A Kantian Response to the Problem of Evil: Living in the Moral World
Abstract
:1. Overview
My commitment to atheism is only as strong as the soundness and validity of my argument. Undercut my argument and proof, at least in my case, no more atheist.1
- There is an all good, all powerful God. (This is assumed for the sake of argument by both Mackie and Plantinga).
- If there is an all good, all powerful God, then necessarily he would be adhering to Moral Evil Prevention Requirements I–III.
- If God were adhering to Moral Evil Prevention Requirements I–III, then necessarily significant and especially horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions would not be obtaining through what would have to be his permission.
- Significant and especially horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions do obtain all around us, which, if God exists, would have to be through his permission. (This is assumed by both Mackie and Plantinga).
- Therefore, it is not the case that there is an all good, all powerful God.The three Moral Evil Prevention requirements in turn, quoting Sterba, are as follows:
- Moral evil prevention requirement IPrevent rather than permit significant and especially horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions without violating anyone’s rights (a good to which we have a right) when that can easily be done.
- Moral evil prevention requirement IIDo not permit rather than prevent significant and especially horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions simply to provide other rational beings with goods they would morally prefer not to have.
- Moral evil prevention requirement IIIDo not permit rather than prevent significant and especially horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions (which would violate someone’s rights) in order to provide such goods when there are countless morally unobjectionable ways of providing those goods.2
- It ought to be the case that being moral is met with proportionate happiness.
- Such a world is one where the Moral Evil Prevention Requirements I–III hold.
- Where knowledge is limited, practical reason enjoys freedom to hold-things-for-true.
- In the world that appears, being moral is not met with proportionate happiness, such that in the world that appears, the Moral Evil Prevention Requirements I–III do not obtain.
- What appears is not fundamental.
- Practical reason is entitled to believe in a moral realm (from 3), wherein the Moral Evil Prevention Requirements I–III do obtain. Such a fundamental moral realm is one where God does adhere to the Moral Evil Prevention Requirements I–III.
- Therefore, the argument from the Moral Evil Prevention Requirements I–III does not provide a necessary argument for the non-existence of God.
- (i)
- To show that the required Kantian ‘outlandish’ assumptions involve affirming something that is indeed logically impossible. In this way, the claim that the existence of God is logically impossible will still stand.
- (ii)
- To qualify and nuance the scope of the argument for the logical impossibility of the existence of God, by specifying that it applies only to the world on a more or less ‘common—sense’ conception of what the world consists of, where apparent spatio-temporal facts and events are, more—or-less, as they appear to be.
- (a)
- Such logical arguments do assume the common-sense preservation requirement.
- (b)
- Such logical arguments do not assume the common-sense preservation requirement.In either case, we have an interesting result. If (a), we face the problem that this is not a neutral requirement, particularly in relation to religious belief. If (b), how are we to go forward? Do we need, in each particular case, to show that the violation of the common-sense preservation requirement amounts to a logical impossibility? This is quite a different project from the one we started out with. The other alternative might be to abandon the claim that this is so austerely an argument about logical impossibility, but that we need not insist on ‘common-sense’ in a way that so flatly excludes much religious belief and instinct. Perhaps we could frame something along the following lines:
- (c)
- Such logical arguments work alongside most plausible and non-extravagant ontologies, although may not work with more ‘extreme’ or ‘outlandish’ metaphysical positions.With (c), of course, the hard-work has only just begun, of specifying the bounds and limits of a plausible and non-extravagant ontology.An even more radical response would be to give up on the claim to demonstrate the ‘logical impossibility’ of the existence of God, and ‘merely’ to argue that the existence of God is impossible, given widely held assumptions about the epistemological status of statements about reality that are based upon how the world appears to us, which, although plausible, are not logically indubitable. The burden of proof is then thrown back onto the Kantian (or to whoever is defending a perspective that goes beyond ‘common-sense’). But, this would come at some cost to anyone, including Sterba, who is eager to insist on the logically impossibility of the existence of God. In relation to this distinctive claim, response (d) amounts to a significant concession, and a retreat, albeit a dignified one.
2. The Kantian Picture
- (1)
- The ‘inner value’ of the world is freedom, and nothing else. Freedom means: setting ends for yourself, without being impacted upon by anything external to you. Other things may be admirable, or impressive, but they lack this value.
- (2)
- Reason is a larger category than knowledge. There is far more that we can have rational beliefs about, than we can know about. This means that Kant would not recognise the ultimate validity of a debate between ‘faith and reason’: because faith, religious belief (Glaube), is entirely within the stretch of reason, even though it goes beyond the bounds of knowledge.
- (3)
- Thinking about the ‘conditions of possibility’ of something can expand your knowledge, and your set of rational beliefs. Consider: if you know something, or have a rational belief about something, you can then ask, ‘what else must be the case, or, what else do I need to believe, in order to make this possible?’. You then have warrant for affirming, for ‘holding-for-true’, whatever comes out of this conceptual investigation. You might not know it, but, as we have seen, from the second principle, knowledge is not everything. There is a caveat here: anything you come up with must not contradict something that you know. But that is a fairly minimal test, precisely because we do not know very much.
- (4)
- Kant thinks in a way that is big and binary. His philosophy tends to lead us to a crossroads, where he finds that everything (created and uncreated) is either this way or that way, where what is offered is an entire package, a whole and encompassing world-view. In relation to the question of morality and freedom the options are these: we either live in a ‘moral world’ where freedom is possible, or, we live in a world of mechanistic determinism, where freedom and morality are impossible. The former world has value, the latter world is a ‘mere desert’, entirely without value. Kant finds that we can, indeed, must rationally believe that the entire and whole world is undergirded by freedom, and not mechanism, and so, that it is a world with value.
The actions here in the world are mere Schemata of the intelligible [actions]; yet these appearances (this word already signifies “schema”) are still interconnected in accordance with empirical laws, even if one regards reason itself, in accordance with its expressons, as a phaenomenon (of the character). But what the cause of this may be we do not discover in phaenomenis. Insofar as one cognizes one’s own character only from the phaenomenis, one imputes it to oneself, although it is, to be sure, itself determined by external causes. If one knew it in itself, then all good and evil would not be ascribed to external causes but only to the subject alone, together with the good and the disadvantageous consequences. In the intelligible world nothing happens and nothing changes, and there the rule of causal connection disappears.(R 5612)
- It ought to be the case that being moral is met with proportionate happiness.(Principle 1, but slightly developed—acting freely is the inner value of the world, and the highest expression of freedom is autonomy, which involves acting according to the moral law).
- Such a world is one where the Moral Evil Prevention Requirements I–III hold.
- Where knowledge is limited, practical reason enjoys freedom to hold-things-for-true. (Principles 2, 3 and 4)
- It is not the case that in the world that appears, being moral is met with proportionate happiness, such that in the world that appears, the Moral Evil Prevention Requirements I–III do not obtain.
- What appears is not fundamental. (Principle 4)
- Practical reason is entitled to believe in a moral realm (from 3 above), wherein the Moral Evil Prevention Requirements I–III do obtain. Such a fundamental moral realm is one where God does adhere to the Moral Evil Prevention Requirements I–III. (Principles 2 and 3).
- Therefore, the argument from the Moral Evil Prevention Requirements I–III does not provide a necessary argument for the non-existence of God.
3. Kant’s ‘Moral Proof’
4. A ‘Need, a Problem, and a Solution’ in the Second Critique
4.1. The Need of Practical Reason
In the highest good which is practical for us, that is, to be made real through our will, virtue and happiness are thought as necessarily combined, so that the one cannot be assumed by pure practical reason without the other also belonging to it.(CPrR, 5: 114)
In the practical task of pure reason, that is, in the necessary pursuit of the highest good, such a connection is postulated as necessary: we ought to strive to promote the highest good (which must therefore be possible).(CPrR, 5: 125)
4.2. The Problem
No necessary connection of happiness with virtue in the world, adequate to the highest good, can be expected from the most meticulous observance of moral laws.(CPrR, 5: 114)
4.3. The Solution
In the antinomy of pure speculative reason there is a similar conflict [to the practical antinomy] between natural necessity and freedom in the causality of events in the world. It was resolved by showing that there is no true conflict if the events and even the world in which they occur are regarded (and they should also be so regarded) merely as appearances; for, one and the same acting being as appearance (even to his own inner sense) has a causality in the world of sense that always conforms to the mechanism of nature, but with respect to the same event, insofar as the acting person regards himself at the same time as nouemenon (as pure intelligence, in his existence that cannot be temporally determined), he can contain a determining ground of that causality in accordance with laws of nature which is itself free from all laws of nature.(CPrR, 5: 114)
For it is practically possible, and the maxims of such a will, which refer to it as regards their matter, have objective reality, which at first was threatened by that antinomy in the combination of morality with happiness in accordance with a universal law, but only from a misinterpretation, because the relation between appearances was held to be a relation of things in themselves to those appearances.(CPrR, 5: 115)
5. Concluding Reflections
- the success of transcendental style arguments at generating justified beliefs.
- the ability of practical reason to move beyond the limits of knowledge.
- the ability of practical reason, when moving beyond such limits, to think in entire systems and world-views.
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | |
2 | Sterba, ‘Is a good god logically possible?’, 2, 4. |
3 | |
4 | |
5 | Influential ‘metaphysical’ readers of Kant include Karl Ameriks, Rae Langton, Desmond Hogan, and Andrew Chignell. More deflationary commentors include figures such as Henry Allison and Andrews Reath. A previous generation of commentators, represented by Peter Strawson, tended to read Kant as having metaphysical commitments, but in a way that was thoroughly disreputable and contrary to the deepest principles of his thought. |
6 | Commentators who read Kant as attempting, but often failing, to express a philosophical Lutheranism, combining elements of Platonic theological rationalism, include Palmquist, Pasternack, Wood, Kain, Marina, and Kanterian. |
7 | See, for example, Walker (1978, p. 149). |
8 | |
9 | |
10 | |
11 | |
12 | |
13 | |
14 | Onora O’Neill ‘Kant on Reason and Religion’. |
15 | |
16 | |
17 | |
18 | John Silber’s defends Kant’s notion of the highest good, by claiming that it adds content to the moral law, such that the maxim to promote happiness in proportion to virtue is itself a categorical imperative. Silber argues that the concept of the highest good does vital work in Kant’s system, providing a material end (happiness in proportion to virtue), to what –Silber regards– would otherwise be Kant’s empty formalism. See Silber (1959a, 1959b, 1963). For more recent contributions to the so-called ‘Silber-Beck’ controversy see Mariña (2000), and Friedman (1984). Lawrence Pasternack’s important article, ‘Restoring Kant’s Conception of the Highest Good’, effectively cuts through some of the knots in the Silber-Beck controversy, pointing out, for example, that our contribution to the highest good need not be that of distributing happiness in proportion with morality (which only God can do), but of making ourselves worthy of the happiness that is so distributed, see esp. pp. 447–49. |
19 | See Wood (1970, chps. 1 and 5), Beiser (2002, pp. 588–629). In some of his suggestions, Pasternack also seems to back the notion of the highest good supporting our motivation: see Michalson (2014), and Pasternack (2017). |
20 | For a fuller articulation of what is summarised here, see Kant and the Divine, chps. 11–12, and ‘The Irreducible Importance of Religious Hope in Kant’s Conception of the Highest Good’. |
21 | For a fuller account, which draws on a wide range of Kant’s texts, see Kant and the Divine, chp. 11. |
22 | See Kant and the Divine, chps. 10–13. |
23 |
References
Kant Texts
References to Kant, with the exception of the Critique of Pure Reason, refer to the Akademie edition, Kants gesammelte Schriften, edited by the Royal Prussian (later German) Academy of Sciences (Berlin: Georg Reimer, later Walter de Gruyter and Co., 1900-). These references are cited by volume: page number, and are prefaced by an abbreviation of the title of the work, as set out below. Citations to the first Critique are to the first (‘A’) or second (‘B’) edition. The translations referred to are those provided in The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant ed. by Paul Guyer and Allen Wood (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992-).- CPrR
- Kritik der praktischen Vernunft (1788). Critique of Practical Reason in Immanuel Kant: Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008), trans. and ed. by Mary J. Gregor, 5: 3–309.
- R
- Reflexionen (1753–1804). Reflections, in Notes and Fragments, ed. by Paul Guyer, trans. by Curtis Bowman, Paul Guyer, Frederick Rauscher (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 17: 229–19: 654.
- Rel
- Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der Bloβen Vernunft (1794). Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason, in Immanuel Kant: Religion and Rational Theology, trans. and ed. by Allen W. Wood and George di Giovanni (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 6: 3–202.
Other Texts
- Augustine, Saint. 1998. The City of God against the Pagans. Edited by Robert Dyson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Bks. 13–14. [Google Scholar]
- Auxter, Thomas. 1979. The Unimportance of Kant’s Highest Good. Journal of the History of Philosophy 17: 121–34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Beck, Lewis White. 1960. A Commentary on Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, Phoenix Books, pp. 244–45. [Google Scholar]
- Beiser, Frederick. 2002. The Cambridge Companion to Kant and Modern Philosophy. Edited by Paul Guyer. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 588–629. [Google Scholar]
- Friedman, R. Zev. 1984. The Importance and Function of Kant’s Highest Good. Journal of the History of Philosophy 22: 325–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Insole, Christopher J. 2011a. Intellectualism, Relational Properties and the Divine Mind in Kant’s Pre-Critical Philosophy. Kantian Review 16: 399–428. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Insole, Christopher J. 2011b. Kant’s Transcendental Idealism and Newton’s Divine Sensorium. Journal of the History of Ideas 72: 413–36. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Insole, Christopher J. 2013. Kant and the Creation of Freedom: A Theological Problem. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Insole, Christopher J. 2015a. A Thomistic Reading of Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: Searching for the Unconditioned. Modern Theology 31: 284–311. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Insole, Christopher J. 2015b. The Intolerable God: Kant’s Theological Journey. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans. [Google Scholar]
- Insole, Christopher J. 2016. Kant on Christianity, Religion, and Politics: Three Hopes, Three Limits. Studies in Christian Ethics 29: 14–33. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Insole, Christopher J. 2019a. Free Belief: The Medieval Heritage in Kant’s Moral Faith. Journal of the History of Philosophy 57: 501–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Insole, Christopher J. 2019b. Kant, Divinity, and Autonomy. Studies in Christian Ethics 32: 470–84. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Insole, Christopher J. 2020. Kant and the Divine: From Contemplation to the Moral Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Janz, Paul. 2009. God, the Mind’s Desire: Reference, Reason, and Christian Thinking. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mariña, Jacqueline. 2000. Making Sense of Kant’s Highest Good. Kant-Studien 91: 329–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Michalson, Gordon. 2014. Fallen Freedom: Kant on Radical Evil and Moral Regeneration. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Murphy, Jeffrie G. 1966. The Highest Good as Content for Kant’s Ethical Formalism. Kant-Studien 56: 102–10. [Google Scholar]
- Pasternack, Lawrence. 2017. Restoring Kant’s Conception of the Highest Good. Journal of the History of Philosophy 55: 435–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pasternak, Lawrence. 2014. Kant on Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason. London and New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Pogge, Thomas. 1997. Kant on Ends and the Meaning of Life. In Reclaiming the History of Ethics. Edited by Andrews Reath, Barbara Herman and Christine Korsgaard. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 361–87. [Google Scholar]
- Rawls, John. 1980. Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory. The Journal of Philosophy 77: 515–72. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Reath, Andrews, Barbara Herman, and Christine Korsgaard. 1997. Reclaiming the History of Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Silber, John R. 1959a. Kant’s Conception of the Highest Good as Immanent and Transcendent. The Philosophical Review 68: 469–92. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Silber, John R. 1959b. The Copernican Revolution in Ethics: The Good Re-examined. Kant-Studien 51: 85–101. [Google Scholar]
- Silber, John R. 1963. The Importance of the Highest Good in Kant’s Ethics. Ethics 73: 179–95. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sterba, James. 2019. Is a Good God Logically Possible? London and New York: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Sterba, James. 2020. Is a good god logically possible? International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 87: 203–8. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Velkley, Richard. 1989. Freedom and the End of Reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 152–53. [Google Scholar]
- Walker, Ralph. 1978. Kant. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, p. 149. [Google Scholar]
- Wood, Allen. 1970. Kant’s Moral Religion. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, chps. 1&5. [Google Scholar]
- Wood, Allen. 1999. Kant’s Ethical Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Insole, C.J. A Kantian Response to the Problem of Evil: Living in the Moral World. Religions 2023, 14, 227. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14020227
Insole CJ. A Kantian Response to the Problem of Evil: Living in the Moral World. Religions. 2023; 14(2):227. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14020227
Chicago/Turabian StyleInsole, Christopher J. 2023. "A Kantian Response to the Problem of Evil: Living in the Moral World" Religions 14, no. 2: 227. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14020227
APA StyleInsole, C. J. (2023). A Kantian Response to the Problem of Evil: Living in the Moral World. Religions, 14(2), 227. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14020227