Next Article in Journal
Teachers’ Professional Digital Competence
Previous Article in Journal
Cuteness and Its Emotional Responses
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Entry

Behaviorally Stretched Microeconomics

Department of Economics, Federal University of Santa Catarina, Florianopolis 88049-970, SC, Brazil
Encyclopedia 2025, 5(3), 147; https://doi.org/10.3390/encyclopedia5030147
Submission received: 4 August 2025 / Revised: 4 September 2025 / Accepted: 11 September 2025 / Published: 14 September 2025
(This article belongs to the Section Behavioral Sciences)

Definition

A common misconception is that behavioral economics rejects microeconomics. This entry explains how behavioral economics, despite challenging core assumptions of rationality, remains fundamentally aligned with the structure of microeconomics. Anchored in the insight that rational market outcomes can emerge even when individual behavior is non-rational, it revisits the explanatory role of constraints in economic theory. Rather than displacing microeconomics, behavioral economics extends it by incorporating bounded rationality while preserving key structural principles. Central to this integration is Say’s law, the macro-level notion that production generates income and thus the capacity for demand. This connection makes microeconomic constraints reflect deeper macroeconomic principles. Even when market behavior is distorted by correlated cognitive biases and their associated positive feedback dynamics—such as herding or bubbles—the fundamental identity that supply generates the income necessary for demand remains intact, provided that adjustments occur over the long run. The analysis also considers how behavioral deviations affect aggregate outcomes. Ultimately, this entry shows that behavioral economics is not a departure from microeconomics but its natural extension: by embedding bounded rationality within the framework of economic constraints, it preserves the structural coherence of microeconomics while adding psychological depth.

1. Introduction: Becker Raises the Curtain

In the foundational paper Irrational Behavior and Economic Theory, Gary Becker [1] argues that the core results of economic theory, especially the downward-sloping demand curve, do not require the assumption of individual rationality. Instead, these results can emerge from a wide variety of behaviors, including non-rational ones, because market responses are shaped by constraints (budgets, prices, income), not necessarily by rational optimization.
This prompts a reassessment of the role that rationality plays in economic theory. Traditional microeconomics assumes that agents are rational, meaning that they maximize a well-ordered utility or profit function. Critics argue that real agents (households and firms) often behave inconsistently, impulsively, or habitually, and thus violate assumptions like transitivity. Becker does not aim to defend rationality per se but to demonstrate that rational outcomes can emerge even under non-rational decision-making.
A clear distinction must be drawn here between markets and individuals. Individual behavior may be erratic and aggregate market behavior is often systematic. Market-level predictions (like negatively sloped demand curves) often hold true even if individuals deviate from rational behavior.
Becker considers two models of non-rational behavior: (1) impulsive behavior, where households choose randomly from their opportunity set, and (2) inertial behavior, where individuals stick to past choices unless forced to change. He shows that even in these extreme cases, the aggregate market demand curve remains downward sloping because changes in relative prices shift the opportunity set, not just optimal points, and the distribution of choices shifts in predictable ways.
The argument is extended from households to firms: even non-rational firms must respect budget (profit) constraints. Becker shows that established results, such as lower output under monopoly than competition, can arise even if firms are not profit maximizers, if their behavior responds to opportunity constraints.
As a general implication, many standard results in economic theory (including demand curves and supply responses) are robust to the assumption of rationality. Rational market behavior may arise from non-rational microbehavior, much like macro-regularities in physics arise from random particle motion.
In conclusion, Becker’s central claim is that the explanatory power of economics lies in constraints, not necessarily in assumptions about mental calculations. He even calls for more rigorous models of non-rational behavior to understand their aggregate implications. This opens the door for subsequent developments like bounded rationality [2] and the emergence of behavioral economics [3]. Individuals may not maximize utility in a strict sense. Instead, they may “satisfice,” follow heuristics and cognitive biases, or act based on habits. Still, constraints (budgets, prices, income) discipline behavior, shaping market-level outcomes. Ultimately, microeconomics could remain valid even when agents are not rational in the traditional sense, so long as they are subject to real-world constraints. In particular, behavioral economics could emerge not as a challenge to microeconomics but as a natural extension of it. Therefore, behavioral economics is also microeconomics: a richer, empirically grounded version that incorporates human psychology without abandoning the foundational role of constraints.
However, while behavioral economics accepts bounded rationality as the norm, it increasingly investigates how aggregate behavior departs from standard microeconomic predictions.
Behavioral economics is closely linked to psychology because it highlights the cognitive processes and biases that shape decision-making. At the same time, its dialogue with microeconomics is essential, since concepts such as rationality and consistency—though often bounded or systematically biased in practice—remain central benchmarks for evaluating behavior. This dual perspective underscores the importance of the topic, as it connects the psychological foundations of choice with the structural logic of economic theory.

2. Bounded Minds, Ordered Markets?

Market mechanisms often aggregate diverse, noisy, and biased behaviors into predictable macro-patterns. For example, price adjustments, arbitrage, and competition can eliminate idiosyncratic errors. Even if many investors are overconfident or loss-averse, the market price of assets may still reflect rational behavior in the aggregate—up to a point.
Recent microeconomic models explore behavioral deviations at the individual level and investigate whether standard economic outcomes still emerge when these behaviors are aggregated through institutions such as markets or firms. In some cases, aggregation fails to restore rational outcomes.
Schwartzstein [4] develops a microeconomic model in which agents exhibit selective attention: they focus only on certain signals when forming beliefs. This limited attention can lead to systematic mislearning, where agents persist in incorrect beliefs even when more accurate information is available. Rather than disappearing in the aggregate, these biases can lead to persistent inefficiencies, especially when learning environments do not incentivize full attention.
Hanna et al. [5] present a model of technological learning in which individuals “learn through noticing.” They selectively attend to certain input dimensions and only learn from the data they choose to observe. They show that even highly experienced agents can remain off the production frontier if they fail to notice key aspects of the data they already possess. Testing this in a field experiment with farmers, the authors find that they consistently overlook pod size as a critical input. Simply providing raw experimental data does not improve their practices; behavioral change occurs only when the information is reorganized into summaries that exhibit previously unattended-to relationships. This shows how attention-based learning failures can persist, and how targeted informational interventions are needed for correcting them.
Mullainathan et al. [6] build a theoretical model of “coarse thinking,” in which individuals simplify complex decision environments by grouping similar but distinct states into broad categories. This form of categorization can make individuals susceptible to persuasion, particularly when a persuader frames information to shift perceptions across categories. The model shows that such persuasion can lead to systematic deviations from rational choice and result in persistent misallocations, especially in markets for financial products, advertising, or political messaging. Unlike models where biases wash out, this framework suggests that coarse thinking can affect aggregate outcomes and firm behavior in predictable ways. In sum, aggregation does not necessarily restore microeconomic regularities in their model; rather, coarse thinking can persistently distort decisions and market outcomes.
Rabin and Schrag [7] craft a formal model of confirmatory bias, where individuals update their beliefs selectively: overweighting information that confirms prior beliefs and underweighting or ignoring disconfirming evidence. This leads to systematic and persistent deviations from Bayesian rationality, which can cause agents to hold incorrect beliefs even after exposure to large amounts of informative data. (Bayesian rationality refers to the normative benchmark where individuals update their beliefs by correctly applying Bayes’ rule, objectively incorporating all available evidence, whether confirming or disconfirming, into their prior beliefs to form accurate posterior beliefs.) While Rabin and Schrag show that confirmatory bias can lead individuals to persistently misinterpret evidence and hold erroneous beliefs, they also suggest that institutional structures, such as markets or organizational mechanisms, can, in some contexts, attenuate these effects by introducing corrective feedback or aggregating diverse beliefs. Thus, although micro-level distortions in belief updating can produce macro-level inefficiencies, these distortions need not preclude rational outcomes in the aggregate, especially when institutional filters are in place. The study illustrates that behavioral deviations may persist, but their influence can be bounded rather than systemically destabilizing.
Sims [8] proposes the theory of rational inattention, in which agents face limits on how much information they can process and therefore must selectively attend to signals. This introduces frictions into decision-making that deviate from the full-information rational agent assumed in neoclassical models. However, these individual-level deviations are not arbitrary; they result from optimal information allocation under cognitive constraints. Importantly, Sims shows that while behavior at the micro level reflects these informational limits, aggregate outcomes can still display predictability, especially when institutions or market mechanisms help diffuse and summarize dispersed information. The model implies that bounded rationality in the form of rational inattention need not undermine the integrity of macro-level patterns, thus suggesting that systematic individual deviations can still give rise to broadly rational outcomes at the aggregate level.
Gabaix [9] develops a formal model of bounded rationality grounded in the concept of rational inattention, where agents optimally choose to ignore certain dimensions of information due to cognitive or informational processing costs. The model introduces sparsity (the idea that individuals process only a subset of available variables) as a structured and tractable deviation from full rationality. Crucially, while individuals behave suboptimally in some respects, their decisions still reflect purposeful trade-offs, and the aggregate behavior retains core economic properties, including demand-supply consistency. Gabaix shows that even under limited attention, macro-level predictions of standard economic models can hold approximately, especially when attention allocation follows systematic patterns. This supports the broader argument that behavioral deviations, when disciplined by constraints and optimization under cognitive limits, do not necessarily undermine market-level rationality. Instead, they extend microeconomics to incorporate more realistic psychological foundations while maintaining aggregate coherence.
Bordalo et al. [10] introduce salience theory to model how individuals make decisions under risk by disproportionately focusing on salient payoffs (those that stand out in a given choice context) rather than processing all outcomes with equal weight. This departure from neoclassical expected utility theory captures systematic behavioral biases such as overreaction to extreme outcomes or underweighting of less prominent information. While these salience-driven choices deviate from rationality at the individual level, the authors suggest that such distortions are predictable. This predictability opens the door for potential correction through market mechanisms or institutional design, although the paper itself does not directly evaluate whether aggregate market outcomes remain rational. Nonetheless, the model illustrates how systematic cognitive biases can be formalized and incorporated within microeconomic theory, further bridging the gap between behavioral insights and traditional economic modeling.
Bordalo et al. [11] extend salience theory to consumer choice, showing how individuals systematically overweight the attributes of goods that stand out in a given context (such as unusually low prices) while underweighting less prominent but equally relevant characteristics. This leads to predictable violations of the neoclassical model of utility maximization, including inconsistent choices across seemingly equivalent frames. Yet these distortions are not random; they follow identifiable patterns based on the relative prominence of product attributes. Although the paper focuses primarily on individual-level deviations from rationality, the structured nature of these biases implies that markets could, under some conditions, anticipate or even neutralize them through pricing strategies, product placement, or competition. The work reinforces the broader point that behavioral anomalies can be rigorously modeled within microeconomic frameworks, even if their aggregate effects depend on the institutional environment and market dynamics.
In sum, these models illustrate that behavioral economics is fundamentally a branch of microeconomics. By introducing psychologically grounded assumptions into models of individual choice, they expand rather than reject traditional frameworks. Standard economic results can still emerge, and the models clarify the conditions under which behavioral deviations persist or dissipate. Rather than displacing microeconomics, behavioral economics enhances it, adding depth through insights about attention, cognition, and informational limits, while preserving its structural coherence.

3. From Becker, Back to Say

Say’s law, or the idea that “supply creates its own demand” can be interpreted as a foundational principle of economics, especially when viewed through the lens of Becker’s emphasis on constraints and opportunity sets rather than on individual optimization.
As seen, the core of Becker’s argument is that the power of economic theory lies not in rational agents per se, but in the fact that all agents, rational or not, face constraints. These constraints shape their behavior and yield predictable market outcomes, even if individual decisions are driven by whim, habit, or inertia.
He writes that “irrational units would often be ‘forced’ by a change in opportunities to respond rationally,” which is another way of saying that behavior is shaped by economic constraints like budget lines and opportunity sets. To deepen the connection, it is necessary to move beyond Becker’s formulation and ask where these constraints originate—an inquiry that leads directly back to Say’s law.
This is akin to asking about the deeper meaning of the budget constraint. The microeconomic budget constraint p1x1 + p2x2 = m states that the total expenditure on goods x1 and x2 (where p1 and p2 are their respective prices) must equal the available income m. This is usually taken as an axiom, a boundary condition for consumer choice. But if we ask why it must hold, we land on something deeper: a general equilibrium condition rooted in the macro-level balance between production and income. This is where Say’s law comes in.
Say’s law, most famously stated as “supply creates its own demand,” is widely misunderstood. It does not mean that everything produced is instantly bought, but rather the ability to demand goods and services is fundamentally constrained by one’s ability to supply goods and services. From this view: production → income → expenditure. When someone produces and sells a good, they earn income, which then becomes purchasing power. Hence, aggregate demand exists because people have first engaged in production. So, in terms of the budget constraint the m (income) is not a mysterious number: it represents what the consumer has contributed to the economy (either through labor, capital, or property) and what the economy has given back as purchasing power. Thus, the budget constraint is a micro-level reflection of Say’s law at the macro level.
A further clarification is warranted regarding the historical misinterpretation of Say’s law. The familiar shorthand “supply creates its own demand” is not a formulation that can be traced directly to Say himself. Rather, it appears to have emerged gradually in the secondary literature as economists—especially in the Keynesian tradition—sought to define Say’s law in opposition to Keynes’s own argument about insufficient aggregate demand. While Keynes in Chapter 2 of The General Theory criticized what he called the “classical” view, he did not himself explicitly reduce Say’s law to the slogan “supply creates its own demand.” Keynes recognized the validity of Say’s law as a long-run principle, but he stressed that relying on it was impractical in the short run. In his view, active measures were necessary to mitigate business cycles rather than simply waiting for the law to eventually assert itself. The simplified version seems instead to have been propagated in mid-20th century textbooks, where it served as a foil for Keynesian theory [12]. This narrowing of Say’s message fostered the impression that Say denied the possibility of crises, a misreading that still lingers in modern teaching. Recognizing this history helps to disentangle Say’s original insight—that production generates the capacity for demand—from later textbook simplifications that cast it as an unrealistically frictionless doctrine.
Having clarified how Say’s law has been misrepresented, we can now return to Becker’s contribution and see how his emphasis on opportunity sets resonates with Say’s structural insight. Becker de-emphasizes utility maximization and instead focuses on how the structure of opportunities (budget sets) determines behavior. This structure, in turn, emerges from market forces governed by production and exchange: the same forces Say emphasized. So, the logic flows like this: Say’s law ensures that in equilibrium, income is backed by production. This gives rise to budget constraints that determine what agents can do, even if they do not know what they want. Becker’s insight is that even if agents are not rational, their behavior will still reflect those constraints. Mental optimization is secondary; constraints are primary.
Say’s law is the principle of indestructibility of purchasing power, and this provides the foundations of economic constraints. Only production generates true purchasing power. As Sowell [13] clarified, one cannot consume without first producing, or receiving income derived from someone else’s production. In this framework, credit does not create purchasing power; it merely anticipates future production, since today’s credit becomes tomorrow’s debt, repayable only through tomorrow’s productive output. Likewise, hoarding does not destroy purchasing power; it simply postpones its use. And crucially, to produce is to generate the means to purchase the product in its entirety, because income is created in the very act of producing. This underlies the fundamental identity in national accounting: output equals income. Thus, supply creates its own demand, not in the sense that every product is automatically sold, but in the logical sense that production generates income, and income constitutes demand. This is the true meaning of Say’s law [13,14] (Ch. 2).
In the long run, only production sustains demand. This principle explains why behavior that is systematically unproductive cannot endure: it fails to regenerate the purchasing power needed to participate in markets. Therefore, economic systems are disciplined by the need to replenish what is consumed.
This logic is fully consistent with Becker’s framework, which emphasizes the role of constraints and opportunity sets over assumptions of perfect rationality. Budget constraints are not mere formalities: they are manifestations of Say’s law. Budget constraints are not just mathematical tools; they are institutional and physical realities. These constraints reflect the limits of available resources, the structure of production, and the reciprocal nature of economic exchange (one receives income by supplying something of value). Even when individuals act non-rationally and follow biased heuristics, as behavioral economics reveals, their choices are still ultimately shaped by these constraints. This explains why markets often produce stable patterns, even when micro-level decision-making is noisy or biased.
Hence, we can conclude that Becker’s point about rational market outcomes under constraints is grounded in Say’s law. Constraints exist because only production sustains the ability to demand. Non-rational agents still operate within a system that demands productive contribution, directly or indirectly, for sustained participation. Markets endure not because agents are perfectly rational, but because the system enforces rationality through real constraints grounded in production.
Of note, it is important to distinguish between irrational and non-rational behavior. While Becker refers to irrationality, our focus is on non-rational behavior, an umbrella term that includes bounded rationality. This distinction is crucial, as behavior that appears non-rational in economic terms may still follow an adaptive logic from an evolutionary standpoint [15]. Although most behavioral economists have moved toward this more nuanced framing, a minority continue to use the term irrational [16]. Even setting aside the evolutionary argument, Kahneman [3] (p. 411, 482n) contends that defining rationality strictly as coherence (full adherence to formal logic) is overly demanding for finite human minds. By such a definition, even reasonable individuals would fail to qualify as rational, though they hardly deserve to be labeled irrational. The term irrational carries connotations of impulsiveness, emotionality, or obstinate refusal to reason. For this reason, bounded rationality has become the more widely accepted concept.
The contribution of this entry lies in bridging behavioral economics with the structural logic of microeconomics by tracing Becker’s constraints-based framework back to Say’s law. This perspective shows that behavioral economics does not undermine microeconomics but extends it: bounded decision-making still unfolds within constraints ultimately generated by production and exchange. By reinterpreting Becker through the lens of Say’s law, the entry shows how psychological deviations interact with the enduring economic reality that production generates income, and income enables demand.

4. When Becker’s Argument Breaks Down

Despite its strength, Becker’s framework does not always hold within behavioral economics. As explored in Section 2, whether non-rational individual behavior aggregates into rational market outcomes remains a subject of ongoing debate. Key factors that challenge this aggregation include systematic cognitive biases (as opposed to random errors), limits to arbitrage and institutional frictions, as well as non-convexities and structural discontinuities.
Becker assumes non-rationality is random (impulses or inertia). But behavioral economics shows that biases are often systematic and correlated across individuals; for example, herding behavior [17], framing effects [18], mental accounting [19], and optimism bias [20]. These biases do not cancel out and can lead to market-level anomalies, such as bubbles, under-saving, and inefficient allocations [21,22,23]. Moreover, markets do not always correct non-rationality if there are frictions, such as sticky prices [24], search costs [25], or if arbitrage is risky or limited [26]. Behavior may also be sticky over time or anchored by social norms and narratives [27,28]. Finally, when opportunity sets are non-convex (due to fixed costs, rationing, or nonlinear tax structures) even small behavioral biases can lead to large, persistent misallocations [29].
To sum up, it is possible to build behavioral models assuming bounded rationality at the individual level while maintaining many core market-level economic insights. Here, Becker’s claim offers a powerful foundation for this dual approach. However, behavioral economics also shows when and why markets fail to “correct” individual biases, and these exceptions are where the field has made its greatest contributions. In that sense, Becker’s legacy lives on in models that carefully separate behavioral assumptions at the micro level from predictions at the macro level, while always testing where aggregation might fail.

5. Bounded Minds, Unbroken Law

If agents are systematically biased and markets can be non-rational, does Say’s law still hold? Logically, yes—it continues to hold, though its effects may only fully manifest once necessary adjustments have occurred. Behavioral deviations may distort market outcomes and create temporary misalignments between supply and demand. Yet these anomalies do not destroy the fundamental identity that output generates income. Say’s law is not about instantaneous market clearing; it is about the macro-consistency of real resource flows.
Behavioral disturbances do not destroy opportunity sets. Behavioral errors may lead to misallocation but not to destruction of purchasing power. Income generated from production still exists, even if misdirected. Say’s law governs the availability of income, not its efficiency of use. Market-level rationality can (hopefully) emerge over time, as resources are gradually reallocated from inefficient to productive uses.
Empirical episodes show the remarkable resilience of markets and the enduring role of economic constraints, even amid intense behavioral disruption. During the dot-com bubble, investor overconfidence and herd behavior led to unsustainable asset valuations. Yet when the bubble burst, capital did not disappear. Instead, it was reallocated to the very technological infrastructure (such as broadband networks, cloud computing, and digital platforms) that would come to define the digital revolution [30]. The misallocation was temporary; the underlying productive capacity found new expression in more sustainable uses.
The 2008 financial crisis was another instance where systematic behavioral biases collided with institutional fragility. Narratives rooted in overconfidence and money illusion fueled reckless lending and borrowing behavior [31]. When these “animal spirits” turned, panic set in and credit markets collapsed. Nevertheless, targeted interventions—ranging from fiscal stimulus and central bank liquidity programs to the recapitalization of banks and reform of financial oversight—eventually restored macroeconomic stability. The market did not self-correct immediately, but the productive base of the economy remained, and coordinated policies redirected resources and expectations.
The COVID-19 pandemic triggered an unprecedented, simultaneous demand and supply shock, driven largely by precautionary behavior, uncertainty, and fear [32]. Yet this disruption did not destroy the productive structure of the economy. Instead, swift and coordinated monetary and fiscal responses helped cushion the blow [33]. Governments deployed stimulus packages, expanded social safety nets, and stabilized credit markets, while firms and workers adapted quickly, shifting to remote work, reconfiguring supply chains, and accelerating digitization. As a result, capital and labor gradually reallocated toward emergent sectors such as e-commerce, health tech, and logistics. Though the behavioral shock was deep, it was not terminal; real value continued to be produced, and demand eventually returned.
These episodes reinforce a central insight of this entry: behavioral distortions can delay equilibrium and disrupt allocation, but they do not permanently undermine the fundamental economic logic that productive activity generates the means for demand. Say’s law is not invalidated by panic or misjudgment; it is deferred. The economy’s ability to recover lies in the persistence of real value creation and the adaptive capacity of markets and institutions. Misaligned expectations and overreactions may dominate in the short term, but given time, policy support, and flexible institutions, the economy reorients toward productive balance. This aligns with recent behavioral–macroeconomic work that integrates heuristics into macro models [34].
Therefore, while Say’s law may ensure eventual realignment between supply and demand, one must not assume that such adjustment is fast or painless, nor lapse into complacency. As Keynes famously argued [35] (Ch. 2), relying solely on long-run equilibrium may come at an intolerably high cost, especially in the depths of a business cycle when waiting for markets to self-correct risks prolonged suffering and economic waste.
Even when correlated errors cause market-level non-rationality, Say’s law is not violated, it is deferred, because production still creates income, and thus the capacity for demand. Misallocation, underconsumption, and bubbles reflect transient mismatches, not a permanent breakdown of the supply-demand linkage. As long as production creates goods and services that represent real value, the economy will eventually find demand through price adjustments, innovation, or crisis-induced resets. This view aligns with Hayek’s [36] perspective that markets function as discovery processes rather than perfect calculators, and with Minsky’s [37] insight that instability is the norm, but does not negate fundamentals.
In the end, the enduring logic of Say’s law lies not in the presumption of perfectly rational agents or frictionless markets, but in the deeper reality that value-creating production necessarily generates the income that enables demand. Even when behavioral distortions (herding, pessimism, exuberance) cloud judgment and delay equilibrium, they do not erase the fundamental economic reciprocity between making and consuming. The mispricing of assets, the hoarding of cash, or the panic-induced collapse of spending may obscure this linkage temporarily, but they do not sever it.
What matters is that production yields something of genuine worth: goods and services that meet real human needs. When that condition is met, demand will eventually surface, whether through price corrections, institutional adaptation, or the catalytic force of crisis. This is the robust core of Say’s law: not a utopian vision of always-efficient markets, but a structural truth about the regenerative power of real economic value. It is an unbroken law that holds even in the presence of bounded minds.

6. From Wisdom to Madness—And Back Again

Markets, like crowds, can be wise—or mad. The central challenge is not merely to marvel at the wisdom of crowds, but to confront their potential for collective irrationality. This section deepens the argument from the previous section: even when systematic behavioral distortions drive market misalignments, Say’s law endures in the long run. Understanding how markets swing between coordination and disorder requires moving beyond the assumption that errors are random and cancel out. Instead, behavioral economics compels us to reckon with correlated errors that accumulate and self-reinforce.
Becker’s original logic followed a chain of error → noise → cancellation, assuming that individual idiosyncrasies would wash out in aggregate. But behavioral patterns often follow a different trajectory: error → correlation → accumulation. When individual behaviors are shaped by similar cognitive biases (such as overconfidence, optimism bias, or framing effects) systematic misjudgments can amplify one another through social contagion, media narratives, or institutional incentives.
This dynamic has been observed in episodes of market exuberance and collapse. Shiller [21] documents how contagious narratives and herd behavior fueled the dot-com and housing bubbles, illustrating how correlated errors can inflate asset prices well beyond fundamentals before abrupt corrections restore equilibrium. Informational cascades and imitation can cause even rational agents to disregard private signals and follow the crowd, compounding collective error [17,38].
Yet, as discussed in the previous section, these behavioral distortions do not refute Say’s law. Misallocation, underconsumption, or bubbles distort the timing and direction of demand, but they do not sever the structural link between supply and income generation. Even when purchasing power is misdirected or underutilized, it remains anchored to the act of production. Hence, Say’s law holds in the long run, as institutional learning, price adjustment, and crisis-induced reallocations realign aggregate outcomes.
The concept of “wisdom of the crowd” is pivotal in bridging the gap between market rationality and collective irrationality. Galton’s [39] famous experiment at a livestock fair showed that aggregating 800 independent guesses about an ox’s weight produced an estimate remarkably close to the actual value, showcasing that collective judgment can surpass individual assessments. Surowiecki [40] reinforced this insight: when individual judgments are diverse, independent, and properly aggregated, crowds can outperform the most knowledgeable individuals.
However, when independence and diversity erode, the crowd’s wisdom collapses into madness. This can happen through informational cascades, herding, or dominant narratives that synchronize expectations. In such settings, errors do not cancel but reinforce, leading to demand surges, valuation bubbles, and abrupt crashes. The paradox is that markets rely on coordination, but excess coordination without diversity generates fragility.
Forecasting literature further illuminates the boundaries between wisdom and madness. Many decisions rely on forecasting, such as predicting the consumer price index, unemployment rate, and even inventory levels [41]. The accuracy of these forecasts has significant consequences for both private and public sectors. Enhancing forecast precision requires improved methods for selecting and combining judgments. Importantly, accurate analysis demands distinguishing cognitive bias from behavioral noise (unwanted variability in judgments) as the root causes of errors in judgment [42]. In the presence of cognitive bias, forecasters can sometimes be influenced by unimportant factors, leading them to present optimistic or pessimistic predictions. For instance, official agencies might predict overly high economic growth and unduly low deficits [43]. Forecasters also exhibit overconfidence [44]. An example is CFOs estimating the S&P 500 index’s annual return. Although they claim an 80% confidence interval for their predictions, the actual returns fall within this range only 36% of the time [45].
Behavioral noise in forecasting refers to inconsistency or unreliability [46]. Even experts can be unreliable, making behavioral noise a significant source of forecasting error [47]. There are two types: level noise and pattern noise. Level noise refers to the variability in the average level of judgments by different judges. In particular, different forecasters, even experts in the same field, can have widely varying predictions [47]. For example, there is significant variability among law professors predicting Supreme Court rulings [48] or specialists estimating the benefits of air pollution regulations [49]. Pattern noise is variability in judges’ responses to particular cases. Pattern noise is due to transient effects (occasion noise) and permanent effects from stable preferences. Pattern noise may cause forecasters to deviate from their previous predictions. Thus, forecasting is crucial for decision-making, but it is important to adjust for cognitive biases and behavioral noise in these predictions.
Research provides strategies to reduce forecasting errors due to cognitive bias and behavioral noise. Two prominent noise-reduction strategies are: selecting better judges and aggregating multiple independent estimates. Choosing more competent judges leads to improved judgments. Aggregating multiple independent estimates includes averaging, the select-crowd strategy, prediction markets, the Delphi method, and the mini-Delphi [42].
Averaging multiple forecasts reduces behavioral noise, with averaging 100 judgments decreasing noise by 90% [50]. As seen, this principle is the wisdom of crowds [39,40] or the “many wrongs principle” [51]: aggregated collective judgments can often outperform those of any individual. A “best-member strategy” [52,53] that depends on only one judge, on the contrary, may overlook the collective knowledge of many, and may result in poor outcomes if a less skilled crowd member is selected [54]. Averaging group judgments enhances the overall accuracy of the crowd’s collective estimate. However, averaging does not reduce bias. Thus, for best results, judgments should be independent, minimizing shared biases. Empirical data indicates that averaging multiple forecasts by unweighted average of group of forecasters often enhances accuracy [46]. Additionally, combining forecasts can reduce errors by an average of 12.5% [49]. The wisdom-of-crowd approach showcases the advantages of using statistical groups [55]. Many studies show that basic aggregation methods, like using the median or mean for numbers or a majority vote for categories, often outperform complex strategies [56]. The crowd’s average prediction is usually better than the prediction of its typical member.
A third approach, known as the “select-crowd strategy,” takes the average of predictions from experts selected for their proven accuracy, rather than using a straight average. This method combines both aggregation and selection. While the average group opinion (the wisdom of crowds) can surpass individual judgments, it has its limitations, as does relying on a single expert. Research indicates that averaging the opinions of the top five judges using the select-crowd strategy produces highly accurate results across various scenarios [54]. Despite general skepticism towards crowd opinions, people are more receptive to the select-crowd approach, making it an effective way to harness collective wisdom.
Moreover, enhancing forecasting accuracy can be achieved by selecting better judges and using various aggregation techniques. The most suitable method often depends on the specific forecasting scenario. Prediction markets, another method, allow individuals to bet on outcomes, motivating accurate forecasting. Often, prediction market outcomes closely match real-world event probabilities [57]. Various industries utilize prediction markets to aggregate diverse opinions [58].
Furthermore, the Delphi method involves iterative rounds where participants anonymously submit estimates [59,60]. They then provide reasons for their predictions and react to others’ rationales. This method encourages convergence of estimates. The classic Delphi method can be complicated to execute [61], so there is a simplified version called mini-Delphi or “estimate-talk-estimate” [62]. In this approach, during a single meeting, participants give individual estimates, discuss and justify them, and then offer a new estimate in response to others. The final judgment is the average of the second-round individual estimates.
The Good Judgment Project was initiated by behavioral scientists in an effort to comprehend why certain individuals excel at forecasting [63]. Tens of thousands of volunteers, mainly from the general public, were recruited. Participants were asked to predict significant global events, demonstrating that the challenges faced in these predictions resemble those of more commonplace forecasts. Forecasters provided probabilistic estimates rather than binary predictions to better capture the inherent uncertainty of future events. Participants were allowed to revise their predictions as new information emerged. For evaluation, the researchers employed Brier [64] scores. These scores measure the distance between forecasts and actual outcomes, rewarding both good calibration (accuracy on average) and good resolution (differentiation among forecasts). Lower scores indicate better forecasting accuracy.
Most participants did not perform well. However, about 2% of them, the “superforecasters,” [63] excelled in their predictions. Surprisingly, these superforecasters outperformed intelligence community analysts, even though the latter had access to classified information and specialized training [63]. The Good Judgment Project found that certain people can greatly outperform usual forecasts and expert opinions when given proper methods and tools.
While superforecasters, identified from the Good Judgment Project, tend to score higher than average in intelligence tests, their superiority is not solely due to their intellectual capacity. The defining characteristic of superforecasters is not just their ability with numbers, but their analytical and probabilistic thinking style. They deconstruct large, complex questions into smaller, manageable components, allowing for a more methodical approach to forecasting. Furthermore, superforecasters prioritize the outside view. When they take an outside view, they consider a case to be a member of a class of similar situations, and they think statistically about the class rather than causally about the focused case. They weigh historical and statistical base rates heavily in their predictions. For example, before assessing the current dynamics between two countries in a border dispute, they would first consider the historical frequency of such disputes escalating into conflict. Cognitive style is also important. Superforecasters’ cognitive style embodies a high degree of “active open-mindedness.” Superforecasters are willing to consider opposing evidence and adjust their beliefs accordingly. They value insights from those who disagree with them, constantly updating their predictions based on new information.
Their “perpetual beta” strategy, however, is the most crucial element. Borrowed from software development, the perpetual beta concept implies a continuous cycle of testing, analyzing, refining, and re-testing [63]. Superforecasters are in a perpetual state of learning and self-improvement. The essence of superforecasters lies less in their inherent traits and more in their committed approach of continuous iteration and belief updating. Perpetual beta is therefore the best indicator of becoming a superforecaster [63]. The exceptional forecasting skills of superforecasters stem from their consistent and dedicated application of analytical processes, perpetual self-improvement, and their willingness to revise and refine their beliefs and predictions.
The possibility for teaching individuals to become superforecasters was investigated in an experiment in which forecasters were separated into three methods, each subjected to a different intervention aimed at boosting judgment: training, teaming, and selection [63]. Training involved a tutorial that focused on improving probabilistic reasoning, highlighting biases like base-rate neglect, overconfidence, and confirmation bias, and emphasizing the need to average multiple predictions from various sources. By dividing forecasters into groups and allowing them to discuss and share their predictions, the teaming method actively encouraged open-mindedness. Following a year, the selection procedure classified the top 2% of forecasters as superforecasters, who were then assigned to tasks together. Results revealed that all interventions improved forecasting accuracy, with training having a positive effect, teaming showing a more significant effect, and selection showcasing the largest effect.
Satopää et al. [65] studied how interventions enhanced predictions using the BIN model, which stands for bias, information, and noise. Information is the ability to identify and analyze relevant data. Bias leads forecasters to consistently misjudge outcomes. Noise represents random errors from sources like news overreaction or inconsistent probability scaling. Satopää et al. found that all three interventions primarily reduced noise. Training aimed to combat psychological biases, but mostly reduced noise, as these biases often appear as noise in diverse forecasting. Teaming lowered noise and improved information extraction, showcasing collective intelligence’s strength. Selection had the greatest impact; superforecasters were better at obtaining relevant information and displayed less noise than others. Their standout quality may be their disciplined approach rather than unique insights [65].
The superforecasting project underlines the effectiveness of two decision-making strategies: selection and aggregation. Selection pertains to choosing top performers (like superforecasters) who excel at their tasks. Aggregation is the process of combining multiple judgments, which has been shown to enhance performance, especially when teams are involved. Both these strategies can be applied to various judgments. Ideally, combining both can yield the best results. When assembling teams, it is beneficial to select members who are not only adept at their roles but also bring diverse perspectives and skills. Averaging multiple independent judgments, as seen in wisdom-of-crowd’s experiments, can improve precision. The accuracy gets further boosted when combining judgments that are both independent and complementary [66]. For instance, when multiple witnesses see an event from different vantage points, the collective information they provide is more accurate.
Building a team for judgment is analogous to constructing a set of tests to predict future performances. Using multiple regression, the variable that best predicts the outcome is selected first. The following variables are not necessarily the next best predictors but those that offer complementary insights. Similarly, while assembling a team, the initial selection should be the best judge, but subsequent choices should be individuals offering unique skills rather than merely those with similar competencies. Teams comprising diverse judgments will naturally exhibit pattern noise, meaning individual judgments may vary. However, this diversity paradoxically leads to more accurate collective outcomes compared to homogenous groups [42]. Aggregation’s noise-reducing power works only if judgments are genuinely independent. Group deliberations, without proper structure, can introduce more bias, overshadowing the benefits of noise reduction. Embracing disagreements that arise from independent judgments is vital. Aggregating judgments that are both diverse and independent is an effective decision-making strategy.
Therefore, the forecasting literature in psychology and behavioral economics provides a vivid illustration of how random errors and individual-level biases can be reconciled with coherent outcomes at the aggregate level. Mechanisms such as aggregation, averaging, and institutional filtering often transform behavioral noisy or biased judgments into more accurate collective forecasts. This dynamic parallels Becker’s insight that rational market outcomes can emerge from non-rational individual behavior, and it reinforces the structural role of Say’s law: while micro-level deviations may distort decisions in the short run, the underlying logic that production generates the capacity for demand ultimately reasserts itself.
These findings have profound implications for economic coordination. The same psychological factors that distort individual judgment (cognitive bias, behavioral noise, overconfidence, herding, etc.) can, under the right institutional conditions, be redirected. The key lies not in eradicating human imperfections but in structuring environments that convert them into signal rather than distortion. Just as aggregation and calibration strategies reduce behavioral noise in forecasting, similar mechanisms—competitive markets, feedback through prices, or institutional reforms—can reorient misaligned expectations toward coherent outcomes.
Markets, then, function not as perfect calculators but as noisy information processors. In the presence of dispersed, independent judgments, they resemble the “superforecasters” of economic coordination, gradually aligning prices with real value through iterative corrections. When those conditions fail—when imitation crowds out insight, and narratives overpower information—the signal is drowned in the noise. Yet even then, the market’s adaptive structure, much like the perpetual beta mindset of superforecasters, allows for recovery. Crashes reset expectations. Institutional reforms clarify incentives. Incoherence forces redesign.
This is where Say’s law regains its relevance: not as a claim about instantaneous equilibrium, but as a structural regularity of real economies. Production generates income, which, despite behavioral detours, finds its way to demand. Behavioral economics enriches this picture by showing that the path is not linear, nor the timing frictionless. But the link remains. Aggregation, feedback, and institutional learning serve as the bridges from madness back to wisdom.
What emerges is a view of the economy not as fragile to human error, but resilient through design. Behavioral deviations may destabilize, but they do not invalidate the generative logic of purchasing power creation. As long as goods and services are produced, income is created, and, given the right settings, demand will eventually absorb supply. In this sense, the wisdom of the crowd is not a given, but a goal, achieved not by eliminating bounded minds, but by channeling them toward coherent outcomes. Say’s law endures not despite behavioral economics, but because behavioral economics shows how economic structures recover from the very deviations it studies. Maybe Say’s law endures not by avoiding the madness of crowds, but precisely because markets learn to live with it.

7. Negative vs. Positive Feedback

The discussion can be recast in terms of the underlying dynamics at play. We can argue that while the wisdom of crowds operates through negative feedback (a self-correcting process where deviations from equilibrium are dampened over time), the madness of crowds emerges from positive feedback (a self-reinforcing dynamic where deviations are amplified rather than corrected) [67]. This raises a key question: how can positive feedback mechanisms be reconciled with the long-run validity of Say’s law under behavioral distortions?
Say’s law asserts that supply creates its own demand because production generates income, which is then used to purchase goods. This is a macro-level identity, not a short-run behavioral equilibrium condition. Positive feedback may cause short-run misallocations (for example, bubbles), but it does not erase the underlying income generated by production. Even if demand is misdirected, the purchasing power exists. A bubble does not destroy purchasing power; it redistributes it, often inefficiently. But the accounting identity output = income still holds.
Importantly, positive feedback is self-limiting due to resource constraints. Though positive feedback loops amplify behavior (rising prices encourage more buying), they eventually hit real-world constraints: scarce inputs, budget limits, or diminishing returns. These constraints force a reversion to productive fundamentals. Once the speculative cycle is exhausted, agents must produce again to participate in the economy. Say’s law reasserts itself. During the housing bubble, speculative dynamics distorted allocations [21]. But after the crash, the system did not collapse into barter: it restructured and returned to productive paths.
Furthermore, institutions act as circuit breakers. Even under behavioral distortions, institutions (central banks, bankruptcy courts, regulatory bodies) act to break feedback loops and redirect behavior toward sustainable patterns. Of note, these institutions are not external to Say’s law but emerge in response to the very need to maintain the supply-demand linkage. They filter behavioral excess, restoring long-run consistency. For example, post-crisis stimulus and bank recapitalizations serve to prevent demand collapses that would otherwise decouple from productive capacity.
Of course, Say’s law assumes that what is produced is actually valued. But in cases of extreme positive feedback, production can become misaligned with genuine demand, so that the income it generates does not translate into meaningful purchasing power. For instance, markets may fuel the mass production of overvalued or unwanted goods. When behavioral distortions lead to systematic mispricing, the link between supply and demand can weaken. In such cases, Say’s law may remain true as an accounting identity, but it loses effectiveness as a coordinating principle. As Keynes [35] famously argued, output can exceed effective demand when uncertainty or panic suppresses spending. Thus, while Say’s law may hold in the long run, it can fail to operate in the short run, precisely when stability is most needed.

8. Conclusions: Order from Behavioral Disorder?

This entry has argued that the enduring logic of economic coordination, embodied in Becker’s constraints-based framework and Say’s law, remains robust even under the behavioral turn in economics. Becker showed that rational market outcomes can emerge from a wide range of individual behaviors, including non-rational ones, so long as agents are constrained by real economic conditions. Say’s law underpins this view by explaining where those constraints originate: from the fundamental identity that production generates income, and income enables demand.
While behavioral economics challenges Becker’s key assumption that non-rationality is random and cancels out, it does not overturn his structural insight. Rather, it enriches it. Systematic cognitive biases, institutional frictions, and feedback dynamics introduce distortions that can temporarily decouple supply and demand. However, these deviations tend to be transient, bounded by real-world constraints, and eventually corrected by institutional mechanisms, resource scarcity, or crisis-driven reallocation.
Indeed, the madness of crowds can disrupt markets, but it does not nullify the macroeconomic identity that output equals income. Even under irrational exuberance or panic, the economy does not collapse into mayhem. It stumbles, resets, and reorients toward productive use of resources. This showcases the resilience of markets, and the necessity of understanding both their self-correcting tendencies and their positive-feedback limits.
Therefore, the behavioral revolution in economics does not spell the end of neoclassical foundations. It reaffirms their relevance under more realistic assumptions. By relaxing the ideal of perfect rationality while preserving the architecture of constraints and equilibrium, we gain a more empirically grounded, psychologically informed, and institutionally aware version of microeconomics.
All agents, rational or not, face constraints. These constraints shape their behavior and can or cannot yield predictable market outcomes, even if individual decisions are not rational. Say’s law, when understood not as a claim about instant market clearing but as a structural principle of income generation through production, continues to frame the long-run logic of economic systems, even in a world of bounded minds and behavioral excess.

Funding

This research was funded by CNPq (Grant number: PQ 2 301879/2022-2) and Capes (Grant number: PPG 001).

Conflicts of Interest

The author declares no conflicts of interest.

References

  1. Becker, G.S. Irrational behavior and economic theory. J. Polit. Econ. 1962, 70, 1–13. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  2. Simon, H.A. A behavioral model of rational choice. Q. J. Econ. 1955, 69, 99–118. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  3. Kahneman, D. Thinking, Fast and Slow; Farrar, Straus and Giroux: New York, NY, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
  4. Schwartzstein, J. Selective attention and learning. J. Eur. Econ. Assoc. 2014, 12, 1423–1452. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  5. Hanna, R.; Mullainathan, S.; Schwartzstein, J. Learning through noticing: Theory and experimental evidence in farming. Q. J. Econ. 2014, 129, 1311–1353. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  6. Mullainathan, S.; Schwartzstein, J.; Shleifer, A. Coarse thinking and persuasion. Q. J. Econ. 2008, 123, 577–619. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  7. Rabin, M.; Schrag, J.L. First impressions matter: A model of confirmatory bias. Q. J. Econ. 1999, 114, 37–82. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  8. Sims, C.A. Implications of rational inattention. J. Monet. Econ. 2003, 50, 665–690. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  9. Gabaix, X. A sparsity-based model of bounded rationality. Q. J. Econ. 2014, 129, 1661–1710. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  10. Bordalo, P.; Gennaioli, N.; Shleifer, A. Salience theory of choice under risk. Q. J. Econ. 2012, 127, 1243–1285. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  11. Bordalo, P.; Gennaioli, N.; Shleifer, A. Salience and consumer choice. J. Polit. Econ. 2013, 121, 803–843. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  12. Candela, R.A. The methodological foundations of macroeconomics: A view from Say’s law. In The Palgrave Handbook of Methodological Individualism; Bulle, N., Di Iorio, F., Eds.; Palgrave Macmillan: Cham, Switzerland, 2023. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  13. Sowell, T. Say’s Law: An Historical Analysis; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1972. [Google Scholar]
  14. Sowell, T. Classical Economics Reconsidered; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1974. [Google Scholar]
  15. Da Silva, S. System 1 vs. System 2 thinking. Psych 2023, 5, 1057–1076. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  16. Ariely, D. Predictably Irrational: The Hidden Forces That Shape Our Decisions; HarperCollins: New York, NY, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
  17. Banerjee, A.V. A simple model of herd behavior. Q. J. Econ. 1992, 107, 797–817. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  18. Tversky, A.; Kahneman, D. The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science 1981, 211, 453–458. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  19. Thaler, R.H. Mental accounting and consumer choice. Mark. Sci. 1985, 4, 199–214. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  20. Sharot, T. The optimism bias. Curr. Biol. 2011, 21, R941–R945. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  21. Shiller, R.J. Irrational Exuberance, 2nd ed.; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2000. [Google Scholar]
  22. Laibson, D. Golden eggs and hyperbolic discounting. Q. J. Econ. 1997, 112, 443–478. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  23. Thaler, R.H.; Sunstein, C.R. Nudge: Improving Decisions About Health, Wealth, and Happiness; Yale University Press: New Haven, CT, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
  24. Ball, L.; Romer, D. Real rigidities and the non-neutrality of money. Rev. Econ. Stud. 1990, 57, 183–203. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  25. Diamond, P.A. Aggregate demand management in search equilibrium. J. Political Econ. 1982, 90, 881–894. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  26. Shleifer, A.; Vishny, R.W. The limits of arbitrage. J. Finance 1997, 52, 35–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  27. Akerlof, G.A.; Kranton, R.E. Economics and identity. Q. J. Econ. 2000, 115, 715–753. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  28. Shiller, R.J. Narrative economics. Am. Econ. Rev. 2017, 107, 967–1004. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  29. Deaton, A.; Muellbauer, J. Economics and Consumer Behavior; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1980. [Google Scholar]
  30. Cassidy, J. Dot.con: The Greatest Story Ever Sold; HarperCollins: New York, NY, USA, 2002. [Google Scholar]
  31. Akerlof, G.A.; Shiller, R.J. Animal Spirits: How Human Psychology Drives the Economy, and Why It Matters for Global Capitalism; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
  32. Guerrieri, V.; Lorenzoni, G.; Straub, L.; Werning, I. Macroeconomic implications of COVID-19: Can negative supply shocks cause demand shortages? Am. Econ. Rev. 2022, 112, 1437–1474. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  33. Chetty, R.; Friedman, J.N.; Hendren, N.; Stepner, M.; Opportunity Insights Team. The Economic Impacts of COVID-19: Evidence from a New Public Database Built Using Private Sector Data; National Bureau of Economic Research: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2020. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  34. Bejenaru, C.-E.; Altăr-Samuel, A.; Cheptiș, A.; Vid, A.-I. Behavioral macroeconomics—A basis for developing sustainable economic policies. Sustainability 2025, 17, 1552. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  35. Keynes, J.M. The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money; Macmillan: London, UK, 1936. [Google Scholar]
  36. Hayek, F.A. Competition as a Discovery Procedure. Q. J. Austrian Econ. 2002, 5, 9–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  37. Minsky, H.P. Stabilizing an Unstable Economy; McGraw-Hill: New York, NY, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
  38. Bikhchandani, S.; Hirshleifer, D.; Welch, I. A theory of fads, fashion, custom, and cultural change as informational cascades. J. Polit. Econ. 1992, 100, 992–1026. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  39. Galton, F. Vox populi. Nature 1907, 75, 450–451. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  40. Surowiecki, J. The Wisdom of Crowds; Little, Brown: London, UK, 2004. [Google Scholar]
  41. Brüggen, A.; Grabner, I.; Sedatole, K. The Folly of Forecasting: The Effects of a Disaggregated Demand Forecasting System on Forecast Error, Forecast Positive Bias, and Inventory Levels; Department of Strategy and Innovation Working Paper Series, 07/2020; WU Vienna University of Economics and Business: Vienna, Austria, 2020. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  42. Kahneman, D.; Sibony, O.; Sunstein, C.R. Noise: A Flaw in Human Judgment; Little, Brown Spark: New York, NY, USA, 2021. [Google Scholar]
  43. Frankel, J.A. Over-optimism in forecasts by official budget agencies and its implications. Oxf. Rev. Econ. Policy 2011, 27, 536–562. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  44. Arkes, H.R. Overconfidence in judgmental forecasting. In Principles of Forecasting; Armstrong, J.S., Ed.; Kluwer Academic: Boston, MA, USA, 2001; pp. 495–515. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  45. Ben-David, I.; Graham, J.R.; Harvey, C.R. Managerial miscalibration. Q. J. Econ. 2013, 128, 1547–1584. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  46. Stewart, T.R. Improving reliability of judgmental forecasts. In Principles of Forecasting; Armstrong, J.S., Ed.; Kluwer Academic: Boston, MA, USA, 2001; pp. 81–106. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  47. Armstrong, J.S. (Ed.) Principles of Forecasting: A Handbook for Researchers and Practitioners; Kluwer Academic: Boston, MA, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
  48. Ruger, T.W.; Kim, P.T.; Martin, A.D.; Quinn, K.M. The Supreme Court forecasting project. Columbia Law Rev. 2004, 104, 1150–1209. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  49. Sunstein, C.R. Maximin. Yale J. Regul. 2020, 37, 940–979. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  50. Armstrong, J.S. Combining forecasts. In Principles of Forecasting; Armstrong, J.S., Ed.; Kluwer Academic: Boston, MA, USA, 2001; pp. 417–439. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  51. Bergman, G.; Donner, K.O. An analysis of the spring migration of the common scoter and the long-tailed duck in southern Finland. Acta Zool. Fenn. 1964, 105, 1–59. [Google Scholar]
  52. Yetton, P.W.; Bottger, P.C. Individual versus group problem solving: An empirical test of a best-member strategy. Organ. Behav. Hum. Perf. 1982, 29, 307–321. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  53. Bonner, B.L. Expertise in group problem solving: Recognition, social combination, and performance. Group Dyn.-Theor. Res. 2004, 8, 277–290. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  54. Mannes, A.E.; Soll, J.B.; Larrick, R.P. The wisdom of select crowds. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 2014, 107, 276–299. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  55. Yaniv, I. The benefit of additional opinions. Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci. 2004, 13, 75–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  56. Kerr, N.L.; Tindale, R.S. Group-based forecasting?: A social psychological analysis. Int. J. Forecasting 2011, 27, 14–40. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  57. Wolfers, J.; Zitzewitz, E. Prediction markets. J. Econ. Perspect. 2004, 18, 107–126. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  58. Sunstein, C.R.; Hastie, R. Wiser: Getting Beyond Groupthink to Make Groups Smarter; Harvard Business Press: Boston, MA, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
  59. Rowe, G.; Wright, G. The Delphi technique as a forecasting tool: Issues and analysis. Int. J. Forecasting 1999, 15, 353–375. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  60. Bang, D.; Frith, C.D. Making better decisions in groups. Roy. Soc. Open Sci. 2017, 4, 170193. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  61. Hastie, R. Review Essay: Experimental Evidence on Group Accuracy. In Information Pooling and Group Decision Making: Proceedings of the 2nd Conference on Political Economy, 1986; Jai Press Inc.: Greenwich, CT, USA, 1986; pp. 129–157. [Google Scholar]
  62. Van de Ven, A.H.; Delbecq, A.L. The effectiveness of nominal, Delphi, and interacting group decision making processes. Acad. Manage. J. 1974, 17, 605–621. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  63. Tetlock, P.E.; Gardner, D. Superforecasting: The Art and Science of Prediction; Random House: New York, NY, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
  64. Brier, G.W. Verification of forecasts expressed in terms of probability. Mon. Weather Rev. 1950, 78, 1–3. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  65. Satopää, V.A.; Salikhov, M.; Tetlock, P.E.; Mellers, B. Bias, information, noise: The BIN model of forecasting. Manag. Sci. 2021, 67, 7599–7618. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  66. Davis-Stober, C.P.; Budescu, D.V.; Broomell, S.B.; Dana, J. The composition of optimally wise crowds. Decis. Anal. 2015, 12, 130–143. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  67. Sumpter, D.J.T. Collective Animal Behavior; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Da Silva, S. Behaviorally Stretched Microeconomics. Encyclopedia 2025, 5, 147. https://doi.org/10.3390/encyclopedia5030147

AMA Style

Da Silva S. Behaviorally Stretched Microeconomics. Encyclopedia. 2025; 5(3):147. https://doi.org/10.3390/encyclopedia5030147

Chicago/Turabian Style

Da Silva, Sergio. 2025. "Behaviorally Stretched Microeconomics" Encyclopedia 5, no. 3: 147. https://doi.org/10.3390/encyclopedia5030147

APA Style

Da Silva, S. (2025). Behaviorally Stretched Microeconomics. Encyclopedia, 5(3), 147. https://doi.org/10.3390/encyclopedia5030147

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop