1. Introduction
Starting from Weyl’s 1916 paper [
1], various problems related to the distribution of the sequence of fractional parts
where
and
are two real numbers, were studied. Weyl’s result implies that, for each
, the sequence (
1) is uniformly distributed for almost all
. See also [
2] for a more precise version of this result. In the opposite direction, Koksma [
3] proved that, if
is fixed, then the sequence (
1) is uniformly distributed for almost all
. In this respect, the exceptional
are Pisot and Salem numbers. Recall that an algebraic integer
is called a Pisot number if its conjugates over
other than
itself (if any) all lie in the open unit disc
. An algebraic integer
is called a Salem number if its degree over
is an even number
and
of its conjugates lie on the unit circle
. (Since such
is reciprocal its other conjugates are
and
). See, for instance, the paper of Pisot and Salem themselves [
4], where they proved that, if
and
is a Salem number, then the sequence (
1) is everywhere dense in
, but not uniformly distributed in
. The monographs [
5,
6] contain some basic information about Pisot and Salem numbers, while in Smyth’s review paper [
7] there are more recent references. In some literature, Pisot numbers are also called Pisot–Vijayaraghavan numbers or PV numbers; see, for instance, some early papers of Vijayaraghavan on this subject [
8,
9,
10,
11].
For algebraic numbers
, at least something can be said about the distribution of (
1). Extending an earlier result of Flatto, Lagarias, and Pollington for rational
[
12], in [
13], it was proved that, for each
and each algebraic number
, there should be a gap between the largest and the smallest limit points of the sequence (
1) which depends only on
except if
is a Pisot number or a Salem number when we need an extra condition
. This result is not only of interest itself but also has several applications. In particular, it seems to be useful in a so-called Erdos similarity conjecture [
14]. The cases when
and
is a Pisot number or a Salem number were treated in [
15,
16], respectively; see also [
17]. Nevertheless, for example, Mahler’s
-problem [
18], where he asks whether, for
, there is a so-called
Z-number, namely,
, such that all elements of (
1) lie in
, is unsolved (see [
19,
20,
21]). However, the situation with any specific transcendental number
is more complicated and less known. For example, it is not known if (
1) with
has one or more than one limit point. Determining whether there is a transcendental number
for which the sequence
,
, has only finitely many limit points is still a completely open problem as well.
We remark that the behavior of the sequence (
1) for
and a transcendental number
can be very different depending on
. In [
22], it was shown that, for any sequence of real numbers
,
, and any
, there is a transcendental number
such that
for all
. (Here,
is the distance from
to the nearest integer.) See also two subsequent papers [
23,
24]. In fact, if we want (
2) to hold not for all
, but only for infinitely many
n, then this follows from another paper of Koksma [
25] with
replaced by a sequence of positive numbers
such that the series
are divergent. In [
22], it was also shown that, for any sequence of positive numbers
,
, there is a transcendental number
for which the inequality
holds for infinitely many
. This time, there are no conditions or restrictions whatsoever on the rate of convergence of
to zero.
In this paper, it will be shown that, even if we replace in (
1) a fixed number
by any sequence of positive numbers
,
, which is not converging to zero faster than the exponential function, then there are “many” numbers
such that
is smaller than an arbitrary positive number
for infinitely many
, regardless of how fast the sequence
,
, converges to zero. (This type of sequence, specifically, with
and an integer
, was considered before; see [
26], where their density in
was established, and [
27,
28,
29].) Of course, the theorem stated below holds in the special case when
for each
and, more generally, when
is bounded away from zero, namely,
for
.
Theorem 1. Let and be two sequences of positive numbers such thatThen, for any interval , where , there is an uncountable set such that, for each , the inequalitieshold for infinitely many . Note that the condition (
3) of Theorem 1 cannot be omitted. For example, if
,
and
, then, for each
and each sufficiently large
, we have
so there is no
in the interval
for which the inequality (
4) is true for infinitely many
. Similarly, if
, then there is no
at all for which (
4) is true for infinitely many
.
Of course, since the set
is uncountable and
is countable,
contains an uncountable subset of transcendental numbers
with the property (
4). Therefore, Theorem 1 is already more general than Theorem 3 of [
22] for
.
Replace each
by
and set
for every
. (Here and below,
is the ceiling function, namely, the smallest integer greater than or equal to
.) It is clear then that
is an unbounded nondecreasing sequence of positive integers such that each element of the sequence
does not exceed the corresponding element of the sequence
. Therefore, in order to prove Theorem 1, it suffices to show that for each interval
, there is an uncountable set of real numbers
such that, for every
, the inequalities
hold for infinitely many
.
We will prove the following more general statement:
Theorem 2. Let be a sequence of positive numbers satisfying (3), and let be an unbounded sequence of positive integers. Then, for any interval , , and any real number , there is an uncountable set such that, for each , the inequalitieshold for infinitely many pairs . It is clear that (
6) implies (
5), with, for example,
, so Theorem 2 immediately implies Theorem 1.
We will derive Theorem 2 from the following proposition of independent interest.
Proposition 1. Let be a sequence of real numbers, and let be a sequence of positive numbers. Assume that , where , and let be an infinite subset of . Then there is an uncountable set such that, for each , the inequalitieshold for infinitely many . Note that, if
…
and if the sequence
tends to zero faster than any constant power of
, then the numbers
satisfying (
7) are Liouville numbers. Recall that a Liouville number is a real number whose irrationality exponent is infinite, see p. 248 in [
30]. This means that, for any
, there is a pair of integers
, where
, such that
Therefore, Proposition 1 is the construction of uncountably many Liouville type numbers with good approximation not just by rational fractions , , but by fractions with “moving numerator” . The author thanks Prof. Nikolay Moshchevitin for a useful advice towards this construction. Note that the approximation to those special Liouville type numbers is with and with n being not just in but in any infinite sequence of positive integers . For instance, can be the set of squares or the set of primes.
Next, we will prove Proposition 1 (
Section 2) and then derive Theorem 2 from this proposition (
Section 3). In
Section 4, we will give a stronger version of Theorem 1 under a condition slightly stronger than that in (
3). Then, in
Section 5, we provide another application of Proposition 1.
Section 6 contains some final remarks.
2. Proof of Proposition 1
We begin with the following simple observation:
Lemma 1. Let be a closed real interval with , and let be two real numbers. Then, for each sufficiently large positive integer n, there is an integer such that .
Proof. Take any integer
n satisfying
Note that
. Select
Then
, and hence
. Next, from (
8) and (
9), it follows that
Therefore, the numbers
and
both belong to the interval
I, which completes the proof of the lemma. □
Next, for any sequence of real numbers , , and any infinite sequence of positive integers , we will prove the existence of a real number that is very close to the fraction for infinitely many pairs , where and .
Lemma 2. Let be a sequence of real numbers, and let be a sequence of positive numbers. Let , where , and let be infinite. Then, for any sequence , where for each , there is a positive real number and a sequence in such that, for every , we have Proof. We will construct the number
using the method of nested intervals. Set
. Take the least integer
in
satisfying
and set
Note that
so
chosen in (
11) satisfies the inequality (
8). Choosing
as in (
9), namely,
and applying Lemma 1, we find that both endpoints of the interval
belong to the interval
. Consequently, as
,
is its subinterval, so it satisfies
. Furthermore, for any number
, we have
From
and
, it follows that
(where
is the integral part of
), so (
10) is true for
and any number
from the interval
.
We now argue by induction on
j. Assume that
is an integer such that, for
, there is a nested collection of intervals
with uniquely chosen
…
in
and
such that
For any
, we clearly have
so (
10) is true for
and any number
from the interval
.
Next, we will show how to choose the interval
of the form
contained in
, with
and
in
. To this end, we will apply Lemma 1, with
being the left endpoint of
,
being the right endpoint of
, and the smallest integer
in
satisfying
As above, applying Lemma 1 to
due to
, we can choose an appropriate integer
by (
9), namely,
Then, by Lemma 1, both endpoints of the interval
belong to
. Consequently, the subinterval
of
, which we defined in (
13), satisfies
.
By this construction, since the length of , namely, , tends to zero as , the unique point of the intersection is the required positive real number . (It is clear that .) □
We now show that the numbers
and
are distinct for distinct vectors
Indeed, let
ℓ be the smallest positive integer for which
. Without restriction of generality, we may assume that
and
. Since
, the intervals
and
constructed in (
12) are the same for
. Furthermore, the integers
and
are also the same. (In view of (
14) and (
15), they do not depend on
.) Therefore, by (
12) and
, we find that
and
Note that the intervals and are disjoint. Since and , the numbers and are distinct. In fact, we always have the inequality if the vector is lexicographically smaller than the vector .
Clearly, there is a continuum of such distinct sequences
when
runs over all possible infinite sequences consisting of 2 and 4. As we have shown above, the numbers
are all distinct, so there are continuum of numbers
. This completes the proof of Proposition 1, because in (
10) we have
and
, so (
7) is true for each
.
3. Proof of Theorem 2
Fix any and an interval , where . Note that, without restriction of generality, we may assume that , because in case , one can consider the subinterval of I instead of I itself.
In order to apply Proposition 1, we will consider the sequence of positive numbers
,
for each
. Then,
is a sequence of positive numbers. Let also
for each
.
Fix any
in the interval
. Then, by (
3), there is an infinite sequence
such that, for each
, we have
Furthermore, by (
17), for
, we have
Now, by Proposition 1 applied to the interval
and (
16), there is an uncountable in
J set of positive numbers
B such that, for each
, the inequalities
hold for infinitely many pairs
, where
and
. Multiplying all this by
, we derive that the inequalities
hold for infinitely many pairs
, where
and
. Note that, by (
17), we have
Let
S be the set of numbers of the form
, where
runs over every element of
B. Note that the map
maps the interval
J defined in (
19) into the interval
. Therefore, the set
S is a subset of
. Moreover, the set
S is uncountable because so is the set
B.
Consider the difference
By (
20), the exponent here is in the interval
. Additionally,
by (
20) as well. Consequently, from (
21), it follows that
for a sufficient large
. Here, in view of (
18), for each sufficiently large
, the corresponding integer
m must be positive. This completes the proof of (
6).