1. Introduction
Political neoliberalism, which arrived in the West in the late 1970s and has picked up speed and spread since the demise of communism a decade later, has broken apart the post-WWII “shotgun marriage” [
1] between capitalism and democracy, in favor of a capitalism largely released of democratic constraints. Accordingly, the friendliest reading of contemporary populism is to resurrect democracy, which has been badly battered under neoliberal rule. In one such reading, which however does not specify the neoliberal context, “populisms have a legitimate place in liberal and social democracies. One could even say that they are inevitable given the likelihood of entropy inherent in these regimes” [
2] (p. 80). The plural form in this formulation points to the variety of populisms in past and present. A classic discussion even wondered whether populism is a “unitary concept” or “simply a word wrongly used in completely heterogeneous contexts”, in effect leaning toward the latter [
3] (p. 3).
The least to agree on is that there are left- and right-wing forms of populism—which still leaves “populism” itself undefined. Various alternatives are on offer. Some argue that populism is “ideology” [
4], others that it is political “strategy” [
5], and a third group that it is rhetoric or “style” [
6]. In the canonical definition by Cas Mudde, populism is a “thin-centered ideology”, in which a “pure people” opposes a “corrupt elite” and favors a politics that is “expression of the
volonté générale (general will) of the people” [
4] (p. 543). This implies that, qua “thin-centered”, the populist ideology needs to be complemented by something thicker, most often nationalism, but also socialism. Without this complement, the right/left distinction could not be made.
A critic of the “myth of global populism”, who otherwise prefers a more differentiated vocabulary for the “disparate phenomena” packed under it, is still convinced that Mudde’s definition “cannot (be) improve(d) upon” [
7] (pp. 1, 10). This is also my point of departure. The normatively loaded people/elite dichotomy is the minimal content of all known expressions of populism, left and right, in past and present. Rivalling approaches, for whom populism is more form than content, cannot do without this minimal ideational input, and they are in this sense derivative. After all, the root word of populism is the Latin
populus, the people (
demos in Greek), who nominally rule in a democracy. Populism is nothing less than “a shadow cast by democracy itself”, as Margaret Canovan [
8] argued, articulating democracy’s “redemptive” face that mostly remains hidden behind its “pragmatic” realities.
The populism to be examined in this paper is the one that had its apex in the
annus horribilis, 2016, marked by the double shock of the Brexit referendum that led the UK to leave the European Union, and the victory of Donald Trump in the US presidential elections later that year. Both events have been widely interpreted as the breakthrough of populism in the West, and of a populism that is distinctly right-wing and nationalist, and in the Trumpist version at least toxic to democracy [
9]. It is true, the Brexit and Trump upheavals, when looked at closely, feed on widely different sources, including a chronic unhappiness about Europe in the UK and a diminishing white majority in the US. However, a conspicuous commonality of both is that they happened in the two Anglo-Saxon pioneer countries of neoliberalism, where the latter has also gone to bigger extremes than elsewhere. Promptly, the Brexit/Trump tandem has been taken by many as expression of a deep crisis, if not the end, of liberalism and the liberal order, both domestically and internationally [
10,
11,
12,
13].
Much of this crisis talk has been hyperbole. The populist juggernaut tottered as early as 2017, when Brexit and Trump were not followed by populist victories in the Netherlands and France, contrary to what many had feared. Post-Brexit Britain likes to fashion itself as “truly Global”
1, and Trump went down in 2020 (if narrowly). In Europe, with the exception of Italy where populists have governed twice since 2018, populism-in-power is mainly limited to its eastern half, where the late arrival of liberal democracy post-1989 made these societies extra-vulnerable to illiberal challenges
2. A recent study of “right-wing populist parties” in 16 European countries, west
and east, found an average vote share of just 16 percent in 2021, up from 12.6 percent in 2001 [
14] (p. 13, fn. 22). This is significant but hardly ground for alarm. Most importantly, Larry Bartels attributes this moderate growth “not to increased demand for right-wing populism among ordinary Europeans, but to the increased ability and willingness of populist entrepreneurs to mobilize and cater to that demand” [
14] (p. 150). Judged by their (often inept) leadership, these parties are limited by a “clown ceiling”, with “a rapid ascent, a noisy thud against the ceiling and a swift retreat”
3.
The populist right still represents the “single most successful” new political party family in post-war Europe [
16] (p. 12). Its gradual ascent coincides with the rise of political neoliberalism since the 1980s, while gaining momentum with the onset of globalization post-1989. Pace Brubaker [
17] (p. 357), populism seems to be not just a “moment” but a permanent feature of the neoliberal order. The populism-neoliberalism connection thus requires a closer examination.
While there has been left-wing populism after the 2008 Financial Crisis in the south of Europe and in the US, the right-wing variant has been predominant in the rest of Europe and in the US as well. This fact tells us something important about the neoliberal context in which this populism arises. Considering that populism is inherently counter-establishment and counter-elite, while claiming to bring back-in the neglected people element, a populism that is on the political right
must visualize its opponent in leftist colors. This attests to a shift of political neoliberalism, from being dominated by the right, as under Thatcher and Reagan in the early 1980s, to being dominated by the left—a left that has reformed itself as the “Third Way”, from Clinton and Blair in the 1990s on. In Gary Gerstle’s [
18] seminal account of neoliberalism’s “rise and fall” in the United States, neoliberalism matures from “movement” into “political order” precisely once the left has agreed to its principles. This is a first answer to the question, to be further pursued below, why populism in a neoliberal context is mainly of the political right. In one account [
19] (p. 418), the populist right is entirely a response to “phase two” leftist neoliberalism, which consists of “neoliberal social policies based on the recognition of the rights of women, minorities, migrants and the poor”.
This suggests a change in the meaning of right, which had already greatly fluctuated since its first appearance in the French Revolution [
20]. At its earliest, “right” was simply a spatial notion for the monarchic forces seated on the right side of the new Republican parliament. With the rise and consolidation of capitalism, right became the name of its defenders against the socialist critics, and it has never lost this association—the continuity being that right is always conservative. Accordingly, the earliest incarnation of many populist right parties in Europe was as free market musketeers against bureaucratically bloated states (see the pioneering study by Hans-Georg Betz [
21]). Another early analysis of these parties identified as their “winning formula” the combination of “free market” and “authoritarian” orientations. It tellingly labelled the result “right-authoritarian”, the “right” standing for “neoliberal economic policies”, while “authoritarian” referred to “nationalist, particularist sociocultural policies” [
22] (p. 275).
Today we are used to considering populism and neoliberalism as natural antagonists. However, this was not so initially. Some even attached the adjective “populist” to neoliberalism’s earliest political mainstream articulations in the West. Stuart Hall [
23] famously did this for Thatcher, calling her brand of politics “authoritarian populism”. One can drive this to the point that neoliberal doctrine itself bears populist possibilities. An example is Milton Friedman’s self-fashioning as “leading a revolt of the poor against the rich” and defending the cause of “the ordinary worker and the ordinary consumer”, who for Friedman were the true winners of “less government” [
24] (pp. 71, 78).
Over time, the populist right shed its neoliberal roots and embraced “centrist economic” [
25] (p. 411) and pro-welfare positions, yet only for natives—so-called “welfare chauvinism” [
26]. This was a strategic choice, to cater to the working-class defectors of leftist parties that had adopted Third-Way neoliberalism. In the process, right-wing populist parties became “a new type of working-class party” [
27] (p. 350). Daniel Oesch found that the support for these parties by “production workers” exceeded their average support by a factor of 1.3 in Switzerland, 1.4 in France, 1.6 in Austria, 1.7 in Belgium, and 1.9 in Norway [
27] (p. 356). At the same time, he found that the main concern of working-class voters was not with “economic grievances” but with “questions of community and identity”, especially surrounding immigration, opposition to which became their preferred parties’ signature as well [
27] (p. 349). Colin Crouch [
28] (p. 97) has a simple explanation for the relative absence of economic concerns in the populist right: “Since by definition the political right is anti-egalitarian, rightist populism has to define its enemies in terms other than wealth and power”. To avoid the apparent circularity, we need to place the populist right in the larger context of political and social transformation
4.
This is what I try to do in this paper. In the next section, I argue that the “right” element of populist right becomes especially plausible in the light of cleavage theory in the Lipset–Rokkan tradition (2). I then return to the “populist” element in right-wing populism, which is the advocacy of illiberal democracy (3). I argue that this is not a solution to neoliberalism’s chronic democracy deficit but, on the contrary, further aggravates it. Having clarified the meaning of right and of populist in populist right, the main part of the paper tackles the crucial relationship between economic and cultural factors in explaining its rise
5. The economic backdrop of populism is massively increased inequality and economic insecurity as a result of neoliberal globalization, and the concomitant decline of the middle class, especially its lower segment (4). However, less economic stress than cultural change, in particular that brought by immigration and cosmopolitanism, has set the agenda of the populist right (5). I map the ethnic nationalism that drives the populist right, but show, along the example of welfare chauvinism, that it has had only limited policy impact.
The spirit of this paper is synthetic, to distillate out of a multitude of sector- and area-specific but also broadly comparative political science and sociological analyses, most of them Large-N and quantitative, a holistic picture of populism in the Western neoliberal order, which is at the same time attentive to the complexity of its causes and expressions.
2. Cleavage Theory
Why is the populist right “right”? While we already argued that the neoliberal context is key to an answer, considering two rounds of change that helped establish this context, sheds further light on this. The first round of change actually preceded the rise of neoliberalism. For the generation growing up in the late 1960s to 1970s, especially its more affluent parts, Ronald Inglehart [
31] diagnosed a “silent revolution” in the personal values held by its young members, from “materialist” to “post-materialist”. The political expression was the new social movements and green parties of the 1970s and 1980s. In return, one can look at the emergent populist
right as a late “silent counter-revolution” [
32] on that same new values dimension, which is more about cultural than economic issues, a right that sought a “non-materialistic answer” to the leftist agenda of the “New Politics” [
32] (p. 19). This was a “late” counter-revolution because it kicked in only once the materialists saw their size and numbers dwindling due to generational change. Accordingly, the shrinking and aging materialists responded to the New Politics of the left with a rightist program of “law and order enforcement” and “immigration control” [
32] (p. 25).
The concern about “immigration control” fully materialized only in a second round of change, which was brought by post-1980s globalization. Qua signifying a “denationalization”, that is, a set of border- and boundary-transcending and -relativizing movements, globalization has fundamentally transformed the national political space. It has divided “winners” and “losers” on a new “integration-demarcation” cleavage that is superimposed on the established left-right cleavage [
33]. Martin Lipset and Stein Rokkan [
34] had argued that mid-20th century European party systems were the “frozen” product of the two late-19th to early-20th century national and industrial revolutions, generating four cleavages: center/periphery and state/church as a result of the national revolution; and rural/urban and capital/labor as result of the industrial revolution. In principle, political party formation
could have revolved around all four cleavages and their corresponding interests and identities, depending on the circumstances. In reality, the two cleavages connected to the national revolution, which in some places were expressed in oppositional territorial and religious identities, cooled down, at least in most places. This left only the capital/labor cleavage as the fulcrum of party formation and political conflict (landed interests, and thus the rural/urban cleavage, disappeared with the shrinking of the agrarian sector). This is the origin of the economic left-right distinction in politics as we knew it—until the arrival of neoliberalism. Prior to this arrival, the left stood for social protection and market regulation, and the right for competition and free markets. Globalization, which is but the spatial expression of neoliberalism, amounts to a reopening of the national cleavage type, which is in essence cultural and identity-related.
The globalization-focused update to Lipset-Rokkan’s cleavage theory, by Hanspeter Kriesi et al. [
33], refutes a widespread view that globalization has “added” a new dimension to political space (most recently [
35] (p. 79))
6. Instead, they argue, correctly in my view, that political space
always was two-dimensional, economic and cultural, at least if one follows the Lipset–Rokkan model (which has no real competitor for explaining long-term party-system change). Globalization’s new cleavage, which divides the proponents of (international) “integration” from the partisans of (national) “demarcation”, is thus not added to but “embedded” into the pre-existing two-dimensional basic structure. Because its cultural dimension was already reshaped by the value changes brought by the post-materialist “silent revolution” and its new social movements, globalization amounted to “transforming it
once again” [
33] (p. 13; emphasis supplied). This means that the previously intra-domestic defense of traditional values, mostly around moral and lifestyle issues, turned ethnic and nationalist, bringing to full bloom the combination of opposition to the European Union and to immigration that is the trademark of today’s populist right in Europe [
36] (pp. 977–978, 983).
Importantly, the mainstream (conservative vs. social democratic) political parties, which once had taken opposite positions on the economic left/right cleavage, have come to “view…economic denationalization both as inevitable and beneficial”, and thus they “converged on moderately pro-integration positions” [
33] (pp. 15–16). This alludes to the Third Way transformation of the left and its adoption of neoliberalism. In principle, the all-party neoliberal consensus could have provided an opening for a new opposition force with a strong economic focus on redistribution. However, this did not happen
7.
Instead, the action has all been on the cultural front, where the “driving force” is the new populist right parties assembling the “losers” of globalization [
33] (p. 19). Their focus on culture, while downplaying the fact that “losing” from globalization has a very material meaning (see
Section 4), is not accidental. This is because the new “integration-demarcation” cleavage, “transnational” in brief [
37], is “at its core a cultural conflict”, pitting “libertarian, universalistic values against the defense of nationalism and particularism” [
37] (p. 123). Liesbet Hooghe and Gary Marx point out that this new cleavage has “greater salience” [
37] (p. 127) for new parties that are undivided on its issues and thus take more extreme positions on them. These are, next to the populist right parties, green and new left parties on the other end of the political spectrum. By contrast, mainstream parties face internal division in this respect: conservative parties are globalist in economic but not cultural respect, and vice versa for (traditional) social democrats, who are culturally liberal but economically pro-statist and welfarist. Accordingly, the result of globalization is the fragmentation of (non-majoritarian) party systems in Europe, due to the arrival of new parties on the new cleavage axis. This fragmentation shows in the fact that the average voting share of the three traditional party families: social democratic, conservative, and liberal, has steadily decreased, from 75 percent in 2000 to 64 percent in 2017 [
37] (p. 127), and the trend continues.
3. Illiberal Democracy
In its 2016 program, the populist
Alternative für Deutschland (AfD) presented itself as a party of “liberals and conservatives”, “free citizens of our country”, and “convinced democrats” [
38] (preamble). The AfD wants to be “an alternative to what the political class believes it can impose on us as ‘without alternative’ (
alternativlos)”. It opposes the “political class of professional politicians”, which primarily cares about itself and constitutes a “political cartel” [
38] (p. 8). Only the “state people” (
Staatsvolk) of the Federal Republic could “put an end to this illegitimate situation”.
This AfD statement not only confirms Cas Mudde’s [
4] “ideational” definition of populism, that is, the pure people/corrupt elite binary. It also replicates, down to the word, Richard Katz and Peter Mair’s [
39] “cartel party” theory, which argues that parties no longer represent civil society but have become colluding and self-serving parts of the state apparatus. Confirming its neoliberal roots that would be shortly shed in favor of
völkisch nationalism, the 2016 AfD program curiously favors the privatization of state institutions [
38] (p. 9), and even makes a brainy reference to Friedrich Hayek’s views on the imperfectability of human knowledge and political action [
38] (p. 10). Apart from these neoliberal vestiges, the critique of an atrophied political process dominated by a “small and powerful political clique within the parties” [
38] (p. 8) closely resembles leading academic critiques, not only of “cartel party” but also of “post-democracy” [
28]. In this vein, Takis Pappas [
40] understands populism entirely as endogenous response to a “democratic representation crisis” [
40] (p. 124), or to “liberal decay” [
40] (p. 262), which is likewise not far from the AfD’s 2016 views: “Increased bureaucratization and institutional rigidity in politics, the recycling of political elites and the rise of technocracy, the entrenchment of interest groups, the lack of transparency, widespread corruption, and spreading cynicism” [
40] (p. 262). This is what populists rail against, in their own as much as in the views of their scholarly observers.
However, Pappas [
40] (p. 190) also concludes, on the basis of in-depth case studies of populists in power, that “in the long run and almost without fail, populism is calamitous for liberal democracy”: “It decimates old established institutions, generates intense social polarization, and produces economic and political crisis; sometimes, it even morphs into autocracy”. In line with most recent key contributions [
4,
41,
42,
43,
44,
45], Pappas argues that populism, while “always democratic” (which distinguishes it from fascism or communism), is “never liberal” [
40] (p. 35). In short, populism is “democratic illiberalism” [
40] (p. 33). Merely inverting the words, Mudde [
4] (p. 561) speaks of “illiberal democracy”, because populism “rejects all limitations on the expression of the general will, most notably the constitutional protection of minorities and the independence…of key state institutions”.
In particular, pluralism and constitutionalism, and thus the two pillars of the “liberal” in liberal democracy, meet the ire of populists. Pluralism is repudiated because it dilutes the direct and unmediated expression of the general will, which is a dangerous hoax to pluralists; constitutionalism is not liked because it puts a brake on the general will’s real-world approximation, the majority will. Opinions are divided on whether democracy minus the liberal element is still democracy. On the yes-side is Yascha Mounk [
43] (ch. 1), who finds “democratic energy” in populism. To Mounk, this makes its contemporary incarnations distinct from “older far-right movements”: “today’s populists claim…to deepen the democratic elements of our current system. That matters”. On the no-side, Jan-Werner Müller argues, convincingly in my view, that “democracy can only exist on a liberal basis” (quoted in [
46] (p. 263)). This is because without pluralism and constitutionalism, the “institutionalized uncertainty” that “real democracy” requires cannot be obtained [
47] (p. 71). From this follows that “illiberal democracy” is an oxymoron.
Populism fails the democratic test because it is not what it claims to be, a return to the classic idea of direct democracy. Instead, populism is a “new form of representative government, but a disfigured one”, one that entails “direct representation” [
44] (p. 4). Nadia Urbinati’s characterization of populism as “direct representation” is a deliberate contradiction in terms, to capture the fact that populism requires a leader and thus is itself a “representative form of politics” [
44] (p. 115). However, it is a peculiar form of representation, not “mandate representation” as in party government, which is replaceable; instead, it is “representation as embodiment”, which is not replaceable. This “creates an irresponsible leader”, and “jeopardizes pluralism by principle” [
44] (p. 116). Moreover, true representative democracy is “diarchic”, consisting not just of “will” (expressed in elections and decision-making) but also of “opinion” (the pluralist element), both “remain(ing) independent” [
44] (p. 7). Populist direct representation tilts the pluralist element. The result is “illiberal democracy”, which is “not democracy at all” [
44] (p. 10). The populist leader faces the dilemma that he (it is rarely a she) “must become an insider”, if he succeeds, “without ever appearing to be one” [
44] (p. 156). This is why populists in power are in permanent campaign mode (as one knows from Donald Trump, 2017–2021): they “must be able to collapse the difference between movement and power, and between inside and outside” [
44] (p. 156).
Nadia Urbinati’s convincing case for populism as threat to democracy is on the assumption that populism is less “ideology and style” than “strategic movement to remake political authority” [
45] (p. 115). Such populism thus requires to be in power for releasing its poisonous quality. However, Urbinati also makes a compelling argument why already qua “ideology and style”, populism cannot be the fix to democracy’s deficits that it claims to be. This is because its claim to represent the “people” as a whole is false to begin with, and thus the claim to express the “general will”. In reality, populism “is a phenomenology that involves replacing the whole with one of its parts” [
44] (p. 13). This is also entailed by but not reflected in Mudde’s pure-people/corrupt-elite binary [
4]. In populist imaginary, the people are always qualified by an adjective: “pure”, “real”
8, etc. But this makes them less than the whole, already because the elite is not included (who, technically speaking, must be part of the people, unless it is imagined as of foreign origins). Even more clearly in form of the majority, typically the silent one that populists claim to be or speak for, “the part erases the whole and makes politics a question of partiality” [
44] (p. 37).
In a nutshell, real-existing populism means factionalism and polarization. Of course, representative democracy, in its classic party government form, also implies the majority principle. Nevertheless, its logic is
pars pro toto, the assumption being that who constitutes the majority can—even must—change over time. By contrast, in populism, the logic shifts to
pars pro parte [
44] (p. 15), the majority being fixed and always the same. As a result, the “majority principle” morphs into “majority rule”, or from “procedure” into “a force” [
44] (p.95). Populism rests on a “possessive conception of politics”, as Urbinati puts it to the point [
44] (p. 14). It seeks a “regime of rather than by the majority” [
45] (p. 123).
Another way of putting the matter is that populist politics is “like a war rather than a game, a matter of winners and losers, with no fiction of universalism” [
44] (p. 192). Reviewing the “grand dichotomy of the 20th century”, which is the left-right division that has structured this century’s politics, Steven Lukes [
49] notes that this dichotomy embodies the “principle of parity”. According to it, “political alternatives are legitimately equal contenders” [
49] (pp. 606–607). The arrival of identity politics, in which the opponent is demonized as illegitimate and to be overcome or even erased, and of which right-wing populism is only one variant, falls short of Lukes’ parity principle. This is why populism “cannot answer the problems that populists are reacting against” [
44] (p. 207).
5. Cultural Deflection
The notion of cultural deflection addresses the crucial fact that the economic root causes of populism, identified here as inequality and middle-class decline, find little direct expression in the preferences and programs of the populist right, which nevertheless is the main electoral haven for the losers of these processes. What Cas Mudde stated in 2007: that “the economic program is a secondary feature in the ideologies of populist right parties” [
78] (p. 119), and “also secondary to their electorates” [
78] (p. 120), remains true today [
48].
The “economics versus culture question” [
68] in the explanation of the populist right requires a composite answer, one that eschews a simplistic either-or as much as settling on only
one mechanism when combining the two. A strikingly simple bridge from economic root causes to cultural deflection builds on the fact that populist right parties draw support from two rather heterogeneous occupational groups, “blue-collar workers” and “owners of small businesses” [
79]. Their economic interests are diametrically opposed, pro-state-interventionist the workers’ and anti-interventionist the small owners’. This raises the paradox that the two groups that give “disproportionate” support to the populist right are also the ones that are “the most divided” on economic issues [
79] (p. 489). Hence, as Elisabeth Ivarsflaten showed along detailed case studies of the French Front National and the Danish People’s Party, the need to bridge the economic differences by “issues cross-cutting the economic dimension” [
79] (p. 471): restricted immigration, law and order, EU skepticism, anti-corruption, in sum, the cultural “position” and political “valence” issues that populist right parties hold in ample storage. However, this political supply-side explanation dodges the question why these (and not other) non-economic issues could arise in the first, and why they should appeal precisely to these groups. For this, we need something akin to the cleavage theory discussed earlier.
Starting with the plausible assumption that “globalization shocks” are driving the rise of the populist right, Dani Rodrik [
68] has laid out a “conceptual framework” of the multiple channels through which these shocks (that he further differentiates into trade, immigration, and finance shocks) help amass populist votes. In this framework, culture is “an intermediate variable rather than the ultimate driver”, merely “amplifying the political effects of globalization shocks” [
68] (p. 135). That means, there
is the possibility of the “economic dislocations” brought by globalization shocks
directly shaping “individual policy preferences” on the demand-side, or “party programs” on the supply-side,
without the detour of culture. However, this would amount to the leftist class voting and the class politics that has taken a nosedive under neoliberalism, and that only in some places (and limited times) has found a left-populist successor. Instead, the more likely causal paths are indirect, working through the variable set of “culture, racial attitudes, social identity” [
68] (p. 140). This may again happen on either the political demand or supply side, the culture set directly shaping individual voting preferences, or these preferences being indirectly elicited by party programs that first adopted the culture set. The two culture-mediated paths are the more likely today, as the fortunes and agendas of the populist right attest to. Overall, Rodrik’s “conceptual framework” suggests that a “comprehensive analysis” needs to reckon with four causal channels for globalization to fuel populism, two each on the demand- and supply-side of politics
19. Needless to say, this is a “tall order” that no single analysis has as yet pulled off [
68] (p. 141). However, despite the complexity, Rodrik offers a simple reason, equally working for the supply
and demand sides of politics, why the globalization backlash has taken the “right-wing, nativist form” that works through culture. This is because globalization by definition generates “outsider targets”: “foreign exporters, culturally different workers, international banks”. As a result, economic distress is “recast as threats on the dominant group’s traditional way of life, deepening the divide between ‘us’ and ‘them’” [
68] (p. 162).
Both Ivarsflaten [
79] and Rodrik [
68], in different ways, operate with the assumption of cultural deflection, and of a propensity of the political right to engage in it. There are historical precedents for this. Daniel Ziblatt [
81] (p. 34) has addressed the “conservative dilemma” in the making of 19th century European democracies, which is that playing “the numbers game” to win elections required compromising their “inegalitarian and hierarchical views”. The solution was to “find and exploit issues that cross-cut and diminish the impact of social class as an electoral cleavage, supplanting it with issues such as nationalism, religion, and patriotism” [
81] (p. 49). A contemporary variant is the US Republican Party, which already before Donald Trump had mobilized white identity to defend wealth inequality [
82] (see also [
83]; a cross-national confirmation of the Ziblatt thesis is [
84]).
5.1. Ethnic Nationalism
What makes the populist right “right” is a “specific form of nationalism”, which Cas Mudde called “nativism”: “an ideology, which holds that states should be inhabited exclusively by members of the native group” [
78] (p. 19). Nativism is another word for ethnic nationalism, which is usually distinguished from civic or liberal nationalism.
To the limited degree that an intellectual doctrine can be attributed to the ethnic nationalism that circulates in the populist right, it is “ethnopluralism”. Developed by the French
Nouvelle Droite, in particular Alain de Benoist, ethnopluralism has been influential for the French Front National and other populist right parties in Europe [
85] (pp. 3–4)
20. Much as these parties are located on a new cleavage axis, New Right thinking also has been a response to a prior multiculturalism, which in France has figured as the “right to difference” (
droit à la différence) on the part of minorities. Now the right to difference is claimed on behalf of the majority. “What is good for the Bororos or the Guayaquis, should be no less good for us”: “the right of peoples to be themselves” [
87] (p. 103). De Benoist, chief thinker of the
Nouvelle Droite, calls this borrowing from multiculturalism “mutual decolonization”, in which “White Power” is the logical progression from “Black Power”. At the same time, “racism” is nominally rejected: “I am for non-discrimination, for de-colonization, for the self-determination of peoples” [
87] (p. 102). Unlike classical racism, which was hierarchical, the novelty of ethnopluralism is to be horizontal. It stipulates the “equal value of homogenous peoples in their native territories” (De Benoist, quoted in [
88] (ch. 1)). Indeed, a manifesto entitled
The French New Right in the Year 2000 [
89], is often indistinguishable from leftist multiculturalism—
Telos, where it was published, incidentally was one of the left’s intellectual strongholds in the 1980s. This manifesto identifies the “true wealth of the world” in “the diversity of its cultures and peoples” [
89] (p. 11, typescript). And it opposes the “homogenizing universalism” of the West that it sees embodied in liberalism, consequently dubbed “the main enemy” [
89] (p. 3). The French New Right is even depicted in this manifesto as allied with the “peoples struggling against Western imperialism” and against “racism”, in a posture self-described as “differentialist anti-racism” [
89] (p. 13). Already long before this striking document, Pierre-André Taguieff had mocked the “third-worldism of the right”, calling De Benoist, the 2000 manifesto`s main author, “one of the last French leftists” [
86] (p. 21).
However, the unmistakable dividing line between left and right is the right’s instinctual endorsement of inequality and hierarchy as natural and ineradicable features of human society. As this has been a definitional element of the right since its birth post-1789 [
20], it must be a defining feature of the New Right as well. The rub is that positively valued inequality and hierarchy are not easily matched with the “pluralism” element in ethnopluralism, which the latter borrows from multiculturalism and which suggests symmetry and equality. Accordingly, classic racism slips back in
21. It is barely suppressed in the claim that “all races are superior”, and that “all races have their own genius” [
87] (p. 85). It is out in the open when “racial differences in intelligence (IQ)…cannot be denied”, and when De Benoist oddly distinguishes the “intuitive reasoning” of “blacks” from the “discursive reasoning” of non-blacks [
87] (p. 97).
Most importantly, ethnopluralism rejects the mixing of races and peoples. Each is to stick to their “own” territory without interference by the others. Next to the endorsement of inequality and hierarchy, the rejection of mixing is a second feature of classic racism that pops up in the New Right. From the rejection of mixing follows a principled rejection of immigration, which can only lead to “discrimination, segregation, the loss of culture, and crime” [
87] (p. 99). The rejection of immigration, and this for primarily cultural reasons, is the perhaps strongest communality between New Right ethnopluralism and the agenda of populist right parties, which have been found “unite(d)” in their opposition to immigration [
90] (p. 3).
Central to New Right thinking is the frontal opposition to liberalism (as well as to Christianity, as its historical roots). This replaced an earlier anti-communist stance, which has become anachronistic post-1989 [
86] (p. 14). However, what De Benoist calls “liberal” is perhaps better called “neoliberal”—a notion that never took off in a French intellectual culture that has not liked liberalism much and generally does not distinguish between the two. Liberalism, De Benoist argues, in line with many of his (non-rightist) French compatriots, “destroys community”; it reduces social life to the “care of material things”; it “does not defend liberty but the right to be private”; and politics is reduced to “a kind of service for economic bosses, administration replaces leadership, nations are reduced to mere markets” [
87] (p. 190). Overall, “liberalism”, as De Benoist understands it, is the “main enemy” [
87] (p. 198), which is evidently a repeat-line of his. Communism or Islam take rather subordinate roles in this respect (and Islam perhaps no role at all).
While it is central to New Right thinking, the anti-(neo)liberal motif is subdued in the programs of populist right parties. As mentioned above, this may be due to (many of) these parties’ neoliberal pasts, and their prior endorsement of anti-tax and anti-welfare platforms, in this faithful to the interests of the old middle class of small shop-owners and artisans, their earliest core constituency. Certainly, as they turned anti-immigrant, some populist right parties, especially in the small liberal north-western and northern states of Europe, have complemented their trademark ethnic nationalism with a defense of liberal values, such as gender equality and the freedom of speech [
91]. However, they did so only instrumentally, to denounce an “illiberal” Islam [
92].
The clearest continuity between New Right thinking and populist right party platforms is thus ethnopluralism and its xenophobic implications. If the Danish People’s Party defends the “right of the peoples of Western Europe…to their homelands” [
85] (p. 481), and if it claims that “Denmark belongs to the Danes”, this is ethnopluralism in practice. So is the Austrian FPÖ’s avowal to “protect…the indigenous population” and “Austrian dominant culture” within a Europe of “self-governing peoples and fatherlands” [
93]. US President Donald Trump’s foreign policy also was recognizably ethnopluralist, probably transmitted to him by the Alt-Right in his inner circle: “I honor the right of every nation…to pursue its own customs, beliefs, and traditions. The United States will not tell you how to live or work or worship. We only ask that you honor our sovereignty in return…Ultimately, the only long-term solution to the migration crisis is to help people build more hopeful futures in their home countries. Make their countries great again”
22.
5.2. Welfare Chauvinism
The nasty truth of ethnopluralism is that its “pluralism” part is not meant to apply to domestic society. After all, it is an intellectual articulation of ethnic nationalism, despite the left-multiculturalist rhetoric. In policy terms, welfare chauvinism, next to the rejection of immigration, is this nationalism’s most pertinent expression, at least in Western Europe. Welfare chauvinism “promotes nativism as the main organizing principle of social policy” and has been embraced by populist radical right parties as they moved away from “neoliberal economic views” [
26] (p. 294). Considering that these parties combine an “anti-state petite bourgeoisie” and a “traditionally left-leaning working class” clientele, to become pro-welfare, in however constricted ways, is not an obvious move [
94] (p. 328). Nevertheless, populist right parties may support “deregulation”, perhaps, especially if in coalition with the center-right; but not “welfare retrenchment” [
94] (p. 328). In colloquial language, welfare chauvinism thrives on the image that “Henk and Ingrid pay for Ali and Fatima”, as has been the slogan of Dutch populist Geert Wilders’ PVV party. This choice and distribution of names (two Dutch against two Muslim) suggest that not just shared citizenship, but co-ethnicity should be the condition for welfare entitlement. All immigrants are thus to be categorically excluded. While welfare chauvinism is one of the rare socioeconomic (as against cultural) planks in populist right platforms, it is of interest here as an applied form of ethnic nationalism. Or rather, it shows how little space there is for it in a liberal state.
Indeed, welfare chauvinism, whose thrust is plain ethnic exclusion, runs into severe constitutional obstacles. Not even formal citizenship, which in itself is a rather imperfect proxy for co-ethnicity in liberal states (that tend to have liberal citizenship laws), provides a shell for limiting social benefits. “The principle of equal treatment is simply sacred. Period”, exclaimed a senior civil servant in the Dutch Department of Social Affairs, when probed by his skeptical academic interviewer [
95] (p. 189). As a result, it is “impossible in the Netherlands”, as in other liberal-constitutional states, “to implement any policy that directly discriminates between native-born citizens and legal immigrant residents” [
95] (p. 188). The populist right has adjusted to these constraints, in betting on excessive residence requirements as a second-best. For instance, they demand, as the Dutch PVV does, ten years of legal residence before a migrant becomes eligible for social benefits (five years more than required for legal residence, which usually triggers equal treatment), and they demand excluding temporary migrants in total. The Netherlands, where the populist right has been a strong political force for two decades, shows the reach
and limits of welfare chauvinism: only immigrants with “the most robust status” are entitled to benefits today, after considerable residence time and tough integration tests and requirements [
95] (p. 147).
Welfare chauvinism
sensu stricto is thus non-implementable. Next to the toughening of residence time, one finds two further proxies for it in the populist right. The first is to exclude on the basis of “contribution history”, which is directed against asylum-seekers and undocumented migrants [
26] (p. 307). Consequently, there is little populist opposition to including migrants in pension and unemployment schemes, simply because these schemes operate on the basis of reciprocity and prior insurance payments. By contrast, the strongest opposition is to including migrants in tax-financed social aid or health care, which is the point of the “Henk and Ingrid” polemic. Nevertheless, in insisting on reciprocity and prior contribution, the populist right, not different in this from majority views, takes a de facto neoliberal position, and one that has long found its way into law and policy. Accordingly, a May 2011 report of the Dutch Council for Social Development bears a neoliberal signature that populists, as plain ethnic exclusion is not on offer, can easily accept and make their own: “Who does not contribute…to welfare and innovation cannot stay and is not allowed to make a claim on the welfare state” [
95] (p. 158). The same neoliberal-populist meeting of minds applies to the “duty to integrate” and the responsibility to “maintain oneself independently”, which the Dutch government laid out as its “new vision on integration” in the same year [
95] (p. 161).
Secondly, while right populists have come to oppose welfare retrenchment and austerity, they also oppose positive welfare measures for new risk groups [
96] and Third Way social investment policies [
97]. This proxy for welfare chauvinism, unlike the first, is not a neoliberal position but backward-looking “welfare nostalgia” [
98] (p. 190). Its gist is to continue protecting male and working labor-market insiders, the classic beneficiaries of Bismarckian welfare states. Conversely, welfare nostalgia hits “not only migrants, but also women and perhaps even other non-traditional workers like self-employed and temp workers” [
98] (p. 190). As their main clientele is not actual but prospective losers, who still have something to lose, including relatively secure jobs, populist right parties often support harsh workfare programs for the unemployed, who are considered outside the pale of “hard-working people”. Moreover, these parties stand in for a traditional “transfer-oriented welfare state that downgrades those social investments on which new social risk groups rely” [
99] (p. 10). These populist party positions exactly match the preferences of their voters, who are “pro-welfare” not across the board but only for the “deserving”, like the elderly and handicapped, not the unemployed, within a “particularistic-authoritarian welfare state” [
99] (p. 10).
6. Conclusions
Explaining the populist right in a neoliberal order needs to combine political, economic, and cultural elements, and perhaps more
23. Qua populism, right-wing populism is primarily a political movement addressing the deficit of democracy that is endemic to neoliberalism. However, as it crosses out the liberal elements of democracy, in particular pluralism and constitutionalism, populism, especially the right-wing variant, cannot but become a threat to democracy itself. The economic backdrop to populism is middle-class decline, even though its claims, both on the political demand and supply sides, are mainly cultural. Next to throwing light on the “right” in populist right, cleavage theory is a plausible macro-level explanation of this “cultural deflection”. It shows that globalization has revitalized the cultural cleavage that had first been the result of the late 19th century “national revolution” [
34], but that more recently has taken the form of a transnational cleavage. The economics–culture conundrum remains the central challenge for contemporary populism studies. The least to say is that one-sided, either economy- or culture-focused explanations must fail.
Let us look at two prominent examples. A self-consciously economy-focused analysis of “anti-system politics”, right and left, by Jonathan Hopkin [
101], argues that “creditor countries” generate right-wing populism, while “debtor countries” produce the left-wing variant: “The ways in which welfare systems distribute exposure to economic risks predict whether anti-systems politics takes a…left-wing or right-wing direction” [
101] (p. 17). However, if part of the explanation why populism in (south European) debtor countries is leftist, is that it is carried by “more progressive-minded” youth, the question arises where this “progressive-mindedness” is coming from in the first. It does not appear to be endogenous, so that one would need to factor-in the cultural-value or cleavage changes that Hopkin explicitly rules out: “exposure to inequality and financial insecurity predicts anti-system politics better than cultural changes…” [
101] (p. 51). Moreover, the claim that “(m)ost anti-system right-wingers addressed economic grievances head-on, identifying migration as an economic threat as much as a cultural one” [
101] (p. 251), does not seem to hold empirically. This is even by Hopkin’s own admission, when he argues, correctly in my view, that populist right parties “(lack) credible programs of reform or strategies for fundamental institutional change” [
101] (p. 252).
On the opposite end, a decidedly culture-focused account of the populist right, as recently proposed by Pippa Norris and Ronald Inglehart [
80], also runs into problems. They claim that “cultural values”, better than “economic indicators”, predict populist voting [
80] (p.20). While not denying the role of “economic conditions”, as having “deepened the cultural backlash” (to the post-materialist value revolution of the new left) [
80] (p. 17), their central notion of “cultural backlash” suggests a one-factor explanation that discards economics. Sheri Berman [
60] (pp. 74–75) notes that individual-level surveys, as conducted by Norris and Inglehart [
80], tend to support a cultural explanation of populism, while macro-level analyses support an economic explanation. This is a strong reason for ecumenical thinking on populism. Discarding economic factors faces the difficulty that globalization, which clearly has fueled the rise (and the nationalism) of the populist right, is in the first an economic phenomenon with dismal economic consequences for the core support groups of the populist right. The cleavage theory of Kriesi et al. [
33,
102], which stresses the “cultural logic” (as against “economic logic”) of populist mobilization [
102] (p. 17), nevertheless agrees with the view, favored by most, of culture as only intermediate variable, because the first mover, after all, is “globalization”.
Norris and Inglehart’s “cultural backlash” theory rests on a narrow understanding of who are the “losers” of globalization. The “economic grievance theory” they dismiss is said to identify as losers “the
least prosperous citizens” who provide “strongest support for authoritarian and populist values” [
80] (p. 132; emphasis supplied). However, when summarizing their findings, they concede that “both authoritarian and populist values are consistently stronger among
less well-off people, who are most likely to feel a sense of economic insecurity” [
80] (p. 166; emphasis supplied). As the “least” well-off have long been known to either abstain from the political process or to vote for the left (or for the Democrats in the US, as in the 2016 presidential elections) [
80] (p. 139), Norris and Inglehart in fact confirm the argument of the “squeezed middle” presented above, a middle that has not yet lost but is in fear of losing and inflicted by “social pessimism and nostalgia” [
80] (p. 21). Accordingly, they describe Trump support as “concentrated among socially conservative older white men, non-college graduates, and residents in small-town America” [
80] (p. 21). This, indeed, qua “non-college” and “small-town”, is the declining middle class that, as we argued, has been the main loser of globalization
and support group of the populist right.
I concur with Sheri Berman [
60] (p. 83) that “parsimony is intellectually…satisfying”, but that “understanding the causes of populism and the current problems facing liberal democracy requires embracing complexity and bringing together insights from a variety of perspectives”. I leave it as an open question whether the “economics-culture divide” presupposed in this paper is more a “nominal” than a “real issue”, a self-produced myopia of the mostly “positivist” (Large-N) works that have been synthesized here for explaining the populist right in the neoliberal West
24. Anthropologists, for whom “economics is very cultural and much of culture is about economics”
25, and who have used ethnography rather than survey methods to study the same phenomenon, have been automatically inclined to resist this dichotomy. Don Kalb [
103], for instance, in a review of the “contributions of anthropologists of Europe in…explaining the neo-nationalist ascendancy of the last 20 years”, evocatively speaks of “double devaluations”, which are “all round, economic as well as discursive, cultural as well as material” [
103] (pp. 204, 206)
26. The fact that his picture of “popular shifts towards illiberalism” [
103] (p. 206) is strikingly similar to mine, suggests that there is validity to both.