Did Socrates Meditate? On Some Traces of Contemplative Practices in Early Greco-Latin Philosophy
Abstract
:Etenim quomodo utique adjaciet indicibilissimoomnium aliter quam soporans quæ in ipsa garrulamina?For how else could it [the soul] approach the mostineffable of all things than by putting to sleep the chatter in it?(Proclus, On Providence and Fate, 31, 14, in Steel 2007, p. 56, translation Steel slightly modified)
1. Prelude: The Neurophysiology of Focused and Open Meditation
2. Socrates in the Symposium and the Phaedo
Socrates habitually practiced this: he would stand, so the story goes, in one fixed position, all day and all night, from early dawn until the next sunrise, open-eyed, motionless, in his very tracks and with face and eyes riveted to the same spot in deep meditation (cogitabundus), as if his mind and soul had been, as it were, withdrawn from his body9.
Internal absorption is a relatively early state [along the Path of Zen], a further surge in amplification into hyperawareness. Simultaneously, it deletes vision, hearing, and the sense of one’s physical self-image. These sensate losses seem referable to an inhibitory blockade down at the level of the ventral thalamus, mediated by the back of the thalamic reticular nucleus.
Doesn’t purification (katharsis) then, as the ancient account would have it12, turn out to be the separation of the soul as far as possible away from the body, accustoming it to gathering itself (sunageiresthai) and collecting itself (athroizesthai) by itself, withdrawn from all parts of the body13 and living as far as possible both in the present circumstances and in the future alone by itself, released, as it were, from the chains of the body?”.
What is the meaning of this pleonasm? Surely the words are not linked together for nothing (…) ‘to gather itself together’ (sunageiresthai) means to turn away from corporeal life, and ‘to collect itself’ (athroizesthai) means to turn away from the faculty of opinion. Is it not obvious, moreover, that Plato is giving a parody of the Orphic myths, which tell how Dionysus is torn to pieces by the Titans and is made whole by Apollo, so ‘collecting and gathering itself together’ means passing from the Titanic life to the unitary life? (…) Plato, indeed, gives parodies of Orpheus everywhere.(Olympiodorus 1976, pp. 113–15, translation Westerink, modified)
3. The Doctrine of Innate Ideas
(…) you could best encounter me in a pure way, present and with you day and night, in the most pure and beautiful of unions, without it being possible for me to be separated from you, if you practice rising up to yourself (eis seautên anabainen), collecting (sullegousa) from your body all your dispersed (diaskedasthenta) limbs, which have been cut up (katakermisthenta) into multiplicity, from the state of union that had, until then, prevailed in the greatness of its power. You could gather together (sunagein) and unite (henizein) your innate ideas, trying to articulate them (diarthroun) in their confusion, and bring them to light, now that they have been plunged in darkness. It was starting out from these [innate ideas] that the divine Plato carried out his recalling from sensible things to the intelligibles. Moreover, if you remember them, you could articulate them (diarthroiês).(Porphyry 1969, c. 10)
Therefore, with regard to those things whose images we do not draw in through the senses, but see them within, without images, as they really are and in themselves, we find that learning (discere) them is nothing other than this: those things which memory contained scattered and without order, by thinking them (cogitando), we, as it were, gather them together (colligere), and, by directing our attention to them (animadvertendo), we see to it that, whereas they previously lay hidden, dispersed and neglected, they are now made readily available (ad manum posita), and easily come forward by the familiar kind of effort (familiairi intentione).
4. Aristophanes’ Testimony on Socrates
For in a certain way all things which are in the province of art do partake of measurement; but because people are not in the habit of considering things by dividing them into classes (σκοπεῖν διαιρουμένους), they hastily put these widely different relations into the same category, thinking they are alike; and again, they do the opposite of this when they fail to divide other things into parts.(Plato 1925, translation Lamb modified; cf. Oberhammer 2016, pp. 224–25)
Our job—if indeed we are to examine all these things with scientific knowledge—is to divide (σκοπεῖσθαι αὐτὰ πάντα, οὕτω διελομένους) where they put together, so as to see whether or not both the primary and derivative names are given in accord with nature.(translation C. D. Reeve in Plato 1997)
Ah, my fine fellow, such a conclusion ‘may be’ rash! We must make some distinctions, and examine the question (διαιροῦντες αὐτὸ κατὰ μέρη σκοπώμεθα) rather like this.(translation T. Saunders in Plato 1997)
whenever you hit a dead end, quickly jump to another line of thought (…) if you hit a dead end with one of your ideas, toss it aside and abandon it, then later try putting it in play again with your mind and weigh it up.
Here he attacks Socrates because this is what he did in his investigations.
… think and contemplate, twirl yourself every way and concentrate (φρόντιζε δὴ καὶ διάθρει πάντα τρόπον τε σαυτὸν στρόβει πυκνώσας).(Aristophanes 1998, verse 700, translation Henderson)
“Having condensed (puknôsas): that is, having gathered together (sunagein) your entire intellect” (πυκνώσας] ἤγουν συναγαγὼν πάντα τὸν νοῦν σου.
Now don’t keep winding yourself up in your thoughts; rather, unreel your mind into the air, like a beetle leashed by its leg with a thread (μή νυν περὶ σαυτὸν εἶλλε τὴν γνώμην ἀεί,/ἀλλ’ ἀποχάλα τὴν φροντίδ’ εἰς τὸν ἀέρα/λινόδετον ὥσπερ μηλολόνθην τοῦ ποδός).(Aristophanes 1998, verses 761–63, translation Henderson)
Unreel … air: that is, dissolve yourself (εἰς διάλυσιν δίδου σαυτόν).(Koster 1974, to verse 762β)
5. Εἰς ἑαυτὸν συνειλοῦ: From Aristophanes to Marcus Aurelius
Separating body from soul belongs solely to the one who joined them together; but separating soul from body belongs also to one who longs for virtue. Our fathers call anakhôrêsis a training for death (meletê thanatou) and a flight from the body.
anakhôrêsis from the world does not mean coming to be outside of it in a bodily sense, but breaking off the soul from its sympathy with the body.
It [viz., philosophy] persuades it [viz., the soul] to retreat (anakhôrein) from these senses except where it is necessary to use them, and encourages the soul to gather and collect itself together (autên de eis autên sullegesthai kai athroizesthai) and trust nothing else but itself in itself, whichever of the realities alone by itself it thinks about alone by itself.
Epicurus, in another passage, suggests: “The time when you should most of all withdraw into yourself (in te ipse secede) is when you are forced to be in a crowd.”
People look for retreats (anakhôrêseis) for themselves, in the country, by the coast, or in the hills; and you too are especially inclined to feel this desire. But this is altogether un-philosophical, when it is possible for you to retreat into yourself (eis heauton anakhôrein) at any time you want. There is nowhere that a person can find a more peaceful (hêsukhiôteron) and trouble-free retreat than in his own soul, especially if he has within himself the kind of thoughts that let him dip into them and so at once gain complete ease of mind; and by ease of mind, I mean nothing but having one’s own mind in good order. So constantly give yourself this retreat (anakhôrêsis) and renew yourself.
Withdraw into yourself (Εἰς ἑαυτὸν συνειλοῦ): the reasonable governing self (hêgemonikon) is by its nature content with its own just actions and the tranquility it thus secures.
6. Conclusions
The combined evidence of Aristophanes and Plato suggests that Socrates may have engaged in a practice that has important features in common with meditative practices and experiences attested, for instance, in Zen Buddhism, at least on Austin’s account24. As we have seen, it consists in two stages:
“Do you then think it is possible for the thought to which belongs greatness of soul and the contemplation of all of time and all of substance to regard human life as something great?”“No, that’s impossible.” he replied.“Such a person then will not consider death as something terrifying either?”“No, not at all.”
produced remarkable intensity for his intellect, and rendered his heart a truly divine vessel and another heaven, a dwelling-place more beloved than the heavens, for God, by means of exact attention in accordance with quietude (kath’ hêsukhian)25. That is, in brief, the intellect’s conversion and convergence to itself (tou nou pros heauton epistrophê kai sunneusis26), or rather, amazing as it may sound, the conversion of all the faculties of the soul toward the intellect (pasôn tôn tês psukhês dunameôn (…), pros ton noun epistrophê) and activity according to it and according to God.
Come, noble friends, those who do not prefer earth, which is easily available, to gold, which is hard to procure, and, each of you gathering together the intellect into itself (ton noun (…) eis heauton sunagagontes), as people do with their robes when traversing narrow places, raise it up intently toward the grandeur of thought.(Palamas 1986, Homily 53)
Funding
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Here one may usefully compare the Buddhist doctrine of the triple wisdom (cf. Deroche 2021): wisdom born from reading or listening, wisdom born from thought, and wisdom born from contemplation or cultivation (Sanskrit bhāvanā). Within this third stage, Buddhist theorists distinguish between focused meditation (Skt. śamatha), aimed at states of calm and absorption or concentration (samādhi), and insight meditation (Skt. vipaśyanā); the latter form is characterized by openness. M.-H. Deroche (personal communication) suggests that these two forms of Buddhist meditation may correspond to Hadot’s exercises for the concentration and expansion of the self respectively. |
2 | Both FAM and OMM meditation tend to decrease activity of the DMN by down-regulation and by gating or tuning respectively; cf. (Raffone et al. 2019). On the DMN as correlated with “self-referential processing”, and showing reduced activation during mindfulness meditation, cf. (Tang et al. 2015, p. 220). |
3 | Key centers of the DMN include such midline brain structures as the medial prefrontal cortex, anterior precuneus, and the posterior cingular contex (Tang et al. 2015, p. 220). |
4 | Compare Gehin (1998, p. 175), who points out that in Buddhism “when calm and insight meditation are brought together (…) the unconditioned may be experienced”. |
5 | The two approaches to meditation are often designated as as FAM (Focused Attention Meditation) and OMM (Open Monitoring Meditation) respectively; cf. (Lutz et al. 2008; Raffone et al. 2019). |
6 | Austin classifies internal absorptions as stage VIb in a nine-level division of “Extraordinary Alternate States of Consciousness” (Austin 1998, p. 312). More advanced states include kenshō or Insight-Wisdom (VII), Ultimate Being (VIII), and the State of Ongoing Enlightened Traits (IX). |
7 | The notion of “suchness” in the thought of the Zen master Dōgen (c. 1200–1253) attracted the attention of Pierre Hadot, a few years before his death; cf. (Hadot 2004). |
8 | τὸν οὖν Σωκράτη ἑαυτῷ πως προσέχοντα τὸν νοῦν κατὰ τὴν ὁδὸν πορεύεσθαι ὑπολειπόμενον. Most translations banalize this remarkable expression prosekhein ton noun, which literally means “to direct the attention of one’s intellect”. Cf. Plato, Meno 96d: “So our first duty is to direct our intellect to ourselves (προσεκτέον τὸν νοῦν ἡμῖν αὐτοῖς), and try to find somebody who will have some means or other of making us better”. |
9 | Compare the story of Master Hanshan (16th century), who “sat immobile on a bridge absorbed in samadhi for a day and a night, unaware of his surroundings” (Austin 2006, p. 322). Compare the description by the 6th-7th century CE Christian Johannes Climacus (Scala Paradisi, chp. 5, ed. Migne, Patrologia Graeca vol. 88, 756A), of the Monastery of Repentance, where the monks engaged in sometimes spectacular self-mortification: “I have seen some of these innocent guilty stand under the open sky all night, until the morning, with their feet immobile”. Here, of course, the point of the monks’ practice was not to obtain insight into the nature of reality, but to inflict suffering upon themselves with a view to expiating their sins. |
10 | Hadot (2002, p. 181) himself does not exclude the possibility that Socrates may have been engaged in exercices of breath control in the passages from the Symposium and the Phaedo that speak of exercices for “concentrating the soul”. |
11 | Elsewhere (Austin 1998, pp. 468–519; cf. index s.v. Absorption), Austin speaks of “internal absorption” as cases in which (1998, p. 278), the “visual grasp reflex”, originating primarily in the superior colliculus of the midbrain have been overridden and amplified by the “gaze centers” in the frontal lobe. Internal absorption constitutes phase VI-B in Austin’s scale of nine “ordinary and meditative states of consciousness”; cf. the tables in Austin (1998, pp. 300–3). |
12 | The reference in ὅπερ πάλαι ἐν τῷ λόγῳ λέγεται is probably to an ancient (palai) soteriological doctrine (logos), presumably Orphic, Pythagorean, or a combination of the two. On the expression palaios logos as designating “some Orphic poem in Plato (ap. Platonem quoddam Orphicum carmen)”, cf. (Bernabé Pajares 2004, p. 47), 2nd apparatus criticus to line 7. |
13 | I thank an anonymous reviewer for calling my attention to an interesting parallel from the Hippocratic Corpus, Regimen IV on Dreams (Hippocrates 1931, p. 421, translation modified), which may help to understand in what way the soul, in its waking state, is dispersed throughout the body: “When the body is awake, the soul (psukhê) is its servant; it never comes to belong to itself (ou gignetai autê heôutês), but is partitioned among many things (epi polla merizomenê), assigning a part of itself to each faculty of the body—to hearing, to sight, to touch, to walking, and to acts of the whole body; but thought does not come to belong entirely to itself (autê d’ heôutês hê dianoia ou ginetai). But when the body is at rest, the soul, being set in motion and awake, manages its own household (dioikeei ton heôutês oikon), and itself performs all the acts of the body. For the body when asleep has no perception; but the soul when awake has cognizance of all things—sees what is visible, hears what is audible, walks, touches, feels pain, ponders”. |
14 | χωρίζειν ὅτι μάλιστα ἀπὸ τοῦ σώματος τὴν ψυχὴν. In a highly influential text (Sentences 7–9), Porphyry distinguishes between the process by which nature binds the body within the soul and releases the body from the soul, and that by which the soul binds itself within, and then separates itself from, the body. The former kind of separation or release is natural death, the latter is philosophical death. See the text, translation and commentary in Brisson (2005, vol. I, pp. 310–11, vol. 2, pp. 394–400). |
15 | Cf. (Detienne 1963). Unfortunately, Detienne and others went on to attribute the terminology in question to Pythagoreanism which, he thought, itself represented a vestige of primordial shamanism. These are murky waters: not much is known about ancient Pythagoreanism, as opposed to later Hellenistic reconstructions and forgeries of its doctrines. As for shamanism, for which great claims of historical importance have been made, I cannot judge, although I am sceptical of claims for its all-pervading universality, as was Hadot (1995, p. 116, n. 79; 2002, pp. 181–85). |
16 | Cf. Plato, Phaedo 83b, discussed below. In subsequent Greek philosophy, these two terms are among those used to denote the process by which, according to Aristotle, individual sense impressions are “gathered together” or “collected”, in order to give rise to the formation of universal concepts (Metaphysics A, Posterior Analytics 2.19); cf. (Helmig 2012, pp. 31–32). |
17 | Likewise, for Augustine (De genesi ad litteram XII.xxvi.54), it is possible to ascend from the vision of spiritual realities that resemble bodies to the region of intellectual or intelligible realities, which have no resemblance to bodies and are not obscured by the clouds of false opinions (nullis opinionum falsarum nebulis offuscatur). Since Middle Platonism, opinion (Greek doxa) is identified as the faculty that allows us to perceive and recognize sensible objects. |
18 | Similarly, Proclus (Commentary on the Timaeus, vol. I, p. 198, 11ff. ed. Diehl) reminds us that Apollo is “the god who collects (sunagôn) and reunites (henizôn) the dismembered limbs (ta meristhenta melê) of the lad Dionysus in accordance with the will of the father”. |
19 | On meletê, which Hadot translates by “meditation”, cf. Hadot (1995, pp. 84–86, 87–89 (Epicureans), 96–97 (Platonic), 133–34 (Christian). Hadot defines meletê as “an attempt to control inner discourse, in an effort to render it coherent” (ibid., p. 85). Above all, meditation, for Hadot, is “the practice of dialogue with oneself” (ibid., p. 91). |
20 | The doctrine of innate ideas is essential to Neoplatonic thought, although it has not been sufficiently studied. It originates in the myth of Plato’s Phaedrus, when the souls, prior to their incarnation within a human body, follow the chariots of the gods and contemplate the Platonic Ideas that are found in the supracelestial place. They are thereby filled with wisdom, but when they fall down to earth to be incarnated in a human body, the vestiges of this divine knowledge they carry within their souls in the form of innate ideas, often described as a spark of the intellect, becomes, as it were, cooled off and buried under a heap of ashes. Only with the healing that results from personal tutoring by a skilled Neoplatonic teacher can these buried sparks be fanned until they burst into flame again, at which time they can serve as steps in ladder that can help the soul to rise back up to the intelligible world whence it came. The best presentation of these themes remains Hoffmann (1987); cf. (Chase 2014, p. 85f). |
21 | Stallbaum (Stallbaum 1841, p. 239) compares Phaedrus 265Eff., Sophist 253C-D; Republic 7, 532Aff., and astutely remarks that what is alluded to here is nothing other than the method of analysis and synthesis, on which see (Chase 2015). |
22 | Hadot cites Schaerer (1969, pp. 84–87), who views it as characteristically Platonic. For Hadot (1993, p. 53), this method of approaching a problem from several starting-points was extremely influential: it is likely to have been important in the Academy, and scholars such as Ingemar Düring have argued that it one of the most characteristic features of thought of Aristotle. |
23 | The distinction between separating body from soul (designating natural death, the time and place for which reserved for God) and separating soul from body (designating the Platonic exercise of training for death) goes back to Porphyry, Sentences 7–9; cf. supra n. 14. On the use of Porphyrian material by Evagrius, cf. (Pirtea 2019). |
24 | It should be emphasized, of course, that the ascetic aspects of Greek meditation, largely directed is it was to separating the soul from the body, which is viewed as an obstacle to knowledge and true awareness, is totally foreign to the embodied, holistic viewpoint of Zen. |
25 | On hêsukhia, cf. Marcus Aurelius, Meditations 4.3, cited above (hêsukhiôteron). |
26 | For the expression eis heauton/eis heautên sunneuein, where the meanings of sunneuô include “contract, converge, concentrate” (Lampe 1961), cf. Porphyry, Sentence 43; Proclus, Platonic Theology, vol. 4, p. 110, 13; vol. 5, p. 22, 16 ed. Saffrey-Westerink; Proclus, Commentary on Alcibiades I, p. 247, 14–15 ed. Westerink; Simplicius ? In De an., p. 103, 4; 229 12, 273, 33 ed. Hayduck; Simplicius, Commentary on the Manual of Epictetus, preface line 65 ed. I. Hadot; Michael of Ephesus, In EN IX p. 603, 17 ed. Heylbut, etc. |
References
- Aristophanes. 1998. Clouds. Wasps. Peace. Loeb Classical Library. Translated and Edited by Jeffrey Henderson. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Augustine. 1969. Confessions. Livres IX–XIII. Texte établi et traduit par Pierre de Labriolle. Tome II. Paris: Les Belles Lettres. [Google Scholar]
- Austin, James H. 1998. Zen and the Brain. Toward an Understanding of Meditation and Consciousness. Cambridge and London: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
- Austin, James H. 2006. Zen-Brain Reflections. Reviewing Recent Developments in Meditation and States of Consciousness. Cambridge and London: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
- Austin, James H. 2009. Selfless Insight. Zen and the Meditative Transformations of Consciousness. Cambridge and London: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
- Austin, James H. 2011. Meditating Selflessly. Practical Neural Zen. Cambridge and London: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
- Austin, James H. 2014. Zen-Brain Horizons. Toward a Living Zen. Cambridge and London: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
- Austin, James H. 2016. Living Zen Remindfully. Retaining Subconscious Awareness. Cambridge and London: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
- Basil of Caesarea. 1957–1966. Saint Basile. Lettres. Edited by Yves Courtonne. Paris: Les Belles Lettres. [Google Scholar]
- Bernabé Pajares, Alberto. 2004. Poetae Epici Graeci Testimonia et fragmenta, Pars. II, fasc. 1, Orphicorum et Orphicis similium testimonia et fragmenta. Monachii et Lipsiae: K. G. Saur. [Google Scholar]
- Brisson, Luc, ed. 2005. Porphye, Sentences. Études d’introduction, texte grec et traduction française, commentaire par l’Unité Propre de Recherche n° 76 du Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique, avec une traduction anglaise par John Dillon. Paris: Vrin. [Google Scholar]
- Chase, Michael. 2014. Time and Eternity from Plotinus and Boethius to Einstein. ΣΧOΛH, Ancient Philosophy and the Classical Tradition 8: 67–110. [Google Scholar]
- Chase, Michael. 2015. Quod est primum in compositione, est ultimum in resolutione. Notes on analysis and synthesis in Late Antiquity. Anuario Filosófico 48: 103–39. [Google Scholar]
- Chase, Michael. 2019. Attention in Neoplatonism: From Plato to Porphyry and the Christian Church Fathers. Available online: https://www.academia.edu/39801745/Attention_in_Neoplatonism_From_Plato_to_Porphyry_and_some_Christian_Church_Fathersfinitive_version (accessed on 22 December 2021).
- Cunliffe, Richard John. 1963. A Lexicon of the Homeric Dialect. Norman: University of Oklahoma Press. [Google Scholar]
- Davey, Christopher G., Jesús Pujol, and Ben J. Harrison. 2016. Mapping the self in the brain’s default mode network. NeuroImage 132: 390–97. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Deroche, Marc-Henri. 2021. Mindful wisdom: The path integrating memory, judgment, and attention. Asian Philosophy 31: 19–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Detienne, Marcel. 1963. La notion de «daïmôn» dans le pythagorisme ancien. Paris: Les Belles Lettres. [Google Scholar]
- Diccionario Griego-Español. n.d. Available online: http://dge.cchs.csic.es/xdge/ (accessed on 14 September 2021).
- Dover, K. 1968. Aristophanes, Clouds. Edited with an Introduction and Commentary. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Gehin, Rupert. 1998. The Foundations of Buddhism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Gellius, Aulus. 1927. Attic Nights, Volume I: Books 1–5. Loeb Classical Library. Translated by John Carew Rolfe. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Guillaumont, Antoine. 1991. Anachoresis. Claremont Coptic Encyclopedia. Available online: http://ccdl.libraries.claremont.edu/cdm/ref/collection/cce/id/123 (accessed on 19 December 2021).
- Hadot, Pierre. 1993. Exercices spirituels et philosophie antique. Troisième édition, revue et augmentée. Paris: Institut d’Études Augustiniennes. [Google Scholar]
- Hadot, Pierre. 1995. Philosophy as a Way of Life. Spiritual Exercises from Socrates to Foucault. Edited with an Introduction by Arnold I. Davidson. Translated by Michael Chase. Oxford and Cambridge: Basil Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Hadot, Pierre. 2002. What is Ancient Philosophy? Translated by Michael Chase. Cambridge and London: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hadot, Pierre. 2004. Préface à Yoko Orimo, Le Shôbôgenzô de Maître Dôgen. In Le Shôbôgenzô de Maître Dôgen, La Vraie loi, Trésor de l’œil. Edited by Yoko Orimo. Paris: Seuil, pp. 15–21. [Google Scholar]
- Hadot, Pierre. 2019. La Philosophie Comme Éducation des Adultes. Textes, Perspectives, Entretiens. Préface d’Arnold Davidson. Postface d’Ilsetraut Hadot. Édition établie par Arnold I. Davidson et Daniele Lorenzini. Paris: Vrin. [Google Scholar]
- Harter, Pierre-Julien. 2018. Spiritual exercises and the Buddhist path: An exercise in thinking with and against Hadot. In Buddhist Spiritual Practices Thinking with Pierre Hadot on Buddhism, Philosophy and the Path. Edited by David Fiordalis. Berkeley: Mangalam Press, pp. 147–79. [Google Scholar]
- Helmig, Christoph. 2012. Forms and Concepts: Concept Formation in the Platonic Tradition. Berlin and Boston: Walter de e Gruyter. [Google Scholar]
- Hippocrates. 1931. Hippocrates, Heracleitus. IV. In Nature of Man. Regimen in Health. Humours. Aphorisms. Regimen 1–3. Dreams. Heracleitus: On the Universe. Translated by William Henry Samuel Jones. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hoffmann, Philippe. 1987. Catégories et langage selon Simplicius—La question du σκοπός du traité aristotélicien des Catégories. In Simplicius: Sa vie, son œuvre, sa survie, Actes du Colloque international de Paris (28 sept.–1er Oct. 1985). Organisé par le Centre de Recherches sur les Œuvres et la Pensée de Simplicius (RCP 739-CNRS). Edited by Ilsetraut Hadot. Berlin and New York: Walter de Gruyter, pp. 61–90. [Google Scholar]
- Horn, Christoph. 1998. Antike Lebenskunst. Glück und Moral von Sokrates bis zu den Neuplatonikern. München: Verlag C.H. Beck. [Google Scholar]
- Koster, Willem Johann Wolff. 1974. Prolegomena de comoedia. Scholia in Acharnenses, Equites, Nubes (Scholia in Aristophanem 1.3.2). Groningen: Bouma. [Google Scholar]
- Lampe, Geoffrey William Hugo. 1961. A Patristic Greek Lexicon. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Liddell, Henry George, Robert Scott, Henry Stuart Jones, Roderick McKenzie, and P. G. W. Glare. 1996. A Greek-English Lexicon. Oxford: Clarendon Press, New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lutz, Antoine, Heleen A. Slagter, John D. Dunne, and Richard J. Davidson. 2008. Attention regulation and monitoring in meditation. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 12: 163–69. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Marcus Aurelius. 1840. Theophrasti Characteres. Marci Antonini Comentarii…. Edited by Jean-Frédéric Dübner. Paris: Didot. [Google Scholar]
- Marcus Aurelius. 1944. Markou antwninou autokratoros ta eis eauton/The Meditations of the Emperor Marcus Antoninus. 2 vols. Edited with Translation and Commentary by Arthur Spencer Loat Farquharson. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Oberhammer, Arnold Alois. 2016. Buchstaben als Paradeigma in Platons Spätdialogen. Dialektik und Modell im Theaitetos, Sophistes, Politikos und Philebos. Berlin: De Gruyter. [Google Scholar]
- Olympiodorus. 1976. In Platonis Phaedomen commentaria. In The Greek Commentaries on Plato’s Phaedo [Olympiodorus]. Edited by Leendert Gerrit Westerink. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Co., vol. 1. [Google Scholar]
- Palamas, Gregory. 1986. Γρηγορίου τοῦ Παλαμᾶ ἅπαντα τὰ ἔργα. Edited by Panagiotis K. Chrestou. Θεσσαλονίκη: Πατερικαὶ Ἐκδόσεις Γρηγόριος ὁ Παλαμᾶς, vol. 11. [Google Scholar]
- Palamas, Gregory. 1992. Γρηγορίου τοῦ Παλαμᾶ συγγράμματα. Edited by Panagiotis K. Chrestou. Θεσσαλονίκη: συνδρομὴ του Βασιλικοῦυ Ιδρύματος Ερευνών, vol. 5. [Google Scholar]
- Pirtea, Adrian. 2019. The origin of passions in Neoplatonic and early Christian thought: Porphyry of Tyre and Evagrius Ponticus. In Platonism and Christian Thought in Late Antiquity. Edited by Panagiotis G. Pavlos, Lars Fredrik Janby, Eyjólfur Kjalar Emilsson and Torstein Theodor Tollefsen. London: Routledge, pp. 258–74. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. 1925. Statesman. Philebus. Ion. Translated by Harold North Fowler, and W. R. M. Lamb. Loeb Classical Library 164. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. 1997. Complete Works. Edited, with Introduction and Notes, by John M. Cooper. Associate editor D. S. Hutchinson. Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. 2017. Euthyphro. Apology. Crito. Phaedo. Translated and Edited by Christopher Emlyn-Jones, and William Preddy. Loeb Classical Library. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ponticus, Evagrius. 1971. Évagre le Pontique. Traité pratique ou le moine. Edited by Antoine Guillaumont and Claire Guillaumont. Paris: Éditions du Cerf, vol. 2. [Google Scholar]
- Porphyry. 1969. Letter to Marcella. In Porphyrios. Πρὸς Μαρκέλλαν. Edited by Walter Pötscher. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Raffone, Antonino, Laura Marzetti, Cosimo Del Gratta, Mauro Gianni Perrucci, Gian Luca Romani, and Vittorio Pizzella. 2019. Toward a brain theory of meditation. In Meditation. Edited by Narajana Srinivasan. Cambridge: Academic Press, pp. 207–31. [Google Scholar]
- Schaerer, René. 1969. La Question Platonicienne. Paris: Vrin. [Google Scholar]
- Scholia to Aristophanes. 1977. Edited by Douwe Holwerda. In Prolegomena de comoedia. Scholia in Acharnenses, Equites, Nubes (Scholia in Aristophanem 1.3.1). Groningen: Bouma. [Google Scholar]
- Stallbaum, Godofredus. 1841. Platonis Opera omnia, recensuit et commentariis instruxit Godofredus Stallbaum. Vol. IX, Sect. I, continens Politicum et Minoem. Gothae: Sumptibus Fridericae Hennings. [Google Scholar]
- Steel, Carlos. 2007. Proclus. On Providence. London: Duckworth. [Google Scholar]
- Tang, Yi-Yuan, Britta K. Hölzel, and Michael. I. Posner. 2015. The neuroscience of mindfulness meditation. Nature Reviews Neurosciences 16: 213–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Tzetzes, Johannes. 1960. Jo. Tzetzae commentarii in Aristophanem. Edited by Douwe Holwerda (Scholia in Aristophanem 4.2). Groningen: Bouma. [Google Scholar]
- Usener, Hermannus. 1887. Epicurea. Lipsiae: B. G. Teubner. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Chase, J.M. Did Socrates Meditate? On Some Traces of Contemplative Practices in Early Greco-Latin Philosophy. Religions 2022, 13, 479. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13060479
Chase JM. Did Socrates Meditate? On Some Traces of Contemplative Practices in Early Greco-Latin Philosophy. Religions. 2022; 13(6):479. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13060479
Chicago/Turabian StyleChase, John Michael. 2022. "Did Socrates Meditate? On Some Traces of Contemplative Practices in Early Greco-Latin Philosophy" Religions 13, no. 6: 479. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13060479
APA StyleChase, J. M. (2022). Did Socrates Meditate? On Some Traces of Contemplative Practices in Early Greco-Latin Philosophy. Religions, 13(6), 479. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13060479