Ishq’. Islamic Studies 42: 331–45. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. 1999. Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by Terence Irwin. Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company Inc. [Google Scholar]
- Blumenfeld, Jacob. 2022. The Role of Potentiality in Aristotle’s Ethics. Journal of Human Values 28: 91–166. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chittick, William. 1982. The Five Divine Presences: From al-Qūnawī to al-Qaysarī’. The Muslim World 72: 107–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chittick, William. 1989. The Sufi Path of Knowledge: Ibn ‘Arabī’s Metaphysics of Imagination. Albany: State University Press of New York. [Google Scholar]
- Chittick, William. 1992. Faith and Practice of Islam: Three Thirteenth Century Sufi Texts. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Corbin, Henry. 1997. Alone with the Alone: Creative Imagination in the Sūfism of Ibn ‘Arabī. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dagli, Caner. 2016. Ibn al-‘Arabī and Islamic Intellectual Culture: From Mysticism to Philosophy. London and New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Dastagir, Golam. 2001–02. Plotinus and Ibn Sina on the Doctrine of Emanation and the Generation of the Soul. The Jahangirnagar Review Part C 13: 1–14. [Google Scholar]
- De Cillis, Maria. 2014. Free Will and Predestination in Islamic Thought: Theoretical Compromises in the Works of Avicenna, al-Ghāzālī and Ibn ‘Arabī. London and New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Dudley, John. 2018. God’s Pleasure and Man’s Pleasure according to St. Thomas Aquinas. Divus Thomas 121: 178–88. [Google Scholar]
- Dudley, Jonathan. 1983. The Love of God in Aristotle’s Ethics. Neue Zeitschrift für Systematische Theologie und Religionsphilosophie 25: 126–37. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- El-Bizri, Nader. 2001. Avicenna and Essentialism. The Review of Metaphysics 54: 753–78. [Google Scholar]
- Fakhry, Majid. 1976. The Contemplative Ideal. Journal of the History of Philosophy 14: 137–45. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Faydei, Akbar. 2020. Some Logical Ideas of Samarqandī and Allāma Tabataba’i’s Innovative Opinion on the Parts of the Proposition. Islamic Philosophical Doctrines 15: 197–212. [Google Scholar]
- Goichon, Amélie-Marie. 1956. The Philosopher of Being. In Avicenna Commemoration Volume. Edited by Victor Courtois. Calcutta: Iran Society, pp. 107–17. [Google Scholar]
- Griffel, Frank. 2007. On Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāzī’s Life and the Patronage He Received. Journal of Islamic Studies 18: 313–44. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gutas, Dimitri. 1988. Avicenna and The Aristotelian Tradition: Introduction to Reading Avicenna’s Philosophical Works. Leiden and New York: E. J. Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Gutas, Dimitri. 2012. Avicenna: The Metaphysics of the Rational Soul. The Muslim World 102: 417–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gutas, Dimitri. 2014a. Avicenna and the Aristotelian Tradition. Leiden and Boston: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Gutas, Dimitri. 2014b. Orientations of Avicenna’s Philosophy: Essays on his Life, Method, Heritage. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Houben, Jean. 1956. Avicenna and Mysticism. In Avicenna Commemoration Volume. Edited by Victor Courtois. Calcutta: Iran Society, pp. 205–24. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn ‘Arabī, Muḥyī al-Dīn. 2002. Fuṣūṣ al-ḥikam. Beirut: Dār al-Kitāb al-‘Arabī. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn ‘Arabī, Muḥyī al-Dīn. 2017. The Alchemy of Human Happiness (Fī ma‘rifat kīmiyā’ al-sa‘āda). Translated by Stephen Hirtenstein. Oxford: Anqa Publishing. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn ‘Arabī, Muḥyī al-Dīn. n.d. Al-Futūḥāt al-makkiyya. Qom: Mu’assasat Āl al-Bayt li Iḥyā’ al-Turāth.
- Ibn Ḥanbal, Aḥmad. 2001. Musnad al-imām Aḥmad ibn Ḥanbal. Beirut: Mu’assasat al-Risāla. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn Ḥibbān, Muḥammad. 1988. Al-Iḥsān fī taqrīb ṣaḥīḥ Ibn Ḥibbān. Beirut: Mu’assasat al-Risāla. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn Sīnā, Abū ‘Alī. 1899. Risāla fi’l-‘ishq. Leiden: E. J. Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn Sīnā, Abū ‘Alī. 1968. Al-Ishārāt wa’l-tanbīhāt ma‘ sharḥ Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī. Egypt: Dār al-Ma‘ ārif. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn Sīnā, Abū ‘Alī. 1986. Tis‘ rasā’il fi’l-ḥikma wa’l-ṭab‘iyyāt. Edited by Ḥasan ‘Āṣī. Beirut: Dār al-Qābis. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn Sīnā, Abū ‘Alī. 1993. Al-Ishārāt wa’l-tanbīhāt ma‘ sharḥ Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī. Beirut: Mu’assasat al-Ghamān. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn Sīnā, Abū ‘Alī. 1998. Al-Ilāhiyyāt min kitāb al-shifā’. Qom: Maktaba Āyatollāh Mar‘ashī. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn Sīnā, Abū ‘Alī. 2007. Aḥwāl al-nafs. Paris: Dār Byblion. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn Sīnā, Abū ‘Alī. n.d.a. Al-Najāt. N.p: N.p. Available online: https://lib.eshia.ir/73017/1/784 (accessed on 18 January 2023).
- Ibn Sīnā, Abū ‘Alī. n.d.b. Rasā’il Ibn Sīnā. Qom: Intishārāt Baydār.
- Inati, Shams. 1995. The Relevance of Happiness to Eternal Existence: Some Reflections on Ibn Sina’s View. Digest of Middle East Studies 4: 12–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Inati, Shams. 1996. Ibn Sīnā and Mysticism: Remarks and Admonitions: Part Four. London and New York: Kegan Paul International. [Google Scholar]
- Inati, Shams. 2014. Ibn Sina’s Remarks and Admonitions: Physics and Metaphysics. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Izutsu, Toshihiko. 1969. The Fundamental Structure of Sabzavārī’s Metaphysics. In Introduction to the Arabic Text of Sabzavārī’s Sharḥ-i manẓūmah. Edited by M. Mohaghegh and T. Izutsu. Tehran: McGill University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Izutsu, Toshihiko. 1983. Sufism and Taoism. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kalin, Ibrahim. 2010. Knowledge in Later Islamic Philosophy: Mullā Ṣadrā on Existence, Intellect and Intuition. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Karamustafa, Ahmet. 2007. Sufism: The Formative Period. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Khademi, Einollah. 2014. A Study of the Views of Farabi and Ibn Sina on the Definition of Happiness and Its Relation to the Faculties of the Soul. Religious Inquiries 4: 65–76. [Google Scholar]
- Lala, Ismail. 2019. Knowing God: Ibn ‘Arabī and ‘Abd al-Razzāq al-Qāshānī’s Metaphysics of the Divine. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Lala, Ismail. 2021. Qur’anic Knowledge and Akbarian Wisdom: Ibn ‘Arabī’s Daring Hermeneutics in Fuṣūṣ al-Ḥikam. Cumhuriyet Theology Journal 25: 479–93. [Google Scholar]
- Lala, Ismail. 2023a. Muḥammad as the Qur’an in Ibn ‘Arabī’s Metaphysics. Sophia. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lala, Ismail. 2023b. Trauma and the Emergence of Spiritual Potentiality in Ibn ‘Arabī’s Metaphysics. Religions 14: 407. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lane, Edward. 2003. An Arabic-English Lexicon, 8 vols. New Delhi/ Chennai: Asian Educational Services. [Google Scholar]
- Massignon, Louis. 1982. The Passion of al-Ḥallāj: Mystic and Martyr of Islam. Translated by M. Mason. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- McGinnis, Jon. 2010. Avicenna. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Morewedge, Parviz. 1971. The Logic of Emanationism and Ṣūfism in the Philosophy of Ibn Sīnā (Avicenna), Part I. Journal of American Oriental Society 91: 467–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Morewedge, Parviz. 1972. The Logic of Emanationism and Ṣūfism in the Philosophy of Ibn Sīnā (Avicenna), Part II. Journal of American Oriental Society 92: 1–18. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Morewedge, Parviz. 2001. The Mystical Philosophy of Avicenna. Binghamton: Global Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Morrissey, Fitzroy. 2020. Sufism and the Scriptures: Metaphysics and Sacred History in the Thought of ‘Abd al-Karīm al-Jīlī. London: I.B. Tauris. [Google Scholar]
- Murtada’i, Behzad. 2012. The Impact of Ibn Arabi’s Gnostic Unveilings upon Mulla Sadra’s Philosophical Thoughts. Kheradnameh Sadra Quarterly 67. Available online: https://philpapers.org/rec/MURTIO-17 (accessed on 20 January 2023).
- Muslim, Abu’l-Ḥusayn. n.d. Ṣaḥīḥ Muslim. Beirut: Dār Iḥyā al-Turāth al-‘Arabī.
- Nasr, Seyyed H. 2014. Happiness and the Attainment of Happiness: An Islamic Perspective. Journal of Law and Religion 29: 76–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nettler, Ronald. 1978. Ibn ‘Arabī’s Conception of Allah’s Mercy. Israel Oriental Studies 7: 219–29. [Google Scholar]
- Nettler, Ronald. 2003. Sufi Metaphysics and Qur’ānic Prophets. Cambridge: The Islamic Texts Society. [Google Scholar]
- Peters, Francis. 1968. Aristotle and the Arabs: The Aristotelian Tradition in Islam. New York: New York University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Plotinus. 2018. The Enneads. Edited by Lloyd P. Gerson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rapoport, Michael. 2019. Sufi Vocabulary, but Avicennan Philosophy. Oriens 47: 145–96. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rizvi, Sajjad. 2006. The Existential Breath of al-raḥmān and the Munificent Grace of al-raḥīm: The Tafsīr Sūrat al-Fātiḥa of Jāmī and the School of Ibn ‘Arabī. Journal of Qur’anic Studies 8: 58–87. [Google Scholar]
- Rosenthal, Franz. 1988. Ibn ‘Arabī between “Philosophy” and “Mysticism”. Oriens 31: 1–35. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rustom, Mohammed. 2005. Dāwūd al-Qayṣarī: Notes on His Life, Influence and Reflections on the Muḥammadan Reality. Journal of the Muhyiddin Ibn ‘Arabi Society 38: 51–64. [Google Scholar]
- Sells, Michael. 1988. Ibn ‘Arabī’s Polished Mirror: Perspective Shift and Meaning Event. Studia Islamica 67: 121–49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sells, Michael. 1996. Early Islamic Mysticism: Sufi, Qur’an, Mi’raj, Poetic and Theological Writings. Mahwah: Paulist Press. [Google Scholar]
- Theron, Stephen. 1985. Happiness and Transcendent Happiness. Religious Studies 21: 349–67. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wang, Stephen. 2007. Aquinas on Human Happiness and the Natural Desire for God. New Blackfriars 88: 322–34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wolfson, Harry. 1976. The Philosophy of the Kalam. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Lala, I.; Alwazzan, R. Transcendental Happiness in the Thought of Ibn Sīnā and Ibn ‘Arabī. Religions 2023, 14, 729. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14060729
Lala I, Alwazzan R. Transcendental Happiness in the Thought of Ibn Sīnā and Ibn ‘Arabī. Religions. 2023; 14(6):729. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14060729
Chicago/Turabian StyleLala, Ismail, and Reham Alwazzan. 2023. "Transcendental Happiness in the Thought of Ibn Sīnā and Ibn ‘Arabī" Religions 14, no. 6: 729. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14060729
APA StyleLala, I., & Alwazzan, R. (2023). Transcendental Happiness in the Thought of Ibn Sīnā and Ibn ‘Arabī. Religions, 14(6), 729. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14060729