3.1. Jamesian Pragmatist Antitheodicy: Widening the Concept of Truth
One may argue that an experientially deeper, more dynamic concept of truth than the one available in largely realistic, correspondence-theory-based analytic philosophy of religion—that is, a pragmatic concept of truth we may derive from William James’s pragmatism (see especially James 1907/1975 in (
James 1975–1988), chp. 6)—plays a fundamental role in the structures of acknowledgment when it comes to developing an appropriate ethical attitude to the “truth” of others’ suffering. What we need is a broader, richer, and more clearly non-foundationalist—that is, preferably (but perhaps not necessarily) pragmatist—notion of truth in order to properly communicate experiences of suffering, and our acknowledgment of others’ suffering, in an ethically appropriate way across diverse religious, theological, and secular outlooks. This ethical challenge is
ipso facto a challenge of developing the notion of truth itself in a pragmatist way, in a manner in which the acknowledgment of others’ experiences, such as experiences of suffering, particularly in their ethical dimensions—e.g., our future-oriented worry, care, or
Sorge for the other—is an ineliminable part of the dynamics of truth in adequately responding to otherness. It is this essentially concerned or even “worried” future-directedness that the pragmatist conception of truth arguably takes into account better than any other, especially if we also read James’s writings on truth alongside his relational conception of identity based on his radical empiricism, as suggested in José Medina’s (
Medina 2010) interpretation of his theory of truth. It is on these grounds that we may seek to develop a synthesis of pragmatism and recognition theory (or, rather, the theory of acknowledgment), focusing on the notion of truth.
It can be argued, furthermore, that James’s conception of truth already incorporates important aspects of the more explicitly ethical concept of
truthfulness. Admittedly, the pragmatist theory of truth is far from uncontroversial, as anyone who ever read undergraduate textbooks on truth knows. We might here, however, approach it by referring to the distinction between truth and truthfulness, analyzed, e.g., in Bernard Williams’s (
Williams 2002) important book with that title. These are clearly different notions. One may pursue truthfulness without thereby having true beliefs; one can be truthful also when one is mistaken, insofar as one sincerely seeks to believe truths and avoid believing falsehoods and also honestly seeks to tell the truth whenever possible (and whenever the truth to be told is relevant). Thus, clearly, whatever one’s theory of truth is, one should in some way distinguish between truth and truthfulness. On the other hand, certain theories of truth, such as the pragmatist theory, may be more promising in articulating the intimate relation between truth and truthfulness than some other theories—and this, we may suggest, is highly relevant to the theodicy vs. antitheodicy issue.
We might say that the distinction between truth and truthfulness is in a way “softened” in James’s pragmatist conception of truth, which rather explicitly turns truth into a value to be pursued in one’s (individual and social) life rather than simply a matter of propositional truth corresponding to facts that are mind- and discourse-independently “out there” in the world. Truth(fulness) in the Jamesian sense is, then, richer and broader than mere propositional truth. It is a normative property of our human thought and inquiries (in a wide, practice-embedded sense), not simply a semantic property of statements or beliefs. James’s pragmatic truth hence incorporates truthfulness, as truth belongs to the ethical field of inter-human relations of dependence and acknowledgment. It also incorporates an acknowledgment of the (at least potential) inner truth of others’ experiences, especially experiences of suffering.
In his discussion of James’s theory of truth,
Medina (
2010) also defends Jamesian pluralism in a politically relevant manner: in ethics and politics, we can never reach an “absolute” conception of what is universally best for human beings and societies, but different suggestions, opinions, experiential perspectives, and interests must have their say—or must be recognized or acknowledged (though this is not Medina’s terminology). James advocated not only pragmatic pluralism and individualism but also (on Medina’s reading) a relational conception of individual identities: nothing exists in a self-sustained manner but only as parts of networks of mutual interdependence. While James’s pluralism and relationalism are elements of a metaphysical view according to which “nothing can be understood in and by itself, but rather in relation to other things, in a network of relations”, they are irreducibly ethical and political, applying even to the reality of the self: “to have a sense of self is to have a sense of the dependences that compose one’s life” (ibid., p. 124). We are, Medina continues, “diverse and heterogeneous beings […] shaped and reshaped through diverse and heterogeneous networks of interpersonal relations”, and the Jamesian self is a bundle of such relations (ibid., p. 125; cf. also (
Pihlström 2013)).
It is in this context that we should, according to Medina, understand and appreciate James’s theory of truth. True beliefs, as James himself says, are “good to live by”; when maintaining a belief, any belief, we are responsible for its consequences in our lives, and in those of others. The pragmatic “theory” of truth—which should not be called a “theory”, in order to avoid seeing it as a rival to, say, the “correspondence theory”—invokes not only, say, the agreeable consequences of true beliefs but also ethical ideas such as solidarity and justice. Therefore, we may say that truth (in the Jamesian pragmatic sense), truthfulness, and acknowledgment are conceptually tied to each other. One cannot really pursue truth in the Jamesian sense unless one also acknowledges, or at least truthfully seeks to acknowledge, others’ perspectives on reality—especially those defined by suffering.
If we take even a brief look at James’s various pronouncements of the significance of the problem of evil and suffering,
4 we may note how thoroughly those discussions of the diversity of our human responses to such predicament are characterized by references to reality and truth. I suggest that these occurrences of such philosophical terms ought to be taken seriously as elements of James’s account of truth and reality—and thus as key elements of his pragmatism more generally. James argued, against “the airy and shallow optimism of current religious philosophy”, that what desperate and suffering human beings experience “
is Reality”: “But while Professors Royce and Bradley and a whole host of guileless thoroughfed thinkers are unveiling Reality and the Absolute and explaining away evil and pain, this is the condition of the only beings known to us anywhere in the universe with a developed consciousness of what the universe is”. (James 1907/1975 in (
James 1975–1988), pp. 20–21) Thus, idealist, optimistic (e.g., Hegelian) philosophers “are dealing in shades, while those who live and feel know truth”; a Leibnizian theodicy postulating a harmony of the universe is “a cold literary exercise, whose cheerful substance even hell-fire does not warm” (ibid., pp. 22, 20). What I have called theodicism is, for James, part of the “unreality in all rationalistic systems” of “religious” philosophy that remain “out of touch with concrete facts and joys and sorrows” (ibid., p. 17). James here even quotes at length from Leibniz’s
Théodicée, concluding that “no realistic image of the experience of a damned soul had ever approached the portals of his mind” (ibid., pp. 19–20).
5The references to truth, facts, and reality in these formulations must be understood as elements of the ethically interwoven fabric of James’s pragmatism in general. James’s antitheodicist remarks can be seen as philosophically urging us to acknowledge the meaninglessness of suffering, i.e., the fact that in reality there is no harmonious world-system or a necessary divine reason for suffering. This is, in a sense, to recognize the sufferer as sufferer. As recognition requires the “as” clause—B recognizes A as something, as X—the one who employs the concept of recognition here must presuppose that there is something like the truth about the matter whether A is X, or can be construed as being X. This can, and in many obvious cases is, a truth created by the act of recognition itself; in our social life many important social facts, statuses, and institutions are created in this way. Thus, the fact (or the factual or propositional truth) that A is X, which enables B to recognize A as X, is either independent of B’s recognition act or constituted by it, by B’s “taking” A to be X. However, in both cases we are dealing with truths about the (social) world.
Now, it may be argued that the traditional correspondence theory of truth does not serve this situation very well. What we (arguably) need here is a more dynamic pragmatic notion of truth also covering cases where the truth of A’s being X is “made” by us. But even more importantly, we need a pragmatic notion of truth for those cases where there is no “as” dimension available at all—that is, for acknowledgment rather than recognition. This is another kind of
ethical truth, truth conceived or reconceived as something like truthfulness. It is a conception of ethical truth compatible with, or perhaps even required by, James’s famous dictum in “The Moral Philosopher and the Moral Life” (1891), according to which there can be no “final truth” in ethics until the “last man” has had his experience and his say (James 1897/1979 in (
James 1975–1988), p. 141). Thus, this is precisely the kind of ethical truth we need for a conception of ethics that admits, with James, that “there is no such thing as an ethical philosophy dogmatically made up in advance” (ibid.).
Acknowledging, with James, that there is no such final truth in ethics—or religion—is, we may argue, part of what we can, and should, mean by our being committed to ideals such as truthfulness and sincerity in our acknowledgment of others and their morally relevant perspectives on the world. There can, then, be something like the pursuit of truth, as well as something like truth itself, in the act of acknowledgment even if there is no narrow propositional sense of truth available regarding the “as” clause, as required in recognition. This pursuit of truth in a pragmatist sense is essentially the pursuit of a truthful attitude to the other person’s suffering (or one’s own suffering), which in the end will then lead into, or at least enable, a truthful attitude to experience in general—or the world in general.
6 This yields an indirect (and reflexive) argument in favor of pragmatism: its conception of truth (and truthfulness) in the service of acknowledging diverse others and othernesses, and their various experiences of suffering and attempts to communicate those experiences, pragmatically works.
However, things are not as simple as that. While James’s pragmatism insightfully integrates truth and truthfulness, or incorporates elements of the notion of truthfulness into the pragmatically articulated notion of truth itself, and while (we may say) Jamesian pragmatism generally is framed by taking evil and suffering seriously in an antitheodicist manner (that is, without succumbing to the temptations of theodicy that would allegedly explain away the reality of meaningless suffering), it can be argued that the notion of objective truth itself is, in an irreducible way, required by the kind of antitheodicist attitude that James seems to be recommending as a sine qua non of a properly ethical acknowledgment of otherness.
Can truthfulness, in a sense fundamental to acknowledgment, be maintained even if mere propositional truth (fundamental to recognition, given the central role of the “as” clause) loses at least part of its significance in Jamesian pragmatism? Acknowledgment, rather than recognition, can be seen as the key to truthful explorations of suffering. This can also be regarded as a fundamentally Jamesian view—while employing terminology different from James’s own. In his ethical thought, James argued against our instinctive “blindness” and “deafness” in relation to other human beings and their individual ways of viewing the world. James may be read as presenting us with a profound, and endless, ethical challenge to acknowledge otherness, especially the other’s suffering—as the framing of the entire pragmatist project makes clear. It could even be argued that the way in which James’s pragmatic method is introduced (in James 1907/1975 in (
James 1975–1988), chps. 2–3, in particular) as a method of “making our ideas clear” by (re-)entangling abstract metaphysical concepts with their conceivable ethical relevance (cf.
Pihlström 2009) actually presupposes an antitheodicist understanding of the irreducible reality of suffering as something that needs to be taken fundamentally seriously in any ethical—or, therefore, metaphysical—world engagement.
We are here dealing with the need to acknowledge others’ suffering itself as well as others’ attempts to communicate their suffering, possibly across diverse religious and theological (but also non-religious) outlooks that are foreign to us. As James maintains in his 1898 lecture “Human Immortality”, encouraging us to acknowledge what he calls our “half-brutish prehistoric brothers”: “‘Tis you who are dead, stone-dead and blind and senseless, in your way of looking on. You open your eyes upon a scene of which you miss the whole significance. Each of these grotesque or even repulsive aliens is animated by an inner joy of living as hot or hotter than that which you feel beating in your private breast.” (James 1982 in (
James 1975–1988), p. 99). The same line of thought is strongly present in James’s 1899 essay “On a Certain Blindness in Human Beings”. There James, observing the work of farmers and outdoor manual laborers, charges himself, and us, of being “as blind to the peculiar identity of their [those others’] conditions as they certainly would also have been to the ideality of mine, had they had a peep at my strange indoor academic ways of life” (James 1983 in (
James 1975–1988), p. 134).
It is this kind of blindness that we have a moral duty to avoid, just as we are, according to Emmanuel Levinas (who, of course, comes from a quite different philosophical tradition), invited to appreciate the other’s face—as will be seen in a moment.
7 It is, moreover, by self-critically countering such instinctive blindness that we may cherish the virtues of acknowledgment and truthfulness—and this, I am suggesting, is part of what it means to develop the notion of truth itself in a pragmatic manner. When developed in this Jamesian way, the notion of truth already has an ethics of truthfulness and acknowledgment built into it. This, I submit, is where its deepest antitheodicist significance lies.
3.2. Wittgensteinian Antitheodicy: D.Z. Phillips
Let us, before considering Levinas’s version of antitheodicy, turn from Jamesian pragmatism to a brief examination of the kind of antitheodicism that is central to the distinctive trend in the philosophy of religion inspired by Ludwig Wittgenstein. Theodicies have from a Wittgensteinian perspective been regarded as
unethical violations of religious language use (even though Wittgenstein himself had little to say about this particular topic). Religiously speaking, theodicies could even be criticized as superstitious or blasphemous (cf.
Phillips 1977,
2004).
Let us note, first, that several Wittgensteinian philosophers have argued that theodicies allegedly justifying “God’s ways to man”—that is, arguments seeking to make sense of apparently meaningless and absurd evil and suffering in God’s overall harmonious plan—amount not only to ethically insensitive use of language disregarding or misrecognizing others’ suffering in its utter pointlessness but also to conceptual confusion and pseudo-religious use of language. It is not only ethically wrong but in an important sense
meaningless and
conceptually confused, and thus beyond the meaning-constitutive grammar of religious language-games, to claim that others’ suffering has a metaphysical or theological meaning, function, or explanation. Such a “conceptual oddness” of theodicies has been noted not only by Phillips (see, e.g., (
Phillips 1977,
2004)) but also by Ben Tilghman (
Tilghman 1994, p. 192)—who uses this very phrase—and by Stephen Mulhall (
Mulhall 1994, pp. 18–19), who even suggests that theodicies end up with blasphemy. In a similar vein, Andrew Gleeson (
Gleeson 2012, especially chp. 1), also writing against theodicies in a broadly Wittgensteinian tradition, notes that theodicies should be criticized on both moral and conceptual grounds, while Mikel Burley (
Burley 2012, §5) points out that the theodicist is “so confused as to be unaware of the degree of their own insensitivity” to pain and suffering—with both moral as well as logical and conceptual dimensions pertaining to this confusion.
Let me offer a few more specific observations on Phillips’s approach in particular. The Wittgensteinian method Phillips (along with many other Wittgensteinians) subscribes to carefully looks at the actual use of language in concrete human situations and practices, instead of any a priori rules or principles establishing linguistic meanings. Yet, he also emphasizes the general Wittgensteinian (and also, broadly speaking, pragmatist) ideas that “it is only in the context of [religious] language games that belief in God has any meaning” and “concepts have their life” “only in practice, in what we do” (
Phillips 1993, pp. xi, xiii). In his criticism of theodicies, in particular, Phillips focuses on what goes wrong in the very form of the allegedly moral reasoning the theodicist engages in; he interestingly cites the Book of Job here: “Job cannot make
sense of his afflictions in terms of the [theodicist] arguments of his would-be comforters” (ibid., p. 157). While those defending theodicies try to calculate what kinds of goods or benefits might outweigh or compensate for the evils and sufferings there are, the Phillipsian-cum-Wittgensteinian antitheodicist objects to “the
concept of calculation in this context, because it excludes
moral concepts” (ibid., p. 158; original emphases).
Phillips argues that the truly religious reaction to the contingencies and adversities of human life does not seek to “tidy up” messy human reality or to find explanations and understandings of suffering (see ibid., pp. 166–68). On the contrary, properly (genuinely, truly) religious uses of language, when addressing the problem of evil and suffering, recognize the limits of understanding and linguistic expression—not as contingent limitations that could in principle be transcended but just factually cannot be overcome by us, but as necessary limits defining the relevant language-game and therefore playing a (quasi-)transcendental role in constituting what is meaningful and possible for us (see ibid., p. 168), albeit in the end only contextually necessary limits that could in principle be redrawn as our lives change.
A transcendental critique of theodicies, when formulated from a Wittgensteinian perspective along Phillips’s lines, thus crucially focuses on the “grammar” constitutive of moral and religious language, that is, on the transcendentally meaning-structuring rules of the relevant language games—rules that might, however, themselves be historically transformed. If we take seriously the Wittgensteinian line of thought according to which there can be no meaning without practice-laden, habitual, world-engaging use of expressions within public human ways of acting, or language games, then we should also acknowledge the fact that the meanings of such expressions as “evil”, “suffering”, “God”, “meaning”, etc., are inextricably entangled with our using them in religious (and other) language-games and thus in our forms of life. If we do take this seriously, then it is conceptually, morally, and religiously misguided to seek to provide a theodicy—or to require one.
In many cases, for a genuinely religious person who sincerely attempts to speak about God in a religious way, belief in God’s reality is the necessary background of any potential theological or philosophical account of evil and suffering. Any possible argument, including the atheist’s argument challenging the theist to provide a theodicy by appealing to the problem of evil, will have to be evaluated against this background. The believer might point out, against both the atheist and the theist seeking to provide a theodicy, that it is strictly speaking nonsensical (i.e., beyond the meanings available in religious language-games) for human beings to try to evaluate God’s motives morally, or to seek to criticize or justify them. At the moment when the theodicist begins to engage in an argument, pro or contra, regarding the problem of evil conceived as an atheist challenge, the grammar of the religious language-game will already have been violated and the relevant expressions will no longer be used in a genuinely religious meaning. Therefore, the atheist argument starting from the problem of evil and suffering does not even get off the ground due to this confusion. But those theists who try to respond to such an argument by producing a theodicy are equally confused, or perhaps even more confused, because they do not perceive the atheists’ confusion any more than their own.
Theodicies should therefore be rejected as transcendentally confused misuses of the language of “God”, “evil”, and “suffering”. It can be suggested that one comes close to illegitimately transgressing the limits of meaningful discourse—the limits of religious language—simply in examining the problem of evil in terms of the alleged “argument from evil” and in attempting to respond to such an argument theodicistically. Both the theist and the atheist theodicists fail to follow the grammar of religious language religiously and thus breach the limits of language.
It is roughly in this way that I would like to suggest we can reinterpret Phillips’s and other Wittgensteinians’ perceptive remarks on theodicies being both morally and conceptually (or even logically) confused. The reason why these confusions are so deep is that they are transcendental in the sense of this word that remains available in the later Wittgenstein’s thought. This is the transcendentality of the constitutive (albeit historically transformable and reinterpretable) features of language-games and forms of life. It is only by violating the limits of language that the problem of evil and suffering construed as an atheist argument requiring a theodicy as a response can so much as be formulated. When we realize that such a (mis)formulation is based, precisely, on a violation of grammar, we realize that the entire business of theodicy is misconceived from the start. It is by means of a Wittgensteinian analysis of the limits of language that this point can be brought home.
However, as soon as we note all this we should re-emphasize that the grammar and meanings of our expressions may vary historically along with the changes and transformations taking place in our forms of life. The necessity of transcendental rules is, in a sense, based on the contingency of human life. This applies with full force to the problem of evil and suffering. Different reactions to this problem may become possible in different historical circumstances characterizing the forms of life through which the grammar of the relevant language-games is established. We may, for instance, find it necessary to examine the problem of evil and suffering after the Holocaust in a way essentially different from its pre-Holocaust articulations. In the contingent historical context in which the Holocaust actually took place and will therefore permanently, ineliminably, irredeemably, be part of our human history, it may seem that certain (new) limits of appropriate religious language have been established. It is no longer possible—morally or conceptually—to approach the problem of evil by providing a theodicy. We now—after the Holocaust—can see this as a striking, violent confusion. Moreover, we can now see—after the Holocaust—that it was never possible, even if that was not as clearly perceivable earlier. Historical contingencies may thus ground philosophical, ethical, and conceptual necessities—and this I take to be a fundamental Wittgensteinian message.
In the terms used in the previous
Section 3.1, we might say that contextualizing philosophical inquiries into evil and suffering in this manner—that is, viewing historical events such as, paradigmatically, the Holocaust as crucial in shaping those inquiries or their very possibility today—also amounts to a truthful attitude to the inquiries at issue here, roughly in the sense in which James’s pragmatism was above claimed to incorporate an ethical notion of truthfulness in its account of truth. It is not only objective, propositional truth that we seek when seeking to understand evil and suffering in the context of the Holocaust (using that word metonymically to cover all instances of horrible, meaningless suffering). It is, more broadly, ethical truthfulness of proper acknowledgment that is at issue in our inquiry. It is right here that Jamesian pragmatism and Phillips’s Wittgensteinianism could plausibly join forces.
3.3. Jewish Post-Holocaust Antitheodicy: Emmanuel Levinas
Emmanuel Levinas, whom I am here discussing as a representative of the phenomenological tradition (distinct from both James’s pragmatism and Phillips’s Wittgensteinianism), compellingly argues, in “Useless Suffering”, one of his most important antitheodicist writings, that any theodicy is completely disproportional and out of balance in relation to the forms of suffering we know from the history of the twentieth century.
8 Not unlike
Phillips (
1977), who reminds us that catastrophes may strike “without rhyme or reason”, Levinas emphasizes the “depth of meaninglessness” in suffering, the “for nothing” character of suffering, and the intimate relation between evil and suffering: “All evil relates back to suffering” (
Levinas 2006, p. 79).
Some of the most central themes of Levinas’s philosophy as a whole are in fact strongly present in “Useless Suffering”. It is precisely the “attention to the suffering of the other” that (he argues) “can be affirmed as the very nexus of human subjectivity” and is the “supreme ethical principle” that is “impossible to question” (ibid., p. 81). Moreover, “my responsibility for the other, without concern for reciprocity”, the asymmetrical relation between the other and myself (ibid., p. 87), is a core idea of Levinas’s ethics as a whole, and it finds a particularly strong expression in his treatment of suffering and antitheodicy.
In the main work of his late thought,
Otherwise than Being or beyond Essence, Levinas adds a footnote explaining further one of his best-known formulations of what it means to be an ethical subject, according to which “[t]o be oneself, the state of being a hostage, is always to have one degree of responsibility more, the responsibility for the responsibility of the other” (
Levinas 1981, p. 117). The note explicitly links this with suffering:
The vortex—suffering of the other, my pity for his suffering, his pain over my pity, my pain over his pain, etc.—stops at me. The I is what involves one movement more in this iteration. My suffering is the cynosure of all the sufferings—and of all the faults, even of the fault of my persecutors, which amounts to suffering the ultimate persecution, suffering absolutely. This is not a purifying fire of suffering […]. This moment of the “for nothing” in suffering is the surplus of non-sense over sense by which the sense of suffering is possible.
(ibid., p. 196)
The (nonsensical) “sense” of suffering lies only in the ethical subject’s (
my) absolute and infinite responsibility. While Levinas does not tell us
expressis verbis what kind of impossibility we are dealing with in the impossibility of questioning our responsibility for the other, we may suppose that this impossibility of questioning the duty of attending to the other’s suffering is both ethical and metaphysical—in a sense in which the two are inseparably entangled (in a manner not very dissimilar from James’s pragmatism; cf. (
Pihlström 2009,
2013)). The same inseparability of the metaphysical and the ethical can be seen in Levinas’s uncompromising rejection of any theodicy:
Perhaps the most revolutionary fact of our twentieth-century consciousness—but it is also an event in Sacred History—is that of the destruction of all balance between Western thought’s explicit and implicit theodicy and the forms that suffering and its evil are taking on in the very unfolding of this century. […] This is the century that is drawing to a close in the obsessive fear of the return of […] suffering and evil inflicted deliberately, but in a manner no reason set limits to, in the exasperation of a reason become political and detached from all ethics. […] [T]he Holocaust of the Jewish people under the reign of Hitler seems to me the paradigm of gratuitous human suffering, in which evil appears in its diabolical horror. […] The disproportion between suffering and every theodicy was shown at Auschwitz with a glaring, obvious clarity.
Levinas continues to note that the “suffering for nothing” of the Holocaust victims “renders impossible and odious every proposal and every thought that would explain it by the sins of those who have suffered or are dead” (ibid., p. 84). Again, it is the justification of the other’s (my neighbor’s) pain and suffering that is an “outrage” and “the source of all immorality” (ibid., p. 85). Such an attempt at justification can take very different forms—as recognized in Levinas’s reference to not only the explicit but also the “implicit” (e.g., presumably, secular) theodicies in Western thought.
We should note that Levinas constantly helps himself to modal formulations in his characterizations of the obscenity of theodicies. The “suffering in the other” is not only unjustified but “unjustifiable”, and the crematoria of the final solution render theodicy “impossible” (ibid.). It is in this modal sense, in particular, that we may view Levinas’s post-Holocaust antitheodicy as “Kantian” and transcendental—just as we may view Phillips’s Wittgensteinian antitheodicy as transcendental in its focus on the constitutive features of language games. Theodicies make our moral relations to other human beings (as well as our appropriately ethical discourse on such relations) impossible. This is a clear link between Phillips and Levinas: ultimately the issue concerning theodicy and antitheodicy pertains to the conditions of religious and ethical language and, therefore, to what needs to be presupposed in order for any humanly meaningful discourse in these areas to be possible for us.
In this sense, for Levinas as much as for James and Phillips, any theodicy is a form of ethical
insincerity precisely because it fails to appropriately acknowledge the utter meaninglessness of suffering. This failure is manifested in theodicist language use violating the conditions constitutive of ethically appropriate (religious or secular) language games. There are, of course, major differences between the three philosophers I have cited as representatives of antitheodicism. Their philosophical methodologies are obviously very different. James’s pragmatic method (cf. James 1907/1975 in (
James 1975–1988), chps. 2–3) is relatively far from (and indeed critical of) any Kantian transcendental methodology—even though it has been suggested in James scholarship that it is not implausible to read him as a Kantian thinker in a revised and reinterpreted sense (as proposed in (
Pihlström 2013))—and while Phillips and Levinas are both concerned with the necessary conditions for the possibility of meaning and meaningfulness and have thus been engaged in something like transcendental investigation (albeit not in Kant’s original sense), their approaches remain quite distinct, as Phillips focuses on a Wittgensteinian “grammatical” examination of language games (religious ones included), while Levinas views meaning in relation to the ethical primacy of the other to and for whom we are infinitely responsible. Despite these obvious methodological differences, and the even clearer differences in philosophical style and content, the three thinkers considered share, however, a fundamentally antitheodicist attitude to what goes wrong in philosophical and theological attempts to justify others’ suffering.