Physician Charity Care in America: Almost Always an Illusion, Ever More Commercial
Abstract
:As the stories we live by, myths are inescapable metaphors, and the most we can do is to choose which ones to honor, not to live without them in some Alpine air of cold, clear “reality”.[1]
1. Introduction
- “In St. Louis, Barnes-Jewish Hospital has started charging co-payments to insured patients, no matter how poor they are.”
- “Many hospitals appear focused on reducing aid only for patients who earn between 200 percent and 400 percent of the poverty level, or between $23,340 and $46,680 for an individual.”
- “[S]tarting this year, only patients below the poverty level will receive…charity care, said Paul Trainor, [Southern New Hampshire Medical Center system] vice president of finance.”
- Each physician has an obligation to share in providing care to the indigent. The measure of what constitutes an appropriate contribution may vary with circumstances such as community characteristics, geographic location, the nature of the physician’s practice and specialty, and other conditions. All physicians should work to ensure that the needs of the poor in their communities are met. Caring for the poor should be a regular part of the physician’s practice schedule.
- In the poorest communities, it may not be possible to meet the needs of the indigent for physicians’ services by relying solely on local physicians. The local physicians should be able to turn for assistance to their colleagues in prosperous communities, particularly those in close proximity. Physicians are meeting their obligation, and are encouraged to continue to do so, in a number of ways, such as seeing indigent patients in their offices at no cost or at reduced cost, serving at freestanding or hospital clinics that treat the poor, and participating in government programs that provide health care to the poor. Physicians can also volunteer their services at weekend clinics for the poor and at shelters for battered women or the homeless.
- In addition to meeting their obligation to care for the indigent, physicians can devote their energy, knowledge, and prestige to designing and lobbying at all levels for better programs to provide care for the poor [5].
2. History of the Physician Charity Care Obligation
…to an office of benevolence and charity…always most readily and cheerfully, when applied, to assist gratis, by all means in [their] power the distressed poor and indigent in our respective neighborhoods, who may have no legal means of maintenance from their county; but where such reasonable provision takes place, there [physicians] shall expect a reasonable award…[14].
3. Definitions of Charity Care
1. Provision of help or relief to the poor; almsgiving. 2. Something given to help the needy: alms. 3. An institution, an organization, or a fund established to help the needy. 4. Benevolence or generosity toward others or toward humanity…[19].
4. Rationale for Revisiting the Physician Charity Care Duty
- (1)
- As noted in the previous section, physicians usually charge all patients a fee for their services, and later forgive the debt for those who do not pay. The notion of “charity” therefore, seems questionable in degree and misleading. For Americans who grew up in small town America during the depression or even in the 1950s and 1960s, before the “system” transformation resulting from Medicare and Medicaid implementation, this debt-forgiveness model offered a means of support for many community professionals (such as physicians, lawyers, pharmacists, and dentists). One well-known example of this barter system arrangement is seen in Harper Lee’s To Kill a Mockingbird when farmer Walter Cunningham repays when he can attorney Atticus Finch for services rendered with crops from his farm [21]. As in the novel, Americans of that time lived sober lives of honesty, frugality, and self-reliance, with more community transparency. Physicians of the day were integral to the community and its survival and flourishing. However, this practice of providing services with some expectation of remuneration is probably not the charity care definition that the original provision framers like Rush, Bell, and Hays intended. And with successive revisions of the AMA Code of Ethics over the years, this fact must have been recognized and the language modified and tweaked to accommodate newer views. Even today, some physicians want to further commercialize the accepted definition by allowing tax credits for physician charity care [22]. They argue, quite persuasively, that they are entitled to the same tax breaks as hospitals and foundations that provide charity care. In considering this proposal, the American Medical Association Council on Medical Service opted to support the expansion of insurance coverage under the ACA instead of individual tax credits [23].
- (2)
- Over time, fewer and fewer physicians now honor the obligation to provide charity care to indigents. As the aspirational does not correspond with the norm, the provision appears no longer representative. This has been well documented by researchers familiar with physician practices overall and with specific specialties (such as surgery) [3,24]. The data have not been challenged. This discrepancy raises a related question: are ethical standards based on what doctors do, or on what they should do? Regardless, it becomes increasing more difficult to defend a professional norm as obligatory if fewer and fewer physicians over time are not meeting the standard [25].
- (3)
- Organized medicine lacks the tools and interest to enforce the professional standard. One is hard-pressed to find the record of a physician being disciplined by a professional association or by a board of medical examiners because he or she did not provide charity care. And again, if the standard must be continually enforced by peers to assure its compliance, the ethical obligation then appears more-and-more like a legal or quasi-legal standard rather than an ethical one motivated by charity and goodwill toward the needy.
- (4)
- It would be extremely awkward now—as it was in times past—for individual physicians to separate the “the poor, the destitute, the lowly, the worthy, and the unfortunate” from those that have resources but say they do not [26]. In other words, it is nearly impossible for individual practitioners to categorize true charity care patients from others who have the means to pay for their own health care. What is the reasonable threshold? Despite the efforts of one state medical association, which may hold to this view toward distinguishing real charity care cases, and offer guidance for means testing patients, the practical barriers are too high to sort out and police fairly [27].
- (5)
- As a result of dramatic changing practice patterns, physicians are not usually in the authority or executive positions to make decisions for the broader enterprise that may provide charity care to patients in some cases. Physicians are more frequently employees rather than independent private practitioners within large organizations. The shift toward integration of health care over time has complicated any physician provision on charity care. The 1847 AMA Code is grounded in the framework of individual physicians working in solo or small group private practices. It would have been difficult for Rush, Bell, and Hays to imagine physicians as employees of hospital networks, dependent on insurance companies for fee schedules and payments, or some version of government-provided universal health care. Until the second half of the Twentieth Century, medical options were more-or-less contained within a single practitioner who carried all he or she could offer around in a “black bag”. Today this is no longer the case. One might wonder if organized medicine waits too long to change some policy positions [28], whether it will appear out-of-touch and lose political clout by continuing to support untenable, even though aspirational, views. The present AMA Code of Medical Ethics should reflect current, normative practice standards.
- (6)
- In today’s world of modern medicine with specialization and its dependence on sophisticated diagnostic aids and expensive treatments, it would be very difficult—if not impossible—for a single physician or a group of private practice physicians to deliver the quality of care necessary in totality for most patients. Modern medicine, and the claims of patients for modern medicine, are much more complex than their historical counterparts. As a result, a single physician cannot provide comprehensive charity care in a simple, straightforward way. With this, one may be reminded of the phrase “O God, thy sea is so great, and my boat is so small” [29]. Only the federal government, with its influence and nationwide enforcement authority, could intervene to remedy the problems associated with assuring adequate care for all indigents and vulnerable in all states and jurisdictions [30]. One might note that the federal government has already recognized a responsibility to care for the poor with the enactment of Medicare and Medicaid. The public policy debate today is not really about the recognized authority or role as much as it is about how far the responsibility extends and its associated costs.
- (7)
- Under the federal Emergency Medical Treatment and Active Labor Act (EMTALA) and typical hospital medical staff bylaws, many physicians are under a legal or quasi-legal obligation to render care to patients in emergency departments. In this situation, any additional duty about charity care does not seem to make as much sense. EMTALA was enacted initially to deal with the “patient-dumping” problem that occurred when suburban hospitals transferred unstable, uninsured or indigent patients to inner city medical centers for additional care even though the transferring hospitals had the facilities and capabilities to meet patient needs [31]. The law created an unfunded mandate for hospitals with emergency departments if they have the wherewithal “capacity” and “capability” to serve unstable patients more locally, requiring them to absorb the associated expenses if the patient requires hospitalization and cannot be transferred to another facility. Hospitals share this burden with their credentialed providers—whether the hospitals’ physicians are employed or in private practice—since medical services may only be offered through physician staff members and associates. Moreover, the law extended an entitlement or “right” of sorts to some patients with emergencies who present at hospitals covered by the statute. Obligations exist because of the corresponding duties that are imposed on others to honor the rights [32]. Once an ethical responsibility is elevated to a legal right, as with EMTALA, hospitals and their physician staff are bound by law to meet the standard. Failure to meet EMTALA mandates carries severe legal penalties.
- (8)
- Any individual physician obligation ultimately involves unrealistic expectations. Even with the recent enactment and partial implementation of the 2010 ACA which was crafted to provide some form of health insurance protection to about 95% of Americans as designed, the number of remaining persons in the US who will be uninsured or under-insured will certainly overwhelm any informal physician charity care net. One only needs to cite the plight of the 5% of persons in America who would not be covered by some form of insurance or government plan—such as illegal immigrants—if the ACA were fully implemented to illustrate this point [33].
- (9)
- The charity care duty, in its current form, does not seem to fit with the liability concerns that have arisen under modern legal doctrines. Medical negligence and liability concerns that must be taken into consideration even though a physician may be providing care to a patient with no expectation of remuneration. Malpractice laws have created a safeguard for patients, and the poor should not be deprived of this protection. Some states, in an effort to encourage retired physicians who no longer carry malpractice insurance to practice in charity care clinics, have passed charitable immunity statutes specifically to protect these physicians from liability. This may be considered an extension of the states’ “Good Samaritan statutes” that provide immunity to physicians who stop at the scene of an accident to render emergency aid without the expectation of remuneration [34]. To treat poor and non-poor differently with respect to malpractice claims would have been discriminatory [35].
- (10)
- Increasing scarcity of physicians complicates charity care and makes provision of such care impossible. EMTALA and the expanded coverage under the ACA have given rise to concerns that the physician workforce truly is a scarce good. It has been theorized that there are not enough doctors now to tend to the sick and chronically ill that need services. Some say that with the ACA there will simply not be enough physicians—particularly primary care physicians—to meet patient needs that will have legitimate insurance or government health program claim for physician services [36]. Given labor constraints, there will not be a safety net of providers available to offer any charity care in off-hours.
5. The Dutch Approach
6. Conclusions and Recommendation
This declared indifference [toward slavery], but as I must think, covert real zeal for the spread of slavery, I can not but hate. I hate it because of the monstrous injustice of slavery itself. I hate it because it deprives our republican example of its just influence in the world—enables the enemies of free institutions, with plausibility, to taunt us as hypocrites—causes the real friends of freedom to doubt our sincerity, and especially because it forces so many really good men amongst ourselves into an open war with the very fundamental principles of civil liberty—criticizing the Declaration of Independence, and insisting that there is no real right principle of action but self-interest (emphasis original).[46]
[The physician] binds himself to competence as a moral obligation [and] places the well-being of those he presumes to help above his own personal gain. If these two considerations do not shape every medical act and every encounter with the patient, the profession becomes a lie: The physician is a fraud and his whole enterprise undiluted hypocrisy.[47]
Acknowledgments
Author Contributions
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Christopher A. Thomas. The Lincoln Memorial and American Life. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2002, p. xx. [Google Scholar]
- Abby Goodnough. “Hospitals Look to Health Law, Cutting Charity.” The New York Times, 25 May 2014, A1–A16. [Google Scholar]
- Peter J. Cunningham, and Jessica H. May. “A Growing Hole in the Safety Net: Physician Charity Care Declines Again (Tracking Report No. 13).” Center for Studying Health System Change. March 2006. Available online: http://www.hschange.com/CONTENT/826/ (accessed on 13 March 2014).
- American Medical Association. “Code of Medical Ethics. ” Available online: https://archive.org/details/63310410R.nlm.nih.gov (accessed on 25 May 2015).
- American Medical Association. “Opinion 9.065—Caring for the Poor.” June 1994. Available online: http://www.ama-assn.org/ama/pub/physician-resources/medical-ethics/code-medical-ethics/opinion9065.page (accessed on 13 March 2014).
- Robert Pear. “Rules Will Limit Tactics on Hospitals’ Fee Collection.” The New York Times, 11 January 2015, A10. [Google Scholar]
- Nina Bernstein. “Hospitals Flout Charity Aid Law.” The New York Times, 13 February 2012, A1–A16. [Google Scholar]
- Thomas Percival. Medical Ethics; Or, a Code of Institutes and Precepts, Adapted to the Professional Conduct of Physicians and Surgeons. Manchester: J. Johnson, 1803. [Google Scholar]
- Chauncery D. Leake. “Percival’s Medical Ethics: Promise and Problems.” Western Journal of Medicine 114 (1971): 68–70. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Robert B. Baker. “The American Bioethics Revolution.” In The American Medical Ethics Revolution: How the AMA’s Code of Ethics Has Transformed Physicians’ Relationship to Patients, Profession, and Society. Edited by Robert B. Baker, Arthur L. Caplan, Linda L. Emanuel and Stephen R. Latham. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Edmund D. Pellegrino. “Percival’s Medical Ethics: The Moral Philosophy of an 18th Century English Gentleman.” Archives of Internal Medicine 146 (1986): 2265–69. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Benjamin Rush. Sixteen Introductory Lectures to Courses of Lectures upon the Institutes and Practice of Medicine. Philadelphia: Bradford and Innskeep, 1811. [Google Scholar]
- Chester R. Burns. “Setting the Stage: Moral Philosophy, Benjamin Rush, and Medical Ethics in the United States Before 1846.” In The American Medical Ethics Revolution: How the AMA’s Code of Ethics Has Transformed Physicians’ Relationships to Patients, Professionals, and Society. Edited by Robert B. Baker, Arthur L. Caplan, Linda L. Emanuel and Stephen R. Latham. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1999, pp. 3–16. [Google Scholar]
- Robert B. Baker. Before Bioethics: A History of Medical Ethics from the Colonial Period to the Bioethics Revolution. New York: Oxford University Press, 2013, pp. 143–44. [Google Scholar]
- Maria-Florina Balcan, Avrim Blum, Hubert T-H. Chan, and Mohammad Taghi Hajiaghayi. “A Theory of Loss-Leaders: Making Money by Pricing Below Cost.” In WINE 2007. Edited by Xiaotie Deng and Fan Chung Graham. Berlin: Springer-Verlag, 2007, pp. 293–99. [Google Scholar]
- Rosemary Stevens. Sickness and in Wealth: American Hospitals in the Twentieth Century. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1989, p. 316. [Google Scholar]
- Parker v. Highland Park, 273 N.W.2d 413 (Michigan Supreme Court, 1978).
- Justin M. List. “Beyond Charity—Social Justice and Health Care.” Virtual Mentor 13 (2011): 565–68. [Google Scholar] [PubMed]
- Anonymous. The American Heritage Dictonary of the English Language, 3rd ed. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1992, p. 322. [Google Scholar]
- Erin M. McHugh. “The New EMTALA Regulations and the On-Call Physician Shortage: In Defense of the Regulation.” Journal of Health Law 37 (2004): 61–84. [Google Scholar] [PubMed]
- Harper Lee. To Kill a Mockingbird. Philadelphia: J.B. Lippincott Co., 1960. [Google Scholar]
- Texas Medical Association. “Tax Credits for Physician Charity Care: Background and Issues.” 2014. Available online: http://www.texmed.org/Template.aspx?id=3943 (accessed on 13 March 2014).
- Thomas E. Sullivan. “Physician Tax Credits for Uncompensated Care, Report of the Council on Medical Service.” American Medical Association. 1 February 2011. Available online: http://www.ama-assn.org/resources/doc/cms/i11-cms-report2.pdf (accessed on 13 March 2014).
- Caitlin Nelligan, Brad Wright, John Scarborough, Stephanie Poley, Elizabeth Walker, and Thomas Ricketts. “Charity Care Among Surgeons: Hours Provided Vary by Specialty and Practice Type.” Bulletin of the American College of Surgeons 95 (2010): 40–41. [Google Scholar] [PubMed]
- Edmund D. Pellegrino. “Toward a Virtue-Based Normative Ethics for the Health Professions.” Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 5 (1995): 253–77. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Meriam B. Gerstein. “Resolutions Adopted at the Meeting of the Boston Medical Society, Dec. 18, 1897.” Journal of the American Medical Association 30 (1898): 47. [Google Scholar]
- Texas Medical Association. “Draft Office Policy—Charity Care.” Texas Medical Association. 1 July 2007. Available online: http://www.texmed.org/WorkArea/DownloadAsset.aspx?id=19819 (accessed on 13 March 2014).
- Elizabeth Rosenthal. “Many Doctors Shift to Jobs with Salaries.” The New York Times, 14 February 2014, A15–17. [Google Scholar]
- Anonymous. Breton Fisherman’s Prayer Plaque. Boston: John F. Kennedy Presidential Library and Museum, 1963. [Google Scholar]
- Mark A. Levine, Matthew K. Wynia, Paul M. Schyve, John R. Teagardan, David A. Fleming, Sharaon King Donohue, Ron J. Anderson, James Sabin, and Ezakiel J. Emanuel. “Improving Access to Health Care: A Consensus Ethical Framework to Guide Proposals for Reform.” Hastings Center Report 37 (2007): 14–19. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Tiana M. Lee. “An EMTALA Primer: The Impact of Changes in the Emergency Medicine Landscape on EMTALA Compliance and Enforcement.” Annals of Health Law 13 (2004): 145–78. [Google Scholar] [PubMed]
- David Bruce Ingram, and Jennifer A. Parks. Understanding Ethics. Indianapolis: Alpha Books, 2002, p. 255. [Google Scholar]
- Deborah Sontag. “Deported in a Coma, Saved Back in the U.S.” The New York Times, 9 November 2008, A1–A16. [Google Scholar]
- Howard B. Shapiro. “Providing Charity Care: A Primer on Liability Risk.” Family Practice Management 10 (2003): 52–53. [Google Scholar]
- Clarke C. Havinghurst. Health Care Law and Policy: Readings, Notes, and Questions. Mineola: The Foundation Press, Inc., 1988, p. 581. [Google Scholar]
- Abby Goodnough. “Medicaid Growth Could Aggravate Doctor Shortage.” The New York Times, 29 November 2013, A1–A17. [Google Scholar]
- Jonathan Cohn. “Lessons from abroad: The Dutch Health Care System, Part I.” 6 October 2011. Available online: http://commonwealthfund.org/Blog/2011/Oct/Lessons-from-Abroad.aspx (accessed on 13 March 2014).
- Sarah Thomson, Robin Osborn, and Sarah Jane Reed. “International Profiles of Heath Care Systems, 2011.” The Commonwealth Fund. 10 November 2011. Available online: http://www.commonwealthfund.org/~/media/Files/Publications/Fund%20Report/2011/Nov/1562_Squires_Intl_Profiles_2011_11_10.pdf (accessed on 13 March 2014).
- Bradford H. Gray, and Ewout van Ginneken. “Health Care for Undocumented Migrants: European Approaches.” The Commonwealth Fund. 6 December 2012. Available online: http://www.commonwealthfund.org/~/media/Files/Publications/Issue%20Brief/2012/Dec/1650_Gray_hlt_care_undocumented_migrants_intl_brief.pdf (accessed on 13 March 2014).
- Truus Veenema, Trees Wiegers, and Walter Deville. Toegankelijkheid van de Gezondheidszorg voor "illegalen" in Nederland: Een Update. Utrecht: NIVEL, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Anonymous. “Hoogervorst: Arts Kan Rekening Onverzekerde Betalen.” Medisch Contact. 2006. Available online: http://medischcontact.artsennet.nl/actueel/nieuws/nieuwsartikel/15480/hoogervorst-arts-kan-rekening-onverzekerde-betalen.htm (accessed on 13 March 2014).
- Martin Buijsen. “Het niewe zorgstelsel en het recht op gzondheid. Naar meer ongelijkheid en uitsluiting? ” Mensenrechten & Gezondheidszorg. 2008. Available online: http://repub.eur.nl/pub/23564 (accessed on 13 March 2014).
- American Medical Association. “Opinion 2.095—The Provision of Adequate Care.” June 1994. Available online: http://www.ama-assn.org/ama/pub/physician-resources/medical-ethics/code-medical-ethics/opinion2095.page (accessed on 13 March 2014).
- Bob Mank. “AMA Backs Hot-Button Health Insurance Mandate.” CBS News. 21 June 2011. Available online: http://www.cbsnews.com/news/ama-backs-hot-button-health-insurance-mandate/ (accessed on 13 March 2014).
- Richard Kronick. “Valuing Charity.” Journal of Health Politics, Policy, and Law 26 (2001): 993–1001. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mario M. Cuomo, and Harold Holzer. Lincoln on Democrary. New York: HarperCollins, 1990, p. 67. [Google Scholar]
- Elizabeth Langer. “Edmund D. Pellegrino, Preeminent Bioethicist, Dies at 92.” The Washington Post. 19 June 2013. Available online: http://www.washingtonpost.com/local/obituaries/edmund-d-pellegrino-preeminent-bioethicist-dies-at-92/2013/06/19/34a3e97a-d82f-11e2-9df4-895344c13c30_story.html (accessed on 13 March 2014).
- Eileen Salinsky. “Necessary But Not Sufficient? Physician Volunteerism and the Health Care Safety Net (NHPF Background Paper).” National Health Policy Forum. 4 March 2004. Available online: http://www.nhpf.org/library/background-papers/BP_PhysicianVolunteerism_3-04.pdf (accessed on 13 March 2014).
- Leiyu Shi, and Douglas A. Singh. Essentials of the U.S. Health Care System, 3rd ed. Burlington: Jones & Bartlett Learning, 2013, pp. 39–43. [Google Scholar]
© 2015 by the authors; licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
White, B.D.; Eijkholt, M. Physician Charity Care in America: Almost Always an Illusion, Ever More Commercial. Laws 2015, 4, 201-215. https://doi.org/10.3390/laws4020201
White BD, Eijkholt M. Physician Charity Care in America: Almost Always an Illusion, Ever More Commercial. Laws. 2015; 4(2):201-215. https://doi.org/10.3390/laws4020201
Chicago/Turabian StyleWhite, Bruce D., and Marleen Eijkholt. 2015. "Physician Charity Care in America: Almost Always an Illusion, Ever More Commercial" Laws 4, no. 2: 201-215. https://doi.org/10.3390/laws4020201
APA StyleWhite, B. D., & Eijkholt, M. (2015). Physician Charity Care in America: Almost Always an Illusion, Ever More Commercial. Laws, 4(2), 201-215. https://doi.org/10.3390/laws4020201