4.1. Nature and Form as Works of God
The ancient and medieval Christian tradition agrees with Laozi and Zhu Xi in stressing the significance of nature as a measure of human action. Its concept of nature, however, is much closer to Confucianism than to Daoism. In its understanding of nature, early Christianity is heir to ancient Greek philosophy in which nature plays a central role. Most of the philosophical ethic of antiquity is rooted in the ideal of a life according to nature (secundum naturam vivere).
13 Albeit with certain modifications, Augustine, and with him many medieval thinkers, adopted this idea. Nature, in this tradition, means something similar to what Zhu Xi understands by it—namely, the essence of things and of the human. This essence is conceived as something determinate that one can bring to expression by means of a definition.
According to Augustine, God, the Creator, bestowed everything with a certain nature, i.e., essence (this is similar to the Neoconfucian view of the nature of all beings stemming from the decree of heaven). Augustine frequently cites biblical wisdom literature, where it is written “You have ordered everything by measure, number, and weight” (Proverbs 11,21). He interprets the essence and all the attributes of things that can be comprehended by numbers as works of God. Whoever studies the nature of things and practices the science of numbers recognizes the laws and structures that God, the Creator, placed in nature. Knowledge, therefore, entails a reflection on that which God has planned. For Augustine, whoever acquires knowledge of real beings retraces God’s thoughts.
Whereas Daoism conceives nature as that which is natural in contrast to that which was made by intervention, Augustine interprets nature as that which was created by God in contrast to that which was made by humans. Although the image of the creator as a divine craftsman was always rejected
14, because it does not capture the idea of creation from nothing
15, the Christian understanding of divine creation does indeed have some proximity to human action insofar as the divine creator and the human craftsman both have a preconceived knowledge of what they are going to make. The Daoist ideal of non-intervention (wu wei) seems incompatible with Augustine’s understanding of nature as a product of divine action. Thus, the Daoist critique of knowledge as a form of intervention is not easily applicable to an Augustinian framework, because, for Augustine, knowledge means understanding the thoughts of the God who created nature.
Augustine has a positive view of the definiteness and the formedness of all beings. Determinateness and form are effects of divine creation. While Laozi states, “The Dao of heaven does not speak”
16, Augustine insists that God does speak, since his word is the principle of all creation.
17 God even is a word. The Gospel of John says as much where it is written: “In the beginning was the word, and the word was with God and the word was God” (Jn 1,1). Augustine takes this to mean that all determinacy and form goes back to God and his word, which is the form of all things.
18 For Augustine, form means perfection. This pertains also to the human soul. In Augustine’s view, education leads to the formation of the soul. Through learning and moral practice, a person’s soul gains more and more unity and order
19, and the soul of the saint is perfectly formed. While for Laozi the sage is like “raw material” (“uncarved wood”), ignorant and indeterminate
20, for Augustine the sage is knowing and fully unified and stable.
21Self-knowledge is a very important form of knowledge for both Augustine and the Confucians. According to Augustine, acquiring self-knowledge is a necessary step for the ascent of the soul from material beings towards God. In the
Soliloquia, he plainly asserts that all he strives for is knowledge of God and of the soul.
22 He writes, “Eternal God, I want to know me and you.”
23 Augustine elaborates the connection between self-knowledge and knowledge of God in
De libero arbitrio. He claims that self-reflection of the human mind reveals two things. First, the human mind stands above all material beings because it possesses abstract concepts and unchangeable rules (like those of logic and mathematics) by which it makes judgments on these beings. Second, since the human mind is a changeable entity, it cannot have created these unchangeable rules of judgment itself but must have received them from an eternal being above the human mind, namely God.
24 The human mind, therefore, becomes aware of God’s existence through self-reflection. In Augustine’s view, self-knowledge is a precondition for the knowledge of God. Like the Confucians, he also claims that it is a necessary step on the way to human perfection.
The dispute between Mencius and Xunzi on the goodness or evilness of human nature is reminiscent of Augustine’s distinction between original human nature and fallen nature. From an Augustinian standpoint, Mencius was right with regard to the human nature created by God. For Augustine, human nature was created good, i.e., harmonious, well ordered towards God, and capable of eternal life and happiness. Through sin, however, it was corrupted. For Augustine, primeval sin was not only a moral failure; it also altered human nature for the worse.
25 Xunzi says “The nature of man is evil”; “And by evil is meant imbalance, violence and disorder”; and “It is the original nature […] of man to love profit and seek gain”
26. These sentences could have come directly from Augustine’s mouth when speaking about humans as they are now, i.e., after sin. However, Augustine claims that even in the state of moral corruption, traces of the original goodness of human nature are preserved, most importantly the natural desire for God that manifests itself as a desire for happiness and truth.
27 The natural longing for peace composes another such trace. Augustine envisions peace as a reestablishment of the original order within the soul, between soul and body, and among human beings in society
28. Augustine still calls a life according to nature—that is, original nature—the happy life, which would be impossible for Xunzi to maintain. Mencius’ statement that human nature has a tendency toward the good as water has a natural tendency to flow downward recalls Augustine’s words: “My love is my weight.”
29 Like weight naturally pulls downward, love naturally pulls toward God, who is the highest good. In spite of his negative view on fallen human nature, Augustine still has some proximity to Mencius’ and Zhu Xi’s idea of the goodness of human nature because, for Augustine, traces of that goodness persist even in fallen humanity.
4.2. Faith, Humility, and Learning
On the one hand, the early Christian thinkers inherited the ancient Greek culture of knowledge and its high estimation of learning. In this regard, Augustine’s thought bears similarities to Confucianism and Neo-confucianism. On the other hand, Augustine did not accept the idea that knowledge inevitably leads to human perfection or that it is even a necessary precondition for it.
In his early works, Augustine underlines the importance of knowledge and learning for the perfection of human beings.
De ordine 2 gives an account of training in the liberal arts as a precondition for the ascent to the vision of God. Even here, however, Augustine points out that knowledge needs to be complemented by faith in divine authority, so that it can lead the human to real happiness.
30 His mature writings criticize knowledge and learning more sharply. In
Confessiones 4, Augustine tells a story about how he as a young man studied all the liberal arts books he could get hold of and easily surpassed his peers in scientific knowledge, but this knowledge did not benefit him because he had turned away from God and did not love him but temporal goods instead. He observes that the unlearned people of the church were closer to God than he was at that time because they loved God even though they had no learning.
31 This story demonstrates a stark difference between Augustine and Confucian and Neo-confucian thinkers regarding the idea of wisdom and perfection. To explain this difference, we must describe Augustine’s position more precisely.
Over time, with an increasing focus on the idea of divine revelation, Augustine distanced himself from the ancient culture of knowledge. For Augustine, there is no rational proof for the fact that God revealed himself in Jesus Christ and that this human individual was the incarnate son of God. This fact, he observes, must be accepted through faith. Therefore, the proper human response to God’s act of love and self-humiliation is gratefulness to God and the love of God. Through humility, humans open themselves up for God’s grace, without which they cannot reach the perfection and happiness that constitute the goal of life. Augustine’s emphasis on humility, faith, and love in the field of anthropology brings forth a sharper distinction between reason and will than in ancient Greek philosophy. While for Plato knowledge necessarily leads to love of the true good
32, for Augustine, insight into the truth can remain fruitless if a person lacks humility toward God. According to Augustine, knowledge of God remains useless, or is even detrimental, if a human being does not have faith in the son of God who became man to redeem all humanity.
Augustine’s
Tractates on the Gospel of John contain his most impressive reflections on this subject matter.
33 In these tractates, he explicates the relationship of philosophy and Christian faith by assuming, modifying, and augmenting Plato’s image of the cave.
34 According to Augustine, we do not have to rise up from a cave into the light of day as Plato imagines; we rather need to scale a mountain from the plains. Just as Plato depicts someone who, having emerged from the cave, beholds the sun from the earth’s surface, Augustine depicts a mountain climber who sees the truth, the goal of life, and the destined homeland from a mountain peak. However, for Augustine, this homeland is not reached by sight alone. It resides in the distance and is only glimpsed from afar, for between the mountain summit and the homeland there is a sea that must be overcome, the sea of life. The means of passage is a ship constructed of wood, namely the wood of the cross. It is only onboard this ship that humans can cross the sea and truly reach the homeland glimpsed from the mountain peak.
The image used by Augustine is readily deciphered. The view from the mountain peak represents the noetic vision of divine light, which symbolizes the highest achievement of knowledge. By extending this image with the element of the sea, however, Augustine makes apparent his reservation against knowledge. The metaphysical vision of God does not entail that one has reached the goal, he argues, for this vision is merely a contemplation from afar. Therefore, Augustine draws a distinction between the sight of God and an abiding with God, between the intellectual vision of God and the willful adhesion to God, between the glimpse of the highest good and the ability to travel to the homeland and dwell there.
35 He acknowledges that philosophy does attain to such a vision, but he does not believe that it provides the means to reach the goal of life.
Augustine further elaborates his depiction by distinguishing three types of humans: the great ones, the little ones, and the proud ones. Of the great ones, he writes “It is good…and best of all, if it be possible, that we both see whither we ought to go, and hold fast that which carries us as we go. This they were able to do, the great minds…; they were able to do this, and saw that which is. For John seeing said, ‘In the beginning was the Word, and the Word was with God, and the Word was God.’ They saw this, and in order that they might arrive at that which they saw from afar, they did not depart from the cross of Christ, and did not despise Christ’s lowliness”.
36 The great humans—and Augustine obviously counts the evangelist John among them—can see; they dispose of the noetic vision of the divine, and simultaneously they trust in the cross in order to traverse the sea and arrive at the envisioned reality. Through philosophy, they possess the highest form of knowledge, and through religion, their will is entirely oriented toward God. To learn and to believe, to see the good itself and to love it over everything else, this is the best way to live according to Augustine.
Of the second type of humans, the little ones, Augustine writes “But the little ones who cannot understand this, who do not depart from the cross and passion and resurrection of Christ, are conducted in that same ship to that which they do not see, in which they also arrive who do see”.
37 Consequently, philosophical training, pinnacled in the intellectual vision of the Platonists, is not necessarily required in order to arrive at the goal. Those who cannot see also reach the longed-for homeland if they merely board the ship of faith and trust that it will bring them to the desired place. Augustine thus repels the elitism of Western classical antiquity, which allows only the few who have access to the good of education a chance at happiness. From a Christian point of view, this possibility is open to all, even to those who, due to a lack of learning, cannot attain a vision of the eternal but faithfully appropriate the teachings of God through trust in the authority of Holy Scripture. This is what Augustine means when he writes “For no one is able to cross the sea of this world, unless borne by the cross of Christ. Even he who is of weak eyesight sometimes embraces this cross; and he who does not see from afar whither he goes, let him not depart from it, and it will carry him over”.
38Augustine classifies the pagan Neoplatonist philosophers among the third type of humans, the proud ones. What the apostle Paul says in his epistle to the Romans applies to them: “Professing themselves to be wise, they became fools” (Rom 1,22). Their foolishness does not reside in not knowing God, Augustine claims, but in the fact that they saw him and still could not summon the humility to recognize the son of God become human in Jesus Christ. Augustine writes “They were able to see that which
is, but they saw it from afar: they were unwilling to hold the lowliness of Christ, in which ship they might have arrived in safety at that which they were able to see from afar and the cross of Christ appeared vile to them. The sea has to be crossed, and do you despise the wood? Oh, proud wisdom!”
39 These philosophers became fools because they assumed that knowledge alone would be sufficient for human perfection.
Augustine claims that the incarnate son of God is not accessible by philosophy but only by faith. Since the way for us to become humble and open ourselves for God’s grace entails recognizing God’s self-humiliation in taking on human flesh, faith is required for the healing of the soul. All attempts to become virtuous through one’s own efforts are principally fruitless. Even worse, they bear witness to human pride and haughtiness. With the humility of the divine logos as the model, one must become meek, admit one’s weakness, and shed tears of confession. According to Augustine, if we humbly admit our inability to attain the good, then God in his grace might bestow on us the strength to change our lives and to live according to our insight. It should be observed, however, that Augustine does not completely renounce the value of knowledge. His abiding commendation of learning is evident in the figures of the first group of humans, the perfect ones. For they do possess philosophical insight. While Augustine believes that whoever is able to learn and study should do so since reason is an integral part of being human, he makes clear that learning is not necessary for reaching life eternal.
In contrast to the Confucians, Augustine delimits the value of education for the attainment of wisdom in two ways. First, he claims that knowledge is not necessarily required to attain wisdom; rather, knowledge can be replaced by faith. Augustine’s position accords here with the Confucian claim that everybody can become a sage, though Augustine is even more radical in extending the opportunity of happiness to all human beings. While the Confucians assert that every human being can turn into a sage through learning, Augustine maintains that everybody can become a saint even without learning. One must keep in mind that in the ancient world learning was expensive; it required much free time and a high social status and was thus reserved for the elite of society. By reducing the relevance of learning, Augustine opens the possibility of happiness for everyone.
Second, Augustine is wary of the potential for the accumulation of knowledge to corrupt one’s character, especially by encouraging pride and arrogance. The educated tend to boast of their cognitive abilities. Such pride inhibits the insight that humans are dependent on God to become virtuous. The emergent “proud wisdom” puffs people up, whereas true wisdom presupposes a humility such that God’s gracious assistance may be received to acquire not just full knowledge but also a good will.
In fact, the biggest point of contrast between Augustine’s thinking and Confucianism centers on the question whether humans possess the power to make themselves virtuous or are powerless without the help of God. Confucius states “Is virtue a thing remote? I wish to be virtuous and lo virtue is at hand”
40, and Zhu Xi interprets this as saying that whoever truly wants to be good will be, because only the will is required for achieving true goodness. According to Augustine’s doctrine of grace, however, the human will to be good is not strong enough. By itself it is unable to overcome the bad passions and the egotistical desires of fallen human nature. Only with the help of God’s grace can a human being achieve goodness of the will. Therefore, humans must humbly acknowledge their own moral incapacity and weakness so they may receive God’s help.
At this point, an unexpected congruence between Augustine’s and Laozi’s thought becomes visible. Even though there are many differences between their metaphysical concepts, they share to some degree a critical view of knowledge and learning. Laozi’s ideas of simplicity, softness, renunciation of power, and non-intervention (wu wei) find a parallel in Augustine’s recommendation of humility, weakness, and passivity toward God’s grace. Both Laozi and Augustine dismiss the trust in one’s own strength as a sign of pride and arrogance. They are both sensitive to the way that learning can lead to pride, arrogance, and an overreliance on one’s own power, thereby separating the human from the Dao or from God.