Can Machines Be Artists? A Deweyan Response in Theory and Practice
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Creativity in Psychology and AI: Computational Creativity
A similar high valuation is expressed by the psychologists Beth Hennessey and Teresa Amabile, in a recent major review. They write thatthe ability to generate novel, and valuable, ideas. Valuable, here, has many meanings: interesting, useful, beautiful, simple, richly complex, and so on. Ideas covers many meanings too: not only ideas as such (concepts, theories, interpretations, stories), but also artefacts such as graphic images, sculptures, houses, and jet engines.
They go on to define it as “the development of a novel product, idea, or problem solution that is of value to the individual and/or the larger social group” (Hennesey and Amabile 2010, p. 572). For these writers, civilization itself has arisen naturally through unaided creativity by gifted individuals, but now the demands for progress and national achievement are greater, and scientific psychology and theoretical understanding are required to help it along.If we are to make real strides in boosting the creativity of scientists, mathematicians, artists, and all upon whom civilization depends, we must arrive at a far more detailed understanding of the creative process, its antecedents, and its inhibitors. The study of creativity must be seen as a basic necessity.
3. Some Reservations about These Definitions
These human attributes conventionally belong to innovators in any field. They are not inner processes in the brain but refer to activities in the social world over long periods of time, and certainly apply to the innovating computer scientists responsible for the achievements of CC. However, they cannot comfortably be applied to computers or programmes themselves; if this is the case, it is not the computers of CC which have these qualities and are creative, but the computer scientists who build them and write their programmes. More generally, if these qualities are among the distinctive characteristics of being an artist, it would be misleading to speak of the machine as an artist.The fact that you can put a dozen inexperienced people into a room and conduct a brainstorming session that produces exciting new ideas shows how little relative importance ideas themselves actually have. Almost anybody with the intelligence of the average businessman can produce them, given a halfway decent environment and stimulus. The scarce people are those who have the know-how, energy, daring, and staying power to implement ideas.
In this definition, although creativity may involve generating ideas, more goes on in the mind and the world than the simple generation of novel ideas and valuable products envisaged by earlier writers. This more general picture by Mumford is part of how we judge creativity. Colton makes a similar point on behalf of CC when he writes that the product alone is not enough in assessing creativity and in the case of painting “the process of creating an artefact is often a deciding factor in the assessment of that artefact.” (Colton 2008). In practice, CC is by no means only a search for a creative product but has widespread applications to other fields, such as education and medical diagnosis (Wagstaff 2012; Sturm and Ben-Tal 2017).Creativity is not simply a matter of generating ideas. Instead, creativity is defined as the production of high quality, original, and elegant solutions to complex, novel, ill-defined problems.1
On this way of thinking, it is the brain that is seen as the mysterious (but mechanistic) source of creative products, which is the stance taken by many cognitive scientists who are investigating creativity. As Guilford himself wrote years before he discovered the word, “all the results of human invention and construction are creations of the human brain” (Guilford 1939, p. 486).The notion that creativity requires inspiration derives from puzzlement about how a mechanism (even a biological mechanism like the brain), if it proceeds in its lawful, mechanistic way, can ever produce novelty… for novelty is at the core of creativity. In fact, we shall define creativity operationally, in full accordance with general usage, as novelty that is regarded as having interest or value (economic, aesthetic, moral, scientific or other value).
4. Dewey’s Creativity
John Dewey is often regarded as America’s greatest philosopher and was equally influential as an educationalist and as a psychologist. In addition, his work on thinking and inquiry formed the basis of his monumental work on artistic activity, Art and Experience (Dewey 1934), as well as investigations of scientific thinking. His aim in education was to move away from what regarded as the stultifying effect of learning facts and rules and towards the cultivation of habits of free inquiry and critical thinking (Rudolph 2014). The word “creative” was important in his own thinking about science, the arts, and human living in general. This emphasis on free inquiry put him at odds with standard practice in education and psychology, with its emphasis on intelligence as a fixed power in the mind. He did not like the practice of measuring human minds or the uses to which measurement was put. He did not write at length about this, but in 1917 he edited a book containing contributions from like-minded pragmatist philosophers and psychologists, notably his close friend and colleague G.H. Mead.The key question isn’t “What fosters creativity?” But why in God’s name isn’t everyone creative? Where was the human potential lost? How was it crippled? I think therefore a good question might not be why do people create? But why do people not create or innovate? We have got to abandon that sense of amazement in the face of creativity, as if it were a miracle that anybody created anything.
5. Whitehead’s Creativity
Dewey and Mead discussed Whitehead at length (Cook 1979), and later Dewey introduced the word “creativity” in his own writings. This described an individual process of change to correspond to Whitehead’s more general process of change in the universe, and it reflected his own earlier use of “creative”.In the abstract language here adopted for metaphysical statement, “passing on” becomes “creativity,” in the dictionary sense of the verb create, “to bring forth, beget, produce.” [and] no entity can be divorced from the notion of creativity.
6. Dewey’s Definition of Creativity
Later, in a foreword to Henry Schaeffer-Simmern’s (1948) The Unfolding of Artistic Activity, Dewey gave a definition of “creativity” in a paragraph which captures in a few words his theory of what it means to be creative. He defined creativity asThe emphasis James places upon the individual quality of human beings and all things is, of course, central in his pluralism. But the adjective “individual” is often converted into a noun, and then human beings and all objects and events are treated as if they were individual and nothing but individual. The result is that identification of human beings with something supposed to be completely isolated which is the curse of the so-called individualistic movement in economics, politics and psychology. I find the actual position of James to be well represented in a remark he quotes from a carpenter of his acquaintance: “There is very little difference between one man and another; but what there is, is very important.” It is this element which is precious because it is that which nobody and nothing else can contribute, and which is the source of all creativity. Generic properties, on the other hand, are replaceable and express the routines of nature.
Creative activity, therefore, is activity that has an impact by sustaining or changing the established order that has guided the individual to which she belongs; and is present in everyday activities, such as gardening or cooking, where there is a state of creative intelligence, active interest, and alertness. They are what Dewey called “habits of thinking” and if he ever read Guilford’s 1950 paper his suggested correction would be simple: Instead of “the creative person has novel ideas”, he would write “the creative person has the habits of thought that make for creative activity”; these habits of thought comprise habits of perseverance, patience, interest, curiosity, awareness, as well as those envisaged by Levitt.the life factor that varies from the previously given order, and that in varying transforms in some measure that from which it departs, even in the very act of receiving and using it. This creativity is the meaning of artistic activity—which is manifested not just in what are regarded as the fine arts, but in all forms of life that are not tied down to what is established by custom and convention. In re-creating them in its own way it brings refreshment, growth, and satisfying joy to one who participates.Accompanying this principle… is the evidence that artistic activity is an undivided union of factors, which, when separated, are called physical, emotional, intellectual, and practical—these last in the sense of doing and making. These last, however, are no more routine and dull than the emotional stir is raw excitation. Intelligence is the informing and formative factor throughout. It is manifested in that keen and lively participation of the sense organs in which they are truly organs of constructive imagination”.
desire that they should learn the pleasure of taking time, digging in, asking questions and challenging themselves was being more effectively communicated to the children—and they were responding.
7. Dewey’s Brain
It follows that thinking and intelligence for Dewey are processes that belong to the whole organism and are not confined to the brain or mind.An animal is... continuous with chemico-physical processes which, in living things, are so organised as really to constitute the activities of life with all their defining traits. And experience is not identical with brain action; it is the entire organic agent-patient in all its interaction with the environment, natural and social. The brain is primarily an organ of a certain kind of behaviour, not of knowing the world.
8. Discussion
In the essay itself, Benjamin pointed out that, considered as visual art forms, photography and film differ essentially from traditional museum art, where the individual artefact has an “aura” generated by its authenticity. Reproductions are far less valuable than the unique original since they lack the aura, but this doesn’t apply to photography and film; in these new art forms what we see is always itself a reproduction, and the original can be reproduced indefinitely without loss of value. He argued that it is a mistake to try to assimilate these new forms to what went before, by forcing them into a fixed category or concept of “art”. Instead, the western notion of art has changed, even though we may continue to use the same word. Photography and film have joined painting and sculpture as visual art, even though the aura is lost. The old art talk about meanings and intentions and creative influences will still be there.Our fine arts were developed, their types and uses were established, in times very different from the present, by men whose power of action upon things was insignificant in comparison with ours. But the amazing growth of our techniques, the adaptability and precision they have attained, the ideas and habits they are creating, make it a certainty that profound changes are impending in the ancient craft of the Beautiful. In all the arts there is a physical component which can no longer be considered or treated as it used to be, which cannot remain unaffected by our modern knowledge and power. For the last twenty years neither matter nor space nor time has been what it was from time immemorial. We must expect great innovations to transform the entire technique of the arts, thereby affecting artistic invention itself and perhaps even bringing about an amazing change in our very notion of art.(Valery, quoted in Benjamin [1937] 1968, p. 219)
Dewey would agree that there is no point in this, but not because living in the world and having flesh is irrelevant to human thinking, but the opposite; because it is essential to being human, and therefore to the thinking and creativity that are part of being human. On this view, Turing’s “fairly sharp line” is a mistake that reflects the traditional dualism that Dewey rejected.The new problem (i.e., the Turing test) has the advantage of drawing a fairly sharp line between the physical and intellectual capacities of a man. No engineer or chemist claims to be able to produce a material which is indistinguishable from the human skin. It is possible that at some time this might be done, but even supposing that this invention available we should feel there was little point in trying to make a ‘thinking machine’ more human by dressing it up in such artificial flesh.
9. A Deweyan Approach to the Design of AI Systems for Creativity
Author Contributions
Funding
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Ariza, Christopher. 2009. The interrogator as critic: The Turing test and the evaluation of generative music systems. Computer Music Journal 33: 48–70. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Arnold, Matthew. 1914. Essays by Matthew Arnold. London: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Benjamin, Walter. 1968. The work of art in the age of mechanical reproduction. In Illuminations. London: Fontana, pp. 214–18. First published 1937. [Google Scholar]
- Boden, Margaret A. 1990. The Creative Mind: Myths and Mechanisms. London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson. [Google Scholar]
- Boden, Margaret A. 2009. Computer models of creativity. AI Magazine Fall 30: 23–39. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Boden, Margaret A. 2010. The Turing test and artistic creativity. Kybernetes 39: 409–13. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Claxton, Guy. 2006. Cultivating creative mentalities: A framework for education. Thinking Skills and Creativity 1: 57–61. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Colton, Simon. 2008. Creativity Versus the Perception of Creativity in Computational Systems. Paper presented at the AAAI Spring Symposium: Creative Intelligent Systems, Palo Alto, CA, USA, March 26–28. [Google Scholar]
- Colton, Simon. 2012. The Painting Fool: Stories from Building an Automated Painter. In Computers and Creativity. Edited by McCormack Jon and Mark d’Inverno. Berlin: Springer. [Google Scholar]
- Cook, Gary A. 1979. Whitehead’s Influence on the Thought of G. H. Mead. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 15: 107–31. [Google Scholar]
- Dewey, John. 1934. Art as Experience. New York: Perigree Books. [Google Scholar]
- Dewey, John. 1948. Foreward. In The Unfolding of Artistic Activity. Edited by Henry Schaefer-Simmern. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dewey, John. 1989. William James and the world today. In The Later Works of John Dewey, 1925–1953: Essays, Reviews, and Miscellany, 1942–1948. Edited by Jo Ann Boydston. Carbonville: Southern Illinois University Press. First published 1942. [Google Scholar]
- Dewey, John, Boyd Henry Bode, Horace Meyer Kallen, Addison Webster Moore, Harold Chapman Brown, George Herbert Mead, and Henry Waldgrave Stuart. 1917. Creative Intelligence; Essays in the Pragmatic Attitude. New York: Henry Holt. [Google Scholar]
- Eigemmal, Ahmed, Bingchen Liu, Mohamed Elhoseiny, and Marian Mazzone. 2017. CAN: Creative Adversarial Networks Generating “Art” by Learning about Styles and Deviating from Style Norms. arXiv, arXiv:1706.07068. [Google Scholar]
- Emerson, Ralph. W. 1975. The American Scholar. In The Portable Emerson. Edited by MarkVan Doren. Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin Books, pp. 23–46. [Google Scholar]
- Glӑveanu, Vlad. 2010. Paradigms in the study of creativity: Introducing the perspective of cultural psychology. New Directions in Psychology 28: 79–93. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Guilford, John P. 1939. General Psychology. Princeton: Van Nostrand. [Google Scholar]
- Guilford, John P. 1950. Creativity. American Psychologist 5: 444–54. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Hennessey, Beth A., and Teresa M. Amabile. 2010. Creativity. Annual Review of Psychology 61: 569–98. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Hutton, Charles. 1811. A Course of Mathematics. London: F.C. and J. Rivington. [Google Scholar]
- Johnston, James S. 2006. Inquiry and Education: John Dewey and the Quest for Democracy. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kasparov, Gary. 2010. The Chess Master and the Computer. New York Review of Books, February 11. [Google Scholar]
- Kasparov, Gary. 2018. Deep Thinking: Where Machine Intelligence Ends and Human Creativity Begins. London: John Murray. [Google Scholar]
- Levitt, Theodor. 1963. Creativity Is Not Enough. Harvard Business Review, August. [Google Scholar]
- Mackintosh, Nicholas. J. 2011. IQ and Human Intelligence. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- McCormack, Jon, Gifford Toby, Hutchings Patrick, Llano Maria Teresa, Matthew Yee-King, and Mark d’Inverno. 2019. In a Silent Way Communication between AI and improvising musicians beyond sound. Paper presented at CHI 2019 Conference on Human Factors in Computing Systems, Glasgow, UK, May 4–9. [Google Scholar]
- Maslow, Abraham H. 2000. The Maslow Business Reade. New York: Wiley. First published 1959. [Google Scholar]
- Mazzone, Marian, and Ahmed Eigemmal. 2019. Art, creativity, and the potential of Artificial Intelligence. Arts 8: 26. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Osborn, Alex F. 1948. Your Creative Power: How to Use Imagination. New York: Scribners. [Google Scholar]
- Pachet, François, Pierre Roy, Julien Moreira, and Mark d’Inverno. 2013. Reflexive loopers for solo musical improvisation. In Proceedings of the SIGCHI Conference on Human Factors in Computing Systems. New York: ACM, pp. 2205–208. [Google Scholar]
- Ribot, Th. 1906. Essay on the Creative Imagination. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co., Ltd. [Google Scholar]
- Rudolph, John L. 2014. Dewey’s “Science as Method” a Century Later. Reviving Science Education for Civic Ends. American Educational Research Journal 51: 1058–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schaeffer-Simmern, Henry. 1948. The Unfolding of Artistic Activity. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Silver, David, Julian Schrittwieser, Karen Simonyan, Ioannis Antonoglou, Aja Huang, Arthur Guez, Thomas Hubert, Lucas Baker, Matthew Lai, Adrian Bolton, and et al. 2018. A general reinforcement learning algorithm that masters chess, Shogi, and Go through self-play. Science 262: 1140–44. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Simon, Herbert A. 1995. Explaining the ineffable: Al on the topics of intuition, insight and inspiration. In Fourteenth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence. San Francisco: Morgan Kaufmann, pp. 939–48. [Google Scholar]
- Stein, Morris I. 1953. Creativity and culture. Journal of Psychology 36: 311–22. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Still, Arthur. 1986. The biology of science: An essay on the evolution of representational cognitivism. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 16: 257–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Still, Arthur, and Mark d’Inverno. 2016. A history of creativity for future AI research. Paper presented at 7th International Conference on Computational Creativity (ICCC 2016), Universite Pierre et Marie Curie, Paris, France, June 27–July 1. [Google Scholar]
- Sturm, Bob L., and Oded Ben-Tal. 2017. Back to music practice: The evaluation of deep learning approaches to music transcription, modelling and generation. Journal of Creative Music Systems 2: 1. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Turing, Alan M. 1950. Computing Machinery and Intelligence. Mind 59: 433–60. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Varela, Francisco, Evan Thompson, and Eleanor Rosch. 1991. The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wagstaff, Kiri L. 2012. Machine Learning that Matters. Paper presented at 29th International Conference on Machine Learning, Edinburgh, Scotland, UK, June 26–July 1. [Google Scholar]
- Whitehead, Alfred N. 1968. Process and Reality. New York: The Free Press. First published 1929. [Google Scholar]
- Wiggins, Gareth A. 2008. Computer Models of Musical Creativity: Literary and Linguistic Computing. Literary and Linguistic Computing 23: 109–16. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Yee-King, Matthew, and Mark d’Inverno. 2016. Experience driven design of creative systems. Paper presented at 7th International Conference on Computational Creativity (ICCC 2016), Universite Pierre et Marie Curie, Paris, France, June 27–July 1. [Google Scholar]
- Zamborlin, Bruno, Frédéric Bevilacqua, Marco Gillies, and Mark d’Inverno. 2014. Fluid gesture interaction design applications of continuous recognition for the design of modern gestural interfaces. ACM Transactions on Interactive Intelligent Systems 3: 30–45. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
1 | From the abstract of his paper “Creative Thinking Processes: The Importance of Strategies and Expertise” given at the Southern Illinois Creativity Conference, 2018. |
© 2019 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Still, A.; d’Inverno, M. Can Machines Be Artists? A Deweyan Response in Theory and Practice. Arts 2019, 8, 36. https://doi.org/10.3390/arts8010036
Still A, d’Inverno M. Can Machines Be Artists? A Deweyan Response in Theory and Practice. Arts. 2019; 8(1):36. https://doi.org/10.3390/arts8010036
Chicago/Turabian StyleStill, Arthur, and Mark d’Inverno. 2019. "Can Machines Be Artists? A Deweyan Response in Theory and Practice" Arts 8, no. 1: 36. https://doi.org/10.3390/arts8010036
APA StyleStill, A., & d’Inverno, M. (2019). Can Machines Be Artists? A Deweyan Response in Theory and Practice. Arts, 8(1), 36. https://doi.org/10.3390/arts8010036