Probability of Self-Location in the Framework of the Many-Worlds Interpretation
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Albert’s Setup: Classical Teleportation
Captain Kirk is about to step into the transporter, to beam down to the planet below. He happens to know that the transporter is malfunctioning at the moment—to wit: the transporter is going to make two Kirks on the surface of the planet out of the one that steps in on the ship, each of them dressed in a different color—one blue, one green. Both the Kirks initially arrive on the planet with their eyes closed—and (more generally) with no indication whatever of which particular one of the two Kirks on the planet they are. But each of them knows that they have arrived on the planet, and each one says to himself, correctly, that “there is now some perfectly determinate fact of the matter about which particular one of those two Kirks I am”. And each of them wonders which particular one they might be. And then they open their eyes and find out. So, consider this moment, after they have arrived on the planet but before they have opened their eyes, when each of the Kirks is wondering which particular one of the Kirks he is. Lots of people—a whole academic industry of people—seem to think it makes sense for these Kirks to talk to themselves about “the probability that, when I open my eyes, I will find that I am this particular Kirk or that particular Kirk”, or “the probability that, when I open my eyes, I will see that I am wearing a blue outfit”. And this kind of talk would seem to amount to a way out of the puzzle that I mentioned above—this would seem to offer us a way of talking intelligibly about ‘the probability that I am about to have this experience’ and ‘the probability that I am about to have that experience’ even in circumstances in which I already know absolutely everything about the future physical condition of the world. The idea is that even in circumstances in which I have no ignorance whatsoever about the future objective physical condition of the world, I might still be ignorant—just as these various Kirks are ignorant, when they are standing on the surface of the planet with their eyes closed—about where I am located in it. People call these sorts of probabilities “self-locating” probabilities.
- There is nothing quantum in this setup, but even in this situation, Albert finds discussion of probability confusing. I am interested in the quantum case, but let me first offer a simple operational analysis of this classical case to prepare the ground for the quantum setup.
3. Albert’s Setup: Quantum Teleportation
Imagine (then) that the adventures of Kirk in the transporter correspond to an actual, quantum-mechanical, Everettian splitting. Imagine (that is) a quantum-mechanical measurement—say a measurement of the x-spin of an electron that is initially in an eigenstate of z-spin—whose result is encoded in the color of Kirk’s outfit. Kirk’s outfit is like the pointer on the measuring-device, the color of his outfit is the position of the pointer, and Kirk himself is the sentient observer—and he becomes aware of the outcome of the experiment when he opens his eyes. And the thought is that the quantum-mechanical probability that Kirk will see this or that particular outcome of this measurement is precisely the self-locating probability that “I, Kirk” or “I, among the Kirks”, or whatever it is that I call myself, am going to find, on opening my eyes, that my outfit is this or that particular color.
… For instance, take the time immediately after the [Stern–Gerlach] experiment has been run but before anyone has observed its outcome. At that time, there are two agents in two universes. Each of those agents is about to measure a different outcome, …
- I deny the possibility of talking about two agents at this stage.
… subsequent to a Stern–Gerlach measurement I can know that there is an x-spin-up world and a x-spin-down world but not know which of these two worlds I am in. These self-locating contents are no mere curiosity: for many Everettians they provide the subject matter for objective probabilities in EQM [35,36,37,38,39].
- I argue that in Wilson’s setup, I am in both worlds together, so I cannot ask myself in which world am I. In the literature mentioned by Wilson, there are formal semantic definitions for this question, but I argue that the consideration of this question is improper. For example, the derivation of the Born rule by Sebens and Caroll [39] fails if the question lacks operational meaning for alternatives (see [32,40] and other discussions of the Sebens–Caroll proof [41,42]).
4. Against a Spacetime Worms View of Agents
We can, if we wish, adopt the Lewis criterion for personal identity in Everettian contexts, in which case there are (in that sense) two persons prior to measurement. We could even give these two persons names, say and , so that refers to the person who sees ‘up’ and refers to the person who sees ‘down’. If I walk into the lab and ask “What result is she about to see?”, I might be told “ will see ‘up’ and will see ‘down’, and at the moment and coincide”.
- Saunders and Wallace [35] even claim that we can adopt Lewis’s approach that there are two persons present before branching not only for divergent worlds, but also for branching worlds:
… it is now rather clear, from [35] (Section 2), what we are ignorant of: we do not know which world—which branch, the big bang to the end-of-time—is ours. It is lack of knowledge de se, uncertainty of where we are located, not as a stage S but as a world-stage or world-time , among the branching worlds. Ignorance on this score makes rather obvious sense in the case of diverging worlds, and now we are in a position to see that it makes just as much sense, in our semantics, in the case of branching worlds.
5. Modified Quantum Teleportation and Albert’s Conclusions
I was puzzled by this particular role that spatial position is supposed to play. If branches have decohered, why can’t other properties play this role of differentiating the two agents? Imagine, for instance, the following scenario: although Kirk is unaware of it, mosquitoes on this planet are attracted by the color blue. Blue Kirk hears a mosquito flying around, while Green Kirk hears nothing. There is clearly a difference in their mental state, so these are two different agents at the same spatial location, but being unaware of the attraction of mosquitoes, they are also unaware of the measurement outcome.
- In the semantics of [32] this type of situation corresponds to “tainted self-location uncertainty”. There are two Kirks and they have self-location uncertainty, but it is of the trivial kind, different from uncertainties discussed here and in Albert’s lecture. Contrary to the situation in my modified setup, Kirks are ignorant of an objective relevant fact: the biological property of mosquitoes.
We should not say, and the science of such probabilities should not aspire to say, that this or that theory of the assignment of self-locating probabilities is well confirmed by experiment, or that there are good reasons to believe it, or that it is true or false of the world. What we should say, and all that the science of such probabilities should aspire to say, is that the theory in question is well confirmed for me by experiment, and that there are good reasons for me to believe it, and that it is true or false of the world that is centered on myself…
- Albert considers this conclusion outrageous:
…the important thing to say is that, if probabilities like these are supposed to play a central role in scientific explanations, if probabilities like these are supposed to play the role for example of quantum mechanical chances, then this way of thinking is going to radically diminish the traditional objective realistic aspirations of the scientific project, and the question is why in the world we would even want to fool around with crazy sh*t like this, when there are sensible and workable and flat-footedly mechanical ways of solving the measurement problem on the table…
6. Quantitative Analysis: The Born Rule
7. Conclusions
As the case study shows, postulating self-locating probability in physics is like opening a Pandora’s box: it is full of conceptual difficulties. We may wonder whether it is appropriate to allow self-locating postulates in physics
- I believe that these difficulties appear when we use an abstract approach to science considering a wide range of metaphysical options. I argue that if we limit ourselves to standard practice in physics grounded in operational meaning, this concept is useful and even necessary. The confusion, controversy, and paradox of the probability of self-location follow from the formal concept of “self”. Considering “self” as an entity which is local in space, local in time, and which is macroscopically different from any other self (possibly only due to location in space) allows a satisfactory concept of probability of self-location which keeps the nontrivial feature of having subjective ignorance of self-location without ignorance about the state of the universe.
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Bohm, D. A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory in terms of “hidden” variables. I. Phys. Rev. 1952, 85, 166. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Aharonov, Y.; Cohen, E.; Landsberger, T. The Two-Time Interpretation and macroscopic time-reversibility. Entropy 2017, 19, 111. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Aharonov, Y.; Bergmann, P.G.; Lebowitz, J.L. Time symmetry in the quantum process of measurement. Phys. Rev. 1964, 134, B1410–B1416. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sharp, W.D.; Shanks, N. The rise and fall of Time-Symmetrized quantum mechanics. Philos. Sci. 1993, 60, 488–499. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cohen, O. Pre-and postselected quantum systems, counterfactual measurements, and consistent histories. Phys. Rev. A 1995, 51, 4373. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vaidman, L. Defending Time-Symmetrized counterfactuals in quantum theory. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. Part B Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 1999, 30, 373–397. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vaidman, L. Validity of the Aharonov-Bergmann-Lebowitz rule. Phys. Rev. A 1998, 57, 2251. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vaidman, L. Derivations of the Born rule. In Quantum, Probability, Logic: The Work and Influence of Itamar Pitowsky; Hemmo, M., Shenkar, O., Eds.; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Germany, 2020; Chapter 26; pp. 567–584. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Earman, J. A Primer on Determinism; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1986; Available online: https://books.google.co.il/books?id=hsYmMZCmqOUC (accessed on 30 March 2025).
- Everett, H. “Relative state” formulation of quantum mechanics. Rev. Mod. Phys. 1957, 29, 454. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tappenden, P. Evidence and uncertainty in Everett’s multiverse. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2011, 62, 99–123. Available online: https://www.journals.uchicago.edu/doi/10.1093/bjps/axq006 (accessed on 30 March 2025). [CrossRef]
- Egan, A.; Titelbaum, M.G. Self-Locating Beliefs. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Winter 2022 ed.; Zalta, E.N., Nodelman, U., Eds.; Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2022; Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2022/entries/self-locating-beliefs/ (accessed on 30 March 2025).
- Isaacs, Y.; Hawthorne, J.; Sanford Russell, J. Multiple universes and self-locating evidence. Philos. Rev. 2022, 131, 241–294. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lewis, P.J.; Fallis, D. Simulation and self-location. Synthese 2023, 202, 180. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Adlam, E. Against Self-Location. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2024. accepted. Available online: https://www.journals.uchicago.edu/doi/abs/10.1086/732908?journalCode=bjps (accessed on 30 March 2025).
- Elga, A. Self-locating belief and the Sleeping Beauty problem. Analysis 2000, 60, 143–147. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lewis, D. Sleeping Beauty: Reply to Elga. Analysis 2001, 61, 171–176. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Elga, A. Defeating Dr. Evil with self-locating belief. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2004, 69, 383–396. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lewis, P.J. Quantum Sleeping Beauty. Analysis 2007, 67, 59–65. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Papineau, D.; Durà-Vilà, V. A thirder and an Everettian: A reply to Lewis’s ‘Quantum Sleeping Beauty’. Analysis 2009, 69, 78–86. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Peterson, D. Qeauty and the books: A response to Lewis’s Quantum Sleeping Beauty problem. Synthese 2011, 181, 367–374. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bradley, D. Confirmation in a branching world: The Everett interpretation and Sleeping Beauty. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2011, 62, 323–342. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bradley, D. Four problems about self-locating belief. Philos. Rev. 2012, 121, 149–177. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Groisman, B.; Hallakoun, N.; Vaidman, L. The measure of existence of a quantum world and the Sleeping Beauty Problem. Analysis 2013, 73, 695–706. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wilson, A. Everettian Confirmation and Sleeping Beauty. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2014, 65. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Widstam, J. Everettian Illusion of Probability and Its Implications for Doomsday and Sleeping Beauty. Master’s Thesis, Chalmers University of Technology, Gothenburg, Sweden, 2020. Available online: https://hdl.handle.net/20.500.12380/300787 (accessed on 30 March 2025).
- Albert, D. Worries About Accounts of Probability in Everettian Understandings of Quantum Mechanics. In Foundations of Physics, Harvard University Seminar Series; Barandes, J., Ed.; Harvard University: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2022; Available online: https://harvardfop.jacobbarandes.com/previous-events/20200818mw (accessed on 30 March 2025).
- Lewis, D. Attitudes de dicto and de se. Philos. Rev. 1979, 88, 513–543. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tappenden, P. Objective probability and the mind-body relation. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. Part B Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 2017, 57, 8–16. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- De Finetti, B. La prévision: Ses lois logiques, ses sources subjectives. Annales de l’institut Henri Poincaré 1937, 7, 1–68. [Google Scholar]
- Vaidman, L. Wave function realism and three dimensions. In Quantum Mechanics and Fundamentality: Naturalizing Quantum Theory Between Scientific Realism and Ontological Indeterminacy; Springer: Cham, Germany, 2022; pp. 195–209. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McQueen, K.J.; Vaidman, L. In defence of the self-location uncertainty account of probability in the many-worlds interpretation. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. Part B Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 2019, 66, 14–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Titelbaum, M.G. Ten reasons to care about the Sleeping Beauty problem. Philos. Compass 2013, 8, 1003–1017. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wilson, A. Fundamentality and levels in Everettian quantum mechanics. In Quantum Mechanics and Fundamentality: Naturalizing Quantum Theory Between Scientific Realism and Ontological Indeterminacy; Springer: Cham, Germany, 2022; pp. 397–415. [Google Scholar]
- Saunders, S.; Wallace, D. Branching and uncertainty. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2008, 59, 293–305. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Saunders, S. Chance in the Everett interpretation. In Many Worlds?: Everett, Quantum Theory, & Reality; Saunders, S., Barrett, J., Kent, A., Wallace, D., Eds.; OUP: Oxford, UK, 2010; pp. 397–415. [Google Scholar]
- Wallace, D. The Emergent Multiverse: Quantum Theory According to the Everett Interpretation; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Wilson, A. Objective probability in Everettian quantum mechanics. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2013, 64, 709–737. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sebens, C.T.; Carroll, S.M. Self-locating Uncertainty and the Origin of Probability in Everettian Quantum Mechanics. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2018, 69, 25–74. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kent, A. Does it make sense to speak of self-locating uncertainty in the universal wave function? Remarks on Sebens and Carroll. Found. Phys. 2015, 45, 211–217. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dawid, R.; Friederich, S. Epistemic separability and Everettian branches: A critique of Sebens and Carroll. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2022, 73, 711–721. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ney, A. The Argument from Locality for Many Worlds Quantum Mechanics. J. Philos. 2023. forthcoming. [Google Scholar]
- Vaidman, L. On schizophrenic experiences of the neutron or why we should believe in the many-worlds interpretation of quantum theory. Int. Stud. Philos. Sci. 1998, 12, 245–261. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Greaves, H. Understanding Deutsch’s probability in a deterministic multiverse. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. Part B Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 2004, 35, 423–456. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wilhelm, I. Centering the Born Rule. Quantum Rep. 2023, 5, 311–324. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Saunders, S. Time, quantum mechanics, and probability. Synthese 1998, 114, 373–404. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wallace, D. Epistemology quantized: Circumstances in which we should come to believe in the Everett interpretation. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2006, 57, 655–689. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lewis, P.J. Uncertainty and probability for branching selves. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. Part B Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 2007, 38, 1–14. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Albert, D.; Loewer, B. Interpreting the many worlds interpretation. Synthese 1988, 77, 195–213. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Liao, S.y. What are centered worlds? Philos. Q. 2012, 62, 294–316. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vaidman, L. Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Zalta, E.N., Ed.; Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Deutsch, D. Quantum theory of probability and decisions. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. Ser. A Math. Phys. Eng. Sci. 1999, 455, 3129–3137. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wallace, D. How to prove the Born rule. In Many Worlds?: Everett, Quantum Theory, & Reality; Saunders, S., Barrett, J., Kent, A., Wallace, D., Eds.; OUP: Oxford, UK, 2010; pp. 227–263. [Google Scholar]
- Saunders, S. Branch-counting in the Everett interpretation of quantum mechanics. Proc. R. Soc. A 2021, 477, 20210600. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Saunders, S. Finite frequentism explains quantum probability. In Oxford Philosophy of Science; Oxford University: Oxford, UK, 2024; Available online: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=M9K090onB1E (accessed on 30 March 2025).
- Saunders, S. Finite frequentism explains quantum probability. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2024. accepted. Available online: https://www.journals.uchicago.edu/doi/10.1086/731544 (accessed on 30 March 2025).
- Khawaja, J. Conquering mount Everett: Branch counting versus the Born Rule. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2023. accepted. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Putnam, H. A philosopher looks at quantum mechanics (again). Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2005, 56, 615–634. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Builes, D. Center indifference and skepticism. Noûs 2024, 58, 778–798. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Short, A.J. Probability in many-worlds theories. Quantum 2023, 7, 971. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vaidman, L. Probability in the many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics. In Probability in Physics; Ben Menahem, Y., Hemmo, M., Eds.; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2011; pp. 299–311. [Google Scholar]
- Zurek, W.H. Probabilities from entanglement, Born’s rule pk=|ψk|2 from envariance. Phys. Rev. A—Atomic Mol. Opt. Phys. 2005, 71, 052105. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wallace, D. Quantum probability from subjective likelihood: Improving on Deutsch’s proof of the probability rule. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. Part B Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 2007, 38, 311–332. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Valentini, A.; Westman, H. Dynamical origin of quantum probabilities. Proc. R. Soc. A Math. Phys. Eng. Sci. 2005, 461, 253–272. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chen, E.K. Time’s arrow and self-locating probability. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2022, 105, 533–563. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Vaidman, L. Probability of Self-Location in the Framework of the Many-Worlds Interpretation. Entropy 2025, 27, 416. https://doi.org/10.3390/e27040416
Vaidman L. Probability of Self-Location in the Framework of the Many-Worlds Interpretation. Entropy. 2025; 27(4):416. https://doi.org/10.3390/e27040416
Chicago/Turabian StyleVaidman, Lev. 2025. "Probability of Self-Location in the Framework of the Many-Worlds Interpretation" Entropy 27, no. 4: 416. https://doi.org/10.3390/e27040416
APA StyleVaidman, L. (2025). Probability of Self-Location in the Framework of the Many-Worlds Interpretation. Entropy, 27(4), 416. https://doi.org/10.3390/e27040416