Next Article in Journal
On a Generalization of the Kummer’s Quadratic Transformation and a Resolution of an Isolated Case
Next Article in Special Issue
Analysis of the Zagreb Indices over the Weakly Zero-Divisor Graph of the Ring Zp×Zt×Zs
Previous Article in Journal
Boundary Controlling Synchronization and Passivity Analysis for Multi-Variable Discrete Stochastic Inertial Neural Networks
Previous Article in Special Issue
An Approximation Algorithm for a Variant of Dominating Set Problem
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

Equitable Coloring of IC-Planar Graphs with Girth g ≥ 7

Department of Mathematics, Zhejiang Normal University, Jinhua 321004, China
*
Author to whom correspondence should be addressed.
Axioms 2023, 12(9), 822; https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms12090822
Submission received: 22 July 2023 / Revised: 16 August 2023 / Accepted: 23 August 2023 / Published: 26 August 2023
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Recent Advances in Graph Theory with Applications)

Abstract

:
An equitable k-coloring of a graph G is a proper vertex coloring such that the size of any two color classes differ at most 1. If there is an equitable k-coloring of G, then the graph G is said to be equitably k-colorable. A 1-planar graph is a graph that can be embedded in the Euclidean plane such that each edge can be crossed by other edges at most once. An IC-planar graph is a 1-planar graph with distinct end vertices of any two crossings. In this paper, we will prove that every IC-planar graph with girth g 7 is equitably Δ ( G ) -colorable, where Δ ( G ) is the maximum degree of G.

1. Introduction

Chromatic graph theory originates from the Four Color Conjecture [1], is a focal problem in graph theory. As a special case of chromatic graph theory, equitable coloring has been widely used in industrial production, enterprise management and biology [2]. Especially, it plays a crucial role in the study of schedule [3], partition [4,5,6,7] and load balancing [8]. In this paper, we mainly discuss the equitable coloring of IC-planar graphs with girth g 7 . Some relevant definitions are as follows.
Only undirected, finite and simple graphs are considered in this paper. In a graph G , V ( G ) , E ( G ) , | G | ,   δ ( G ) and Δ ( G ) (or Δ in short) are used to denote the vertex set, edge set, order, minimum degree and maximum degree of G, respectively. The girth of a graph G is the length of shortest cycles of G, denoted by g ( G ) . For v V ( G ) , we use d G ( v ) to denote the degree of a vertex v in G . The set of all neighbors of v is denoted by N G ( v ) . Trivially, | N G ( v ) | = d G ( v ) .
A graph that can be drawn in the Euclidean plane such that any two edges intersect only at their ends is called the planar graph. A planar graph with such a particular drawing is called a plane graph. The face set of a plane graph G is denoted by F ( G ) . For f F ( G ) , we use d G ( f ) to denote the degree of a face f in G. That is, the number of edges on the boundary of f. We denote f = [ v 1 v 2 v k ] when v 1 , v 2 , , v k are the vertices on the boundary of f and arranged in clockwise order. In a graph G, a vertex is called as a k-vertex, a k -vertex or a k + -vertex if its degree is equal to k, at most k or at least k, respectively. Similarly, we can define a k-face, a k -face or a k + -face. For a k-face f F ( G ) , we denote f as ( d 1 , d 2 , , d k ) -face if the vertices on the boundary of f are u 1 , u 2 , , u k such that d ( u i ) = d i , 1 i k .
A 1-planar graph is a graph that can be embedded in the Euclidean plane such that each edge can be crossed by other edges at most once. An IC-planar graph is a 1-planar graph with distinct end vertices of any two crossings, which is introduced by Alberson [9] in 2008.
A proper k-coloring of a graph G is a mapping ϕ : V ( G ) { 1 , 2 , , k } such that ϕ ( u ) ϕ ( v ) for any two adjacent vertices u and v . The minimum positive integer k such that G has a proper k-coloring is called the chromatic number of G , denoted by χ ( G ) . And we use V i ( 1 i k ) to denote the set of vertices colored with i. Notice that V i ( 1 i k ) is an independent set.
Definition 1.
For a proper k-coloring ϕ of G , if | | V i | | V j | | 1 for any i , j { 1 , 2 , , k } , then ϕ is an equitable k-coloring of G, or G is equitably k-colorable. The minimum positive integer k such that G has an equitable k-coloring is called the equitable chromatic number of G , denoted by χ e ( G ) .
Obviously, χ e ( G ) χ ( G ) , and the inequality can be strictly held.
The rest of this article is organized as follows: In Section 2, we will introduce the history and recent progress on equitable coloring, and we also present our motivation and contribution of this paper. In Section 3, we provide some lemmas which are helpful to prove our main theorem. In Section 4, we discuss the structures of IC-planar graphs with girth g 7 and get an important property, which is presented in Lemma 5. In Section 5, we use discharging method to prove Lemma 5, which is used to prove Lemma 6 and Theorem 1. In Section 6, to show Theorem 1, we first give proof of Lemma 6 and then get a corollary. Finally, we summarize our result and get the main theorem.

2. Related Work

In 1973, Meyer [10] introduced the concept of equitable coloring. At the same time, he proposed the following conjecture.
Conjecture 1
([10]). If G is a connected graph except C 2 m + 1 or K m , then χ e ( G ) Δ .
In 1964, Erdős [11] conjectured that every graph is equitably k-colorable for any k Δ + 1 , which was confirmed by Hajnal and Szemerédi [12] in 1970. In 2010, by applying algorithm analysis, Kierstead et al. [13] gave a new and short proof of Erdős’s conjecture. So we are interested in the sufficient conditions for graphs to be equitably Δ -colorable. In 1994, Chen, Lih and Wu [14] put forth the following conjecture.
Conjecture 2
([14]). If G is a connected graph except C 2 m + 1 , K m or K 2 m + 1 , 2 m + 1 for all m 1 , then G is equitably Δ-colorable.
The authors [14] also confirmed Conjecture 2 for all connected graphs with Δ 3 , which was strengthened to graphs with Δ 4 by Kierstead and Kostochka [15]. Chen and Lih [16], Lih and Wu [17] showed Conjecture 2 holds for trees and bipartite graphs, respectively. Kostochka [18] proved that Conjecture 2 holds for outerplanar graphs. Kostochka and Nakprasit [19] proved further that Conjecture 2 holds for d-degenerate graphs with Δ 14 d + 1 . Wang and Zhang [20] showed Conjecture 2 holds for line graphs. In 1998, Zhang and Yap [21] confirmed Conjecture 2 for planar graphs with Δ 13 . In 2012, Nakprasit [22] improved the above result by showing that Conjecture 2 holds for planar graphs with Δ 9 . Recently, this result has been extended to planar graphs with Δ 8 by Kostochka, Lin and Xiang [23]. Therefore, for planar graphs, only the case of 5 Δ 7 remains unsolved. In 2008, Zhu and Bu [24] proved that every planar graph without 4-cycles and 5-cycles is equitably k-colorable for k max { Δ , 7 } . Later, the above result was extended to all planar graphs without 4-cycles and 5-cycles by Wang and Gui [25]. Thus, we have every planar graph with girth g 6 is equitably Δ -colorable. In 2016, Zhang [26] first considered the equitable coloring of 1-planar graphs and obtained that Conjecture 2 holds when Δ 17 , which was improved to Δ 15 by Zhang, Wang and Xu [27] in 2018. At the same time, Zhang, Wang and Xu [27] also confirmed that Conjecture 2 holds for IC-planar graphs with Δ 12 .
Similar with planar graphs, we also want to see whether Conjecture 2 holds for IC-planar graphs with girth limitation. In this paper, we will concern on the equitable coloring of IC-planar graphs with large girth g and will prove the result in the following:
Theorem 1.
Every IC-planar graph with girth g 7 is equitably Δ-colorable.

3. Preliminaries

In this section, we present some helpful lemmas that will be used to prove our main result.
Lemma 1
([24]). Let S = { v 1 , v 2 , , v k } be a subset of V ( G ) , where v 1 , v 2 , , v k are distinct vertices. If G S is equitably k-colorable, and N G ( v i ) S k i for 1 i k , then G is equitably k-colorable.
Lemma 2
([12,13]). For k Δ + 1 , every graph is equitably k-colorable.
Lemma 3
([28]). If G is a planar graph of order n and with no cycles of length 3 and 4, then e ( G ) 5 3 n 10 3 .
Lemma 4.
Let G be an IC-planar graph of order n and with no cycles of length 3 and 4, then e ( G ) 23 12 n 10 3 and G is 3-degenerate.
Proof. 
We denote the graph obtained by deleting one of the edges from each crossing as G . By the definition of IC-planar graph, we delete at most n 4 edges. Obviously, G is a planar graph of order n and with no cycles of length 3 and 4. So e ( G ) 5 3 n 10 3 by Lemma 3. Thus, e ( G ) 5 3 n 10 3 + n 4 = 23 12 n 10 3 .
By Handshaking Theorem, δ ( G ) · n v V ( G ) d ( v ) = 2 e ( G ) 23 6 n 20 3 , which implies that δ ( G ) 3 . Thus, G is 3-degenerate. □

4. Properties of IC-Planar Graphs with Girth g 7

Every IC-planar graph with girth g 7 in the following is assumed to be embedded in the Euclidean plane with the number of crossings as small as possible. The set of all crossing vertices and the edges with no crossings are denoted by C ( G ) and E 0 ( G ) , respectively. Let E 1 ( G ) = { x z , z y | x y E ( G ) \ E 0 ( G ) , and z is the crossing vertex on edge x y }. The associated plane graph of G, denoted by G × , is a plane graph such that V ( G × ) = V ( G ) C ( G ) , and E ( G × ) = E 0 ( G ) E 1 ( G ) . In G × , a vertex v is called true if v V ( G ) , and false if v C ( G ) . Obviously, a false vertex v satisfies d G × ( v ) = 4 . A face f in G × is false if f is incident with at least one false vertex; otherwise, f is true. Let f be a false i-face and v be a true vertex, where i { 3 , 4 } , f is called the pendant false i-face of v if v is not incident with f but is adjacent to the false vertex incident with f. Finally, we use f i ( v ) , n i ( G ) and n i G ( v ) to denote the number of i-faces incident with the vertex v in the associated plane graph G × , the number of i-vertices in the graph G and the number of i-vertices adjacent to the vertex v in the graph G, respectively.
It is easy to check that the following two properties hold by the fact that G is the IC-planar graph with girth g 7 .
Fact 1 ( 1 ) Any two false vertices are not adjacent.
( 2 ) A true vertex is adjacent to at most one false vertex.
Fact 2 A true vertex is incident with at most one false 3-face.
Next, let’s introduce some facts, which is also involved in the proofs of the next lemma. Since the IC-planar graph has been embedded with minimal number of crossings, the following fact holds.
Fact 3 A false 3-face is not incident with any 2-vertex.
Suppose that v is a false vertex. Let v i ( 1 i 4 ) be the vertices adjacent to v in G × and arranged in clockwise order. Let f i = [ v i + 1 v v i ] be the false face with v v i and v v i + 1 as boundary edges, where 1 i 4 and v 5 = v 1 . Not that v 1 v 3 E ( G ) and v 2 v 4 E ( G ) .
Fact 4 Let v be a false vertex. If f 3 ( v ) = 1 , say d G × ( f 1 ) = 3 , then d G × ( f i ) 6 , where i { 2 , 3 , 4 } . Hence, v is incident with at most one false 3-face.
Proof. 
Let f 1 = [ v 2 v v 1 ] . By Fact 2, we have d G × ( v 1 ) 3 and d G × ( v 2 ) 3 . Since v 1 v 3 E ( G ) , v 2 v 4 E ( G ) and v 1 v 2 E ( G ) , we have v 2 v 3 E ( G ) , v 3 v 4 E ( G ) and v 1 v 4 E ( G ) by the fact that g 7 . That is, d G × ( f i ) 4 for i { 2 , 3 , 4 } .
Now we are going to show that d G × ( f 2 ) 6 . Assume to the contrary that d G × ( f 2 ) 5 . If d G × ( f 2 ) = 4 , say f 2 = [ v 3 v v 2 x ] , then x is a true vertex, x { v 1 , v 4 } , and G contains a 4-cycle v 1 v 2 x v 3 v 1 , a contradiction. If d G × ( f 2 ) = 5 , say f 2 = [ v 3 v v 2 x y ] , then x and y are true vertices, x , y { v 1 , v 4 } , and G contains a 5-cycle v 1 v 2 x y v 3 v 1 , a contradiction. Hence, d G × ( f 2 ) 6 . By symmetry, we have d G × ( f 4 ) 6 .
Next we will show that d G × ( f 3 ) 6 . Assume to the contrary that d G × ( f 3 ) 5 . If d G × ( f 3 ) = 4 , say f 3 = [ v 4 v v 3 x ] , then x is a true vertex, x { v 1 , v 2 } , and G contains a 5-cycle v 1 v 2 v 4 x v 3 v 1 , a contradiction. If d G × ( f 3 ) = 5 , say f 3 = [ v 4 v v 3 x y ] , then x and y are true vertices, x , y { v 1 , v 2 } , and G contains a 6-cycle v 1 v 2 v 4 y x v 3 v 1 , a contradiction. Hence, d G × ( f 3 ) 6 . □
Fact 5 Let v be a false vertex. If f 4 ( v ) = 1 , say d G × ( f 1 ) = 4 , then d G × ( f 3 ) 5 , d G × ( f 2 ) 6 , and d G × ( f 4 ) 6 . Hence, v is incident with at most one false 4-face.
Proof. 
Let f 1 = [ v 2 v v 1 x 1 ] , then x 1 is a true vertex, x 1 { v 3 , v 4 } . By Fact 4, we have d G × ( f i ) 4 for i { 2 , 3 , 4 } . By g 7 , we have v 3 x 1 E ( G ) , v 3 v 2 E ( G ) , v 4 x 1 E ( G ) , v 4 v 1 E ( G ) , v 4 v 3 E ( G ) and v 2 v 1 E ( G ) .
Now we are going to show that d G × ( f 2 ) 6 . Assume to the contrary that d G × ( f 2 ) 5 . If d G × ( f 2 ) = 4 , say f 2 = [ v 3 v v 2 x 2 ] , then x 2 is a true vertex, x 2 { v 1 , x 1 , v 4 } and G contains a 5-cycle v 1 x 1 v 2 x 2 v 3 v 1 , a contradiction. If d G × ( f 2 ) = 5 , say f 2 = [ v 3 v v 2 x 2 y 1 ] , then x 2 and y 1 are true vertices, x 2 , y 1 { v 1 , v 4 } and y 1 x 1 . If x 2 = x 1 , then G contains a 4-cycle v 1 x 1 y 1 v 3 v 1 , a contradiction. If x 2 x 1 , then G contains a 6-cycle v 1 x 1 v 2 x 2 y 1 v 3 v 1 , a contradiction. Hence, d G × ( f 2 ) 6 . By symmetry, we have d G × ( f 4 ) 6 .
Next we will show that d G × ( f 3 ) 5 . Assume to the contrary that d G × ( f 3 ) = 4 , say f 3 = [ v 4 v v 3 x 3 ] , then x 3 is a true vertex, x 3 { v 1 , x 1 , v 2 } , and G contains a 6-cycle v 1 x 1 v 2 v 4 x 3 v 3 v 1 , a contradiction. Hence, d G × ( f 3 ) 5 . □
Lemma 5.
Let G be a connected IC-planar graph with g 7 and | G | 6 , then G contains one of the following configurations H 1 H 9 .
Axioms 12 00822 i001
Remark 1.
Each configuration depicted above is such that: ( 1 ) the vertices which are labelled as x k , x k 1 , x k 2 in every configuration are different while the other vertices may be not distinct; ( 2 ) the degree of solid vertices are exactly shown; ( 3 ) the degree of hollow vertices may be larger than or equal to the degree shown in the figure, except for specially pointed.

5. Proof of Lemma 5

On the contrary, assume that Lemma 5 is not true. Let G be a counterexample. Then G is a connected IC-planar graph with g 7 and | G | 6 , but without configurations H 1 H 9 . Now we consider G × , the associated plane graph of G.
In the following, we use Euler’s formula and discharging analysis on G × to derive a contradiction. We define the initial weight function w such that w ( v ) = 2 d G × ( v ) 6 for each v V ( G × ) , and w ( f ) = d G × ( f ) 6 for each f F ( G × ) . By Euler’s formula V ( G × ) E ( G × ) + F ( G × ) = 2 and Handshaking Theorem, we can deduce that
x V ( G × ) F ( G × ) w ( x ) = v V ( G × ) ( 2 d G × ( v ) 6 ) + f F ( G × ) ( d G × ( f ) 6 ) = 12 .
Next, we will design the appropriate discharging rules to redistribute the weights on V ( G × ) F ( G × ) depending on the value of δ ( G × ) . Once the discharging process is finished, a new weight function w ( x ) is produced while the total sum of weights is kept fixed. Then we will show that x V ( G × ) F ( G × ) w ( x ) > 12 = x V ( G × ) F ( G × ) w ( x ) to derive the contradiction. For x , y V ( G × ) F ( G × ) , let τ ( x y ) be the weight transferred from x to y.
By Lemma 4, we have δ ( G ) 3 . So δ ( G × ) 3 . Thus, the proof will be divided into the following cases depending on the value of δ ( G × ) .
Case 1.
δ ( G × ) = 3 .
Our discharging rules are defined as follows.
R1. Suppose that v is a false 4-vertex and f is the face incident with v. If d G × ( f ) = 3 , then τ ( v f ) = 2 ; if d G × ( f ) = 4 , then τ ( v f ) = 3 2 ; if d G × ( f ) = 5 , then τ ( v f ) = 1 2 .
R2. Suppose that v is a true 4-vertex.
R2.1 Let f be a false face incident with v. If d G × ( f ) = 3 , then τ ( v f ) = 1 ; if d G × ( f ) = 4 , then τ ( v f ) = 1 2 ; if d G × ( f ) = 5 , then τ ( v f ) = 1 2 .
R2.2 Let f be a pendant false 3-face of v. Then τ ( v f ) = 1 2 .
R3. Suppose that v is a true 5 + -vertex.
R3.1 Let f be a false face incident with v. If d G × ( f ) = 3 , then τ ( v f ) = 1 ; if d G × ( f ) = 4 , then τ ( v f ) = 1 2 ; if d G × ( f ) = 5 , then τ ( v f ) = 1 2 .
R3.2 Let f be a pendant false face of v. If d G × ( f ) = 3 , then τ ( v f ) = 1 ; if d G × ( f ) = 4 , then τ ( v f ) = 1 2 .
Next, we are going to show that for each element x V ( G × ) F ( G × ) , w ( x ) 0 .
Suppose that v V ( G × ) with d G × ( v ) = k . Let v 1 , , v k be the vertices adjacent to v in G × and arranged in clockwise order. Let f i be the face with v v i and v v i + 1 as boundary edges, where 1 i k and v k + 1 = v 1 .
Claim 1.1  w ( v ) 3 2 k 6 for each true k-vertex v with k 4 .
Proof. 
Let v be a true k-vertex with k 4 . Then w ( v ) = 2 k 6 . By Fact 2 and g 7 , f 3 ( v ) 1 .
If f 3 ( v ) = 1 , say f 1 , then by Fact 4, v does not have pendant false i-faces, i { 3 , 4 } and max { d G × ( f 2 ) , d G × ( f k ) } 6 . Thus, f 4 ( v ) + f 5 ( v ) k 2 . Hence, w ( v ) 2 k 6 1 1 2 ( k 2 ) = 3 2 k 6 by R2–R3.
If f 3 ( v ) = 0 , then by Fact 1, Fact 4 and Fact 5, v has at most one pendant false i-face, i { 3 , 4 } . If v has one pendant false 3-face f, say v 1 is the false vertex incident with f, then min { d G × ( f 1 ) , d G × ( f k ) } 6 by Fact 4. Thus, f 4 ( v ) + f 5 ( v ) k 2 . Hence, w ( v ) 2 k 6 1 1 2 ( k 2 ) = 3 2 k 6 by R2–R3. If v has a pendant false 4-face f, say v 1 is the false vertex incident with f, then max { d G × ( f 1 ) , d G × ( f k ) } 6 by Fact 5. Thus, f 4 ( v ) + f 5 ( v ) k 1 . Hence, w ( v ) 2 k 6 1 2 1 2 ( k 1 ) = 3 2 k 6 by R2–R3. If v does not have any pendant false i-face, i { 3 , 4 } , then w ( v ) 2 k 6 1 2 k = 3 2 k 6 by R2–R3. □
Claim 1.2   w ( v ) 0 for each v V ( G × ) .
Proof. 
Suppose that v is a true 3-vertex. Then w ( v ) = w ( v ) = 0 . Suppose that v is a false 4-vertex. Then w ( v ) = 2 . By Fact 4, f 3 ( v ) 1 . If f 3 ( v ) = 1 , then f 4 ( v ) = f 5 ( v ) = 0 by Fact 4. Thus, w ( v ) = 2 2 = 0 by R1. So suppose that f 3 ( v ) = 0 . Then f 4 ( v ) 1 by Fact 5. If f 4 ( v ) = 1 , then f 5 ( v ) 1 by Fact 5. Thus, w ( v ) 2 3 2 1 2 = 0 by R1. If f 4 ( v ) = 0 , w ( v ) 2 4 × 1 2 = 0 by R1. Suppose that v is a true k-vertex with k 4 . By Claim 1.1, we have w ( v ) 3 2 k 6 3 2 × 4 6 = 0 . □
Claim 1.3   w ( f ) 0 for each f F ( G × ) .
Proof. 
Suppose that d G × ( f ) 6 . Then w ( f ) = w ( f ) 0 . Suppose that d G × ( f ) = k ( 3 k 5 ) . Since G is an IC-planar graph with g 7 , then f is a false face. Let f = [ u 1 u 2 u k ] . By Fact 1, f is incident with one false vertex, say u 1 . Let v 1 , v 2 be the neighbors of u 1 in G × such that v 1 u 2 E ( G ) and v 2 u k E ( G ) .
Suppose that k = 3 . Then w ( f ) = 3 , and τ ( u 1 f ) = 2 by R1. If f is a ( 3 , 3 , 4 ) -face, then max { d G ( v 1 ) , d G ( v 2 ) } 5 or d G ( v 1 ) = d G ( v 2 ) = 4 by G contains no configuration H 1 . Note that f is the pendant false 3-face of v 1 and v 2 . If max { d G ( v 1 ) , d G ( v 2 ) } 5 , say d G ( v 1 ) 5 , then τ ( v 1 f ) = 1 by R3. Hence, w ( f ) 3 + 2 + 1 = 0 . If d G ( v i ) = 4 , where i = 1 , 2 , then τ ( v i f ) = 1 2 by R2. Hence, w ( f ) = 3 + 2 + 2 × 1 2 = 0 . If f is a ( 3 + , 4 + , 4 ) -face, say d G ( u i ) 4 for some i { 2 , 3 } , then τ ( u i f ) = 1 by R2–R3. Hence, w ( f ) 3 + 2 + 1 = 0 .
Suppose that k = 4 . Then w ( f ) = 2 , and τ ( u 1 f ) = 3 2 by R1. If f is a ( 3 , 3 , 3 , 4 ) -face, then min { d G ( v 1 ) , d G ( v 2 ) } 5 by G contains no configuration H 1 . Note that f is the pendant false 4-face of v 1 and v 2 . So τ ( v i f ) = 1 2 by R3, where i = 1 , 2 . Hence, w ( f ) = 2 + 3 2 + 2 × 1 2 = 1 2 . If f is a ( 3 + , 3 + , 4 + , 4 ) -face, say d G ( u i ) 4 for some i { 2 , 3 , 4 } , then τ ( u i f ) = 1 2 by R2–R3. Hence, w ( f ) 2 + 3 2 + 1 2 = 0 .
Suppose that k = 5 . Then w ( f ) = 1 , and τ ( u 1 f ) = 1 2 by R1. Since G contains no configuration H 1 , f must be a ( 3 + , 3 + , 3 + , 4 + , 4 ) -face. So d G ( u i ) 4 for some i { 2 , 3 , 4 , 5 } and τ ( u i f ) = 1 2 by R2–R3. Hence, w ( f ) 1 + 1 2 + 1 2 = 0 . □
Thus, 12 = x V ( G × ) F ( G × ) w ( x ) = x V ( G × ) F ( G × ) w ( x ) 0 , which is a contradiction. Hence, the counterexample graph G does not exist and Lemma 5 holds.
Case 2.
δ ( G × ) = 2 and n 2 ( G × ) 2 .
In Case 2, the discharging rules are the same as those in Case 1. With the same arguments as Case 1, we can prove that w ( x ) 0 if x V ( G × ) with d G × ( x ) 3 or x F ( G × ) with d G × ( x ) 6 , or x F ( G × ) with d G × ( x ) 5 and x is not incident with any 2-vertex.
Claim 2.1   w ( f ) 0 , where f F ( G × ) is a k-face incident with 2-vertices and k 5 .
Proof. 
By g 7 , we have f is a false face. By Fact 3, we have 4 k 5 . Let f = [ u 1 u 2 u k ] . By Fact 1, f is incident with one false vertex, say u 1 . Let v 1 , v 2 be the neighbors of u 1 in G × such that v 1 u 2 E ( G ) and v 2 u k E ( G ) .
Suppose that k = 4 . Then w ( f ) = 2 , and τ ( u 1 f ) = 3 2 by R1. If f is a ( 2 , 3 , 3 , 4 ) -face, then min { d G ( v 1 ) , d G ( v 2 ) } 5 by G contains no configuration H 1 . Note that f is the pendant false 4-face of v 1 and v 2 . So τ ( v i f ) = 1 2 by R3, where i = 1 , 2 . Hence, w ( f ) = 2 + 3 2 + 2 × 1 2 = 1 2 . If f is a ( 2 , 2 + , 4 + , 4 ) -face, say d G ( u i ) 4 for some i { 2 , 3 , 4 } , then τ ( u i f ) = 1 2 by R2–R3. Hence, w ( f ) 2 + 3 2 + 1 2 = 0 .
Suppose that k = 5 . Then w ( f ) = 1 , and τ ( u 1 f ) = 1 2 by R1. Since G contains no configuration H 1 , f is a ( 2 , 2 + , 3 + , 4 + , 4 ) -face. So d G ( u i ) 4 for some i { 2 , 3 , 4 , 5 } and τ ( u i f ) = 1 2 by R2–R3. Hence, w ( f ) 1 + 1 2 + 1 2 = 0 . □
Note that w ( v ) = w ( v ) = 2 for each 2-vertex v. Thus, 12 = x V ( G × ) F ( G × ) w ( x ) = x V ( G × ) F ( G × ) w ( x ) 2 × ( 2 ) = 4 , which is a contradiction. Hence, the counterexample graph G does not exist and Lemma 5 holds.
Case 3.
δ ( G × ) = 2 and n 2 ( G × ) 3 .
Since G does not contain H 2 and H 3 as subgraphs, G satisfies the following properties.
Claim 3.1 2-vertex is not adjacent to any 2-vertex.
Claim 3.2 Any 3 + -vertex is adjacent to at most one 2-vertex.
A 2-vertex u V ( G × ) is called a special 2-vertex if u v E ( G ) with d G ( v ) = 3 . Since G does not contain H 4 as a subgraph, the following claim holds.
Claim 3.3   G × has at most one special 2-vertex.
A 4-vertex v V ( G ) is called a special 4-vertex if v is adjacent to a 2-vertex in G; a bad 4-vertex if v is special and adjacent to a 3-vertex in G; a poor 4-vertex if v is special and not adjacent to any 3-vertex. Since G does not contain H 3 , H 5 and H 6 as subgraphs, the following three claims hold.
Claim 3.4 Suppose that v is a poor 4-vertex. Then n 2 G ( v ) = 1 and n 4 + G ( v ) = 3 .
Claim 3.5 Suppose that v is a bad 4-vertex. Then n 2 G ( v ) = 1 , n 3 G ( v ) = 1 and n 5 + G ( v ) = 2 .
Claim 3.6 A special 4-vertex is not adjacent to any special 4-vertex in G.
Claim 3.7 In G × , if v is a special 4-vertex incident with a 4-face, then f 6 + ( v ) 1 .
Proof. 
Suppose that v is a special 4-vertex and v i ( 1 i 4 ) are the neighbors of v in G × and arranged in clockwise order. Let f i be the face with v v i and v v i + 1 as boundary edges, where 1 i 4 and v 5 = v 1 .
Without loss of generality, assume that f 1 = [ v v 1 x 1 v 2 ] is a 4-face. By g 7 , f 1 is a false face. If v 1 or v 2 is a false vertex, then d G × ( f 4 ) 6 or d G × ( f 2 ) 6 by Fact 5. So f 6 + ( v ) 1 . If x 1 is a false vertex, then the vertices in N G × ( v 1 ) N G × ( v 2 ) { x 1 } are true. If d G × ( v 1 ) = 2 or d G × ( v 2 ) = 2 , then d G × ( f 4 ) 6 or d G × ( f 2 ) 6 by Fact 5. So f 6 + ( v ) 1 . So suppose that d G × ( v 1 ) 3 and d G × ( v 2 ) 3 . Without loss of generality, assume that d G × ( v 3 ) = 2 since v is a special 4-vertex. If d G × ( f 2 ) 6 or d G × ( f 4 ) 6 , then Claim 3.7 holds. So suppose that d G × ( f i ) 5 , where i = 2 , 4 . That is, f 2 and f 4 are false faces. Since the vertices in N G × ( v 1 ) N G × ( v 2 ) { x 1 } are true and g 7 , we have d G × ( f i ) = 5 , where i = 2 , 4 . Let f 2 = [ v v 2 y 1 y 2 v 3 ] . Then y 2 is a false vertex. Let f 3 = [ v v 3 y 2 z 1 z t v 4 ] , where t 0 . If t = 0 , then y 2 v 4 E ( G × ) . Since y 2 is a false vertex, we have y 1 v 4 E ( G ) . Thus, G contains a 4-cycle v v 2 y 1 v 4 v , a contradiction. If t = 1 , then y 2 z 1 E ( G × ) , and z 1 is a true vertex. Since y 2 is a false vertex, we have y 1 z 1 E ( G ) . Thus, G contains a 5-cycle v v 2 y 1 z 1 v 4 v , a contradiction. So t 2 . That is, d G × ( f 3 ) 6 . So f 6 + ( v ) 1 . □
Claim 3.8 If G contains a path P 3 = x y z and x is a special 4-vertex, then d G ( y ) 4 or d G ( z ) 4 .
Proof. 
Suppose that x is a poor 4-vertex. By Claim 3.4, n 2 G ( x ) = 1 and n 4 + G ( x ) = 3 . That is, d G ( y ) 4 or d G ( y ) = 2 . If d G ( y ) = 2 , then d G ( z ) 4 since G contains no configuration H 7 .
Suppose that x is a bad 4-vertex. By Claim 3.5, n 2 G ( x ) = 1 , n 3 G ( x ) = 1 and n 5 + G ( x ) = 2 . That is, d G ( y ) 5 , or d G ( y ) = 2 , or d G ( y ) = 3 . If d G ( y ) = 2 , then d G ( z ) 4 since G contains no configuration H 7 . If d G ( y ) = 3 , then d G ( z ) 5 since G contains no configuration H 8 . □
Corollary 1.
If f is a false 4-face incident with a poor 4-vertex, then f is incident with at least two true 4 + -vertices.
Proof. 
Suppose that f = [ v 1 v 2 v 3 v 4 ] is a false 4-face, where v 1 is a false vertex. Then v 2 , v 3 and v 4 are true vertices by Fact 1. If v 2 or v 4 is a poor 4-vertex, say v 2 is a poor 4-vertex, then max { d G ( v 3 ) , d G ( v 4 ) } 4 by Claim 3.8. Therefore, f is incident with at least two true 4 + -vertices. If v 3 is a poor 4-vertex, then max { d G ( v 2 ) , d G ( v 4 ) } 4 by Claim 3.4. Therefore, f is incident with at least two true 4 + -vertices. □
Corollary 2.
If f is a false 5-face incident with a special 4-vertex, then f is incident with at least two true 4 + -vertices.
Proof. 
Suppose that f = [ v 1 v 2 v 3 v 4 v 5 ] is a false 5-face, where v 1 is a false vertex. Then v 2 , v 3 , v 4 and v 5 are true vertices by Fact 1. If v 2 or v 5 is a special 4-vertex, say v 2 is a special 4-vertex, then max { d G ( v 3 ) , d G ( v 4 ) } 4 by Claim 3.8. Therefore, f is incident with at least two true 4 + -vertices. If v 3 or v 4 is a special 4-vertex, say v 3 is a special 4-vertex, then max { d G ( v 4 ) , d G ( v 5 ) } 4 by Claim 3.8. Therefore, f is incident with at least two true 4 + -vertices. □
In this Case, we define the following discharging rules R1–R6, where R1–R3 are the same as those in Case 1.
R4. Suppose that v is a true 4 + -vertex. Then v gives 1 to each adjacent 2-vertex in G.
R5. Suppose that v is a true 5 + -vertex. Then v gives 3 10 to each adjacent bad 4-vertex in G.
R6. Suppose that f is a false face, and v is a special 4-vertex incident with f.
R6.1 Let f be a false 3-face. If v is a special 4-vertex, then τ ( f v ) = 1 2 .
R6.2 Let f be a false 4-face. If v is a poor 4-vertex, then τ ( f v ) = 1 4 ; if v is a bad 4-vertex, then τ ( f v ) = 0 .
R6.3 Let f be a false 5-face. If v is a poor 4-vertex, then τ ( f v ) = 1 4 ; if v is a bad 4-vertex, then τ ( f v ) = 1 10 .
Claim 3.9 Suppose that v V ( G × ) . If d G × ( v ) 3 , or d G × ( v ) = 2 and v is not a special 2-vertex, then w ( v ) 0 .
Proof. 
Suppose that d G × ( v ) = k . Let v 1 , , v k be the vertices adjacent to v in G × and arranged in clockwise order. Let f i be the face with v v i and v v i + 1 as boundary edges, where 1 i k and v k + 1 = v 1 .
Suppose that k = 2 . Then w ( v ) = 2 . If v is a special 2-vertex, then w ( v ) w ( v ) = 2 . If v is not a special 2-vertex, then n 4 + G ( v ) = 2 by Claim 3.1. Hence, w ( v ) = 2 + 2 × 1 = 0 by R4.
Suppose that k = 3 . Then w ( v ) = w ( v ) = 0 .
Suppose that k = 4 . If v is a false 4-vertex, then with the similar arguments as Case 1, we have w ( v ) 0 . Assume that v is a true 4-vertex. Then n 2 G ( v ) 1 by Claim 3.2. If n 2 G ( v ) = 0 , then with the similar arguments as Case 1, we have w ( v ) 0 . So suppose that n 2 G ( v ) = 1 . That is, v is a special 4-vertex. By Fact 2 and g 7 , f 3 ( v ) 1 .
If f 3 ( v ) = 1 , say f 1 = [ v v 1 v 2 ] and v 1 is a false vertex, then by Fact 4, v does not have pendant false i-faces, i { 3 , 4 } , and d G × ( f 4 ) 6 . Thus, f 4 ( v ) + f 5 ( v ) 2 . By R6.1, τ ( f 1 v ) = 1 2 . If f 4 ( v ) + f 5 ( v ) 1 , then w ( v ) 2 1 1 1 2 + 1 2 = 0 by R2, R4 and R6. So suppose that f 4 ( v ) + f 5 ( v ) = 2 . If v is a poor 4-vertex, then τ ( f i v ) = 1 4 by R6, where i = 2 , 3 . Thus, w ( v ) = 2 1 1 2 × 1 2 + 1 2 + 2 × 1 4 = 0 by R2, R4 and R6. If v is a bad 4-vertex, then by Claim 3.5, n 5 + G ( v ) = 2 . Thus, w ( v ) 2 1 1 2 × 1 2 + 1 2 + 2 × 3 10 = 1 10 by R2, R4 and R5.
If f 3 ( v ) = 0 , then by Fact 1, Fact 4 and Fact 5, v has at most one pendant false i-face, i { 3 , 4 } .
  • Suppose that v has a pendant false 3-face f. Then v is adjacent to a false vertex, say v 1 . So d G × ( f 1 ) 6 and d G × ( f 4 ) 6 by Fact 4. Thus, f 4 ( v ) + f 5 ( v ) 2 . Note that τ ( v f ) = 1 2 by R2. If f 4 ( v ) + f 5 ( v ) 1 , then w ( v ) 2 1 1 2 1 2 = 0 by R2 and R4. So suppose that f 4 ( v ) + f 5 ( v ) = 2 . If v is a poor 4-vertex, then τ ( f i v ) = 1 4 by R6, where i = 2 , 3 . Thus, w ( v ) = 2 1 1 2 2 × 1 2 + 2 × 1 4 = 0 by R2, R4 and R6. If v is a bad 4-vertex, then by Claim 3.5, n 5 + G ( v ) = 2 . Thus, w ( v ) 2 1 1 2 2 × 1 2 + 2 × 3 10 = 1 10 by R2, R4 and R5.
  • Suppose that v has a pendant false 4-face f. Then v is adjacent to a false vertex, say v 1 . So max { d G × ( f 1 ) , d G × ( f 4 ) } 6 by Fact 5. Thus, f 4 ( v ) + f 5 ( v ) 3 . Note that τ ( v f ) = 0 by R2. If f 4 ( v ) + f 5 ( v ) 2 , then w ( v ) 2 1 2 × 1 2 = 0 by R2 and R4. So suppose that f 4 ( v ) + f 5 ( v ) = 3 and d G × ( f 1 ) 6 . If v is a poor 4-vertex, then τ ( f i v ) = 1 4 by R6, where i = 2 , 3 , 4 . Thus, w ( v ) = 2 1 3 × 1 2 + 3 × 1 4 = 1 4 by R2, R4 and R6. If v is a bad 4-vertex, then by Claim 3.5, n 5 + G ( v ) = 2 . Thus, w ( v ) 2 1 3 × 1 2 + 2 × 3 10 = 1 10 by R2, R4 and R5.
  • Suppose that v does not have any pendant false i-face, i { 3 , 4 } . Then f 4 ( v ) + f 5 ( v ) 4 . If f 4 ( v ) + f 5 ( v ) 2 , then w ( v ) 2 1 2 × 1 2 = 0 by R2 and R4. Assume that f 4 ( v ) + f 5 ( v ) = 3 and d G × ( f 1 ) 6 . If v is a poor 4-vertex, then τ ( f i v ) = 1 4 by R6, where i = 2 , 3 , 4 . Thus, w ( v ) = 2 1 3 × 1 2 + 3 × 1 4 = 1 4 by R2, R4 and R6. If v is a bad 4-vertex, then by Claim 3.5, n 5 + G ( v ) = 2 . Thus, w ( v ) 2 1 3 × 1 2 + 2 × 3 10 = 1 10 by R2, R4 and R5. Assume that f 4 ( v ) + f 5 ( v ) = 4 . By Claim 3.7, we have f 4 ( v ) = 0 and f 5 ( v ) = 4 . If v is a poor 4-vertex, then τ ( f i v ) = 1 4 by R6, where i = 1 , 2 , 3 , 4 . Thus, w ( v ) = 2 1 4 × 1 2 + 4 × 1 4 = 0 by R2, R4 and R6. If v is a bad 4-vertex, then by Claim 3.5, n 5 + G ( v ) = 2 . Thus, w ( v ) = 2 1 4 × 1 2 + 2 × 3 10 + 4 × 1 10 = 0 by R2, R4–R6.
Suppose that k 5 . By Claim 1.1, the remaining charge of 5 + -vertex is at least 3 2 k 6 after the discharging process R1–R3. By Claim 3.2, n 2 G ( v ) 1 . If n 2 G ( v ) = 0 , then w ( v ) 3 2 k 6 3 10 k = 6 5 k 6 6 5 × 5 6 = 0 by Claim 1.1 and R5. Now we consider that n 2 G ( v ) = 1 . Since G contains no configuration H 6 , then v will not adjacent to any special 4-vertex in G. Thus, w ( v ) 3 2 k 6 1 = 3 2 k 7 3 2 × 5 7 = 1 2 by Claim 1.1 and R4. □
Claim 3.10   w ( f ) 0 for each f F ( G × ) .
Proof. 
Suppose that d G × ( f ) 6 . Then w ( f ) = w ( f ) 0 .
Suppose that d G × ( f ) = k ( 3 k 5 ) . Since G is an IC-planar graph with g 7 , then f is a false face. Let f = [ u 1 u 2 u k ] . By Fact 1, f is incident with one false vertex, say u 1 . Let v 1 , v 2 be the neighbors of u 1 in G × such that v 1 u 2 E ( G ) and v 2 u k E ( G ) .
Suppose that k = 3 . Then w ( f ) = 3 , and τ ( u 1 f ) = 2 by R1. By Fact 3, f is not incident with any 2-vertex. By Claim 3.6, f is incident with at most one special 4-vertex. If f is not incident with any special 4-vertex, then with the similar discussion as Case 1, we can deduce that w ( f ) 0 . Now suppose that f is incident with a special 4-vertex, say u 2 , then τ ( u 2 f ) = 1 by R2 and τ ( f u 2 ) = 1 2 by R6. If f is a ( 3 , 4 , 4 ) -face, then d G ( v 2 ) 5 by G contains no configuration H 8 . Note that f is the pendant false 3-face of v 2 . Thus, τ ( v 2 f ) = 1 by R3. Hence, w ( f ) 3 + 2 + 1 + 1 1 2 = 1 2 . If f is a ( 4 , 4 + , 4 ) -face, then d G ( u 3 ) 4 . Thus, τ ( u 3 f ) = 1 by R2–R3. Hence, w ( f ) = 3 + 2 + 1 + 1 1 2 = 1 2 .
Suppose that k = 4 . Then w ( f ) = 2 , and τ ( u 1 f ) = 3 2 by R1. Assume that f incident with x poor 4-vertices, thus w ( f ) 2 + 3 2 + 1 2 x 1 4 x = 1 4 x 1 2 by R1, R2 and R6. If x 2 , then w ( f ) 0 . If x = 1 , then f is incident with at least two true 4 + -vertices by Corollary 1. Thus, w ( f ) 2 + 3 2 + 1 2 + 1 2 1 4 = 1 4 by R1–R3 and R6. If x = 0 , then with the similar discussion as Case 2, we can deduce that w ( f ) 0 .
Suppose that k = 5 . Then w ( f ) = 1 , and τ ( u 1 f ) = 1 2 by R1. Assume that f incident with x poor 4-vertices and y bad 4-vertices, thus w ( f ) 1 + 1 2 + 1 2 ( x + y ) 1 4 x 1 10 y = 1 2 + 1 4 x + 2 5 y by R1, R2 and R6. If x 2 , or x = 1 and y 1 , or x = 0 and y 2 , then we have w ( f ) 0 . So suppose that x = 1 and y = 0 , or x = 0 and y 1 . If x = 1 and y = 0 , then f is incident with at least two true 4 + -vertices by Corollary 2. Thus, w ( f ) 1 + 1 2 + 2 × 1 2 1 4 = 1 4 by R1–R3 and R6. If x = 0 and y = 1 , then f is incident with at least two true 4 + -vertices by Corollary 2. Thus, w ( f ) 1 + 1 2 + 2 × 1 2 1 10 = 2 5 by R1–R3 and R6. If x = y = 0 , then with the similar discussion as Case 2, we can deduce that w ( f ) 0 . □
By Claim 3.3, there is at most one special 2-vertex in G × . Thus, 12 = x V ( G × ) F ( G × ) w ( x ) = x V ( G × ) F ( G × ) w ( x ) 2 , which is a contradiction. Hence, the counterexample graph G does not exist and Lemma 5 holds.
Case 4.
δ ( G × ) = 1 .
Subcase 4.1   n 1 ( G × ) = 1 and n 2 ( G × ) 2 .
In Subcase 4.1, the discharging rules are the same as those in Case 2. With the same arguments as Case 2, we can prove that w ( x ) 0 for any x V ( G × ) F ( G × ) V , where V is the set of 1-vertex and 2-vertices. Note that w ( u ) = w ( u ) = 4 for the 1-vertex u and w ( v ) = w ( v ) = 2 for each 2-vertex v. Thus, 12 = x V ( G × ) F ( G × ) w ( x ) = x V ( G × ) F ( G × ) w ( x ) 4 + 2 × ( 2 ) = 8 , which is a contradiction. Hence, the counterexample graph G does not exist and Lemma 5 holds.
Subcase 4.2   n 1 ( G × ) = 1 and n 2 ( G × ) 3 .
In Subcase 4.2, the discharging rules are the same as those in Case 3. By Claim 3.3, there is at most one special 2-vertex in G × . With the same arguments as Case 3, we can prove that w ( x ) 0 for any x V ( G × ) F ( G × ) V , where V is the set of 1-vertex and special 2-vertex. Note that w ( u ) = w ( u ) = 4 for the 1-vertex u and w ( v ) 2 for the special 2-vertex v. Thus, 12 = x V ( G × ) F ( G × ) w ( x ) = x V ( G × ) F ( G × ) w ( x ) 4 + ( 2 ) = 6 , which is a contradiction. Hence, the counterexample graph G does not exist and Lemma 5 holds.
Subcase 4.3   n 1 ( G × ) 2 .
Since G does not contain H 9 as a subgraph, G contains exactly two 1-vertices and no 2-vertex. In Subcase 4.3, the discharging rules are the same as those in Case 1. With the same arguments as Case 1, we can prove that w ( x ) 0 for any x V ( G × ) F ( G × ) V , where V is the set of 1-vertices. Note that w ( u ) = w ( u ) = 4 for each 1-vertex u. Thus, 12 = x V ( G × ) F ( G × ) w ( x ) = x V ( G × ) F ( G × ) w ( x ) 2 × ( 4 ) = 8 , which is a contradiction. Hence, the counterexample graph G does not exist and Lemma 5 holds. □

6. Proof of Theorem 1

Before we prove Theorem 1, it is necessary to present the following result.
Lemma 6.
Let G be an IC-planar graph with g 7 . If k max { Δ , 5 } , then G is equitably k-colorable.
Proof. 
Assume to the contrary that G is a counterexample with fewest vertices of Lemma 6. If the order of each component of G is at most five, then Δ 4 . Thus, k max { Δ , 5 } Δ + 1 , and G is equitably k-colorable by Lemma 2. Otherwise, there is a component of G with order at least six. By Lemma 5, G contains one of the configurations H 1 H 9 in Lemma 6. By Lemma 1, we need to choose the subset S, and define the subset S as follows.
If G contains configurations H i , i { 1 , 4 , 5 , 7 , 8 } , then S = { x k , x k 1 , x k 2 , x k 3 , x 1 } . If G contains configurations H i , i { 3 , 6 } , then S = { x k , x k 1 , x k 2 , x 2 , x 1 } . If G contains configurations H i , i { 2 , 9 } , then S = { x k , x k 1 , x k 2 , x 1 } . By Lemma 4, G is 3-degenerate, thus the remaining unspecified vertices in S can be remarked by choosing the minimum degree vertex in a graph obtained from G by deleting the remarked vertices at each step from highest to lowest indices. It is easy to confirm that for every 1 i k , the subset S defined above satisfies that N G ( x i ) S k i .
Let H = G S G . Then Δ ( H ) Δ . If Δ ( H ) < Δ , then H is equitably k-colorable by Lemma 2. Otherwise, H is equitably k-colorable since G is a counterexample with fewest vertices. Therefore, G is equitably k-colorable by Lemma 1. □
By Lemma 2, we have the following corollary:
Corollary 3.
Let G be an IC-planar graph with g 7 . If Δ 5 , then G is equitably Δ-colorable.
Combining Corollary 3, and the conclusions in [14,15], we complete the proof of Theorem 1.
With this conclusion, we can solve the problem of equitable coloring of IC-planar graphs with large girth g ( g 7 ) limitation.

Author Contributions

Conceptualization, D.H. and X.W.; methodology, D.H.; validation, D.H. and X.W.; writing—original draft preparation, X.W.; writing—review and editing, D.H. and X.W.; supervision, D.H.; project administration, D.H. and X.W.; funding acquisition, D.H. All authors have read and agreed to the published version of the manuscript.

Funding

This research was funded by National Natural Science Foundation of China grant number 12171436.

Data Availability Statement

This paper has no associated data.

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

References

  1. Bondy, J.A.; Murty, U.S.R. Graph Theory with Applications; North-Holland: New York, NY, USA, 1976. [Google Scholar]
  2. Kaul, H.; Jacobson, S.H. New global optima results for the Kauffman NK model: Handling dependency. Math. Program. 2006, 108, 475–494. [Google Scholar]
  3. De Werra, D. A few remarks on chromatic scheduling. In Combinatorial Programming: Methods and Applications, Proceedings of the NATO Advanced Study Institute, Versailles, France, 2–13 September 1974; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1975; pp. 337–342. [Google Scholar]
  4. Monteiro, B.; dos Santos, V.F. Equitable partition of graphs into independent sets and cliques. Math. Contemp. 2022, 48, 116–125. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  5. Zhang, X.; Niu, B. Equitable partition of graphs into induced linear forests. J. Comb. Optim. 2020, 39, 581–588. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  6. Zhang, H.; Zhang, X. Theoretical aspects of equitable partition of networks into sparse modules. Theor. Comput. Sci. 2021, 871, 51–61. [Google Scholar]
  7. Zhang, X.; Zhang, H.; Niu, B.; Li, B. Fast algorithm of equitably partitioning degenerate graphs into graphs with lower degeneracy. Theor. Comput. Sci. 2022, 905, 18–30. [Google Scholar]
  8. Shioura, A.; Yagiura, M. A fast algorithm for computing a nearly equitable edge coloring with balanced conditions. J. Graph Algorithms Appl. 2010, 14, 391–407. [Google Scholar]
  9. Alberson, M. Chromatic number, independent ratio, and crossing number. Ars Math. Contemp. 2008, 1, 1–6. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  10. Meyer, W. Equitable coloring. Am. Math. Mon. 1973, 80, 920–922. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  11. Erdős, P. Extremal problems in graph theory. In Theory of Graphs and Its Applications; Fielder, M., Ed.; Czech Academy of Sciences: Prague, Czech Republic, 1964; p. 159. [Google Scholar]
  12. Hajnal, A.; Szemerédi, E. Proof of a conjecture of P. Erdős. In Combinatorial Theory and Its Applications; Rényi, A., Sós, V.T., Eds.; NorthHolland: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 1970; Volume 2, pp. 601–623. [Google Scholar]
  13. Kierstead, H.A.; Kostochka, A.V.; Mydlarz, M.; Szemerédi, E. A fast algorithm for equitable coloring. Combinatorica 2010, 30, 217–224. [Google Scholar]
  14. Chen, B.L.; Lih, K.W.; Wu, P.L. Equitable coloring and the maximum degree. Eur. J. Comb. 1994, 15, 443–447. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  15. Kierstead, H.A.; Kostochka, A.V. Every 4-colorable graph with maximum degree 4 has an equitable 4-coloring. J. Graph Theory 2012, 71, 31–48. [Google Scholar]
  16. Chen, B.L.; Lih, K.W. Equitable coloring of trees. J. Comb. Theory Ser. B 1994, 61, 83–87. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  17. Lih, K.W.; Wu, P.L. On equitable coloring of bipartite graphs. Discret. Math. 1996, 151, 155–160. [Google Scholar]
  18. Kostochka, A.V. Equitable colorings of outerplanar graph. Discret. Math. 2002, 258, 373–377. [Google Scholar]
  19. Kostochka, A.V.; Nakprasit, K. Equitable colorings of d-degenerate graphs. Comb. Probab. Comput. 2003, 12, 53–60. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  20. Wang, W.F.; Zhang, K.M. Equitable colorings of line graphs and complete r-partite graphs. Syst. Sci. Math. Sci. 2000, 13, 190–194. [Google Scholar]
  21. Zhang, Y.; Yap, H.P. Equitable colorings of planar graphs. J. Comb. Math. Comb. Comput. 1998, 27, 97–105. [Google Scholar]
  22. Nakprasit, K. Equitable colorings of planar graphs with maximum degree at least nine. Discret. Math. 2012, 312, 1019–1024. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  23. Kostochka, A.; Lin, D.; Xiang, Z. Equitable coloring of planar graphs with maximum degree at least eight. arXiv 2023, arXiv:2305.12041. [Google Scholar]
  24. Zhu, J.L.; Bu, Y.H. Equitable list colorings of planar graphs without short cycles. Theor. Comput. Sci. 2008, 407, 21–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  25. Wang, W.F.; Gui, H. Equitable coloring of planar graphs without 4-and 5-cycles. J. Zhejiang Norm. Univ. 2014, 37, 1–6. (In Chinese) [Google Scholar]
  26. Zhang, X. On equitable colorings of sparse graphs. Bull. Malays. Math. Sci. Soc. 2016, 39, 257–268. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  27. Zhang, X.; Wang, H.J.; Xu, L. Equitable Coloring of Three Classes of 1-planar Graphs. Acta Math. Appl. Sin. Engl. Ser. 2018, 34, 362–372. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  28. Tan, X. Equitable coloring of planar graphs without 3- and 4-cycles. Sci. Technol. Eng. 2010, 10, 6607–6609+6627. (In Chinese) [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Huang, D.; Wu, X. Equitable Coloring of IC-Planar Graphs with Girth g ≥ 7. Axioms 2023, 12, 822. https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms12090822

AMA Style

Huang D, Wu X. Equitable Coloring of IC-Planar Graphs with Girth g ≥ 7. Axioms. 2023; 12(9):822. https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms12090822

Chicago/Turabian Style

Huang, Danjun, and Xianxi Wu. 2023. "Equitable Coloring of IC-Planar Graphs with Girth g ≥ 7" Axioms 12, no. 9: 822. https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms12090822

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop