Phenomenological Studies of Visual Mental Imagery: A Review and Synthesis of Historical Datasets
Abstract
:1. Introduction
1.1. Purpose
1.2. Glossary of Terms
1.3. Methods and Ground Rules
2. The Early Period: 1860–1929
2.1. Gustav Fechner’s (1860) Observations on After-Images and Memory Images
“Initially, and in general, it cannot be denied that the mental sphere is subject to quantitative considerations. After all we can speak of a greater or lesser intensity of sensation; there are drives of different strengths, and greater and lesser degrees of attention, of the vividness of images of memory and fantasy, and of clearness of consciousness in general, as well as of the intensity of separate thoughts”.([20], p. 46)
“If the memory-images, fantasy-images and schemata accompanying thought are all still psychophysically founded, so is thought itself, in that every other substance and course of thought presupposes another material and another way of linking the schemata, without which no thought can take place at all, just as another melody and harmony cannot be without other tones and another way of linking the tones. Now a piano, with its comparatively small number of fixed keys, nevertheless affords the possibility of executing the most diverse melodies and harmonies, and however many and however high thoughts man may conceive, 25 letters suffice to express them; in both cases it depends only on the connection and the sequence in which the keys or letters are passed through. The brain, however, with its innumerable fibres, active in various ways, contains incomparably richer means in this respect, so there can be no obstacle to trusting it with at least as great a performance inwardly as we perform outwardly by means of it”.[20]
Sensory impressions once made from the outside continue to exist for a certain time after the removal of the external stimulus as after-images, after-sounds, generally as after-perceptions, which in a healthy, strong state of the senses tend to be less easily perceived, less intense and lasting than in a weakly stimulable state; and they leave behind the capacity to be reproduced in memories or more or less transformed in phantasy images. Both kinds of after-effects are to be considered here mainly, if not exclusively, in the field of facial perception, where they have been most studied; but what is valid here is more or less applicable to other fields of sense perception.
The main differences between after-images on the one hand, and memory and phantasy images on the other, are that the former are only ever accompanied by a feeling of receptivity. The first always arise and exist only with a feeling of receptivity, only in continuity with the sensory impressions made, independent of volition and association with the imagination, and, according to the immediately preceding sensory impressions, also proceed independently of volition, legitimately, whereas the memory and phantasy images, with a feeling of lesser or greater spontaneity, can arise even a long time after preceding sensory influences, partly involuntarily through association with the imagination, partly volitionally, and can be banished and altered again.([21], pp. 3–4)
In general, memory and fantasy images always appear to me as something lacking in corporeality, airy, breathy, in contrast to the more material impression of the after-images.
Thus, the drawing of the memory and fantasy images is more vague and blurred than that of the after-images. I am not able to obtain clear, sharp outlines even on the most familiar memory images of the objects that are daily before my eyes, while the after-images appear with corresponding sharpness as directly seen objects.
After-images in the closed eye are either deeper black or lighter than the surrounding ground of the eye and the uniform black of the field of vision, depending on the brightness of the objects viewed in relation to the ground on which they appeared. Memory images, on the other hand, generally give me a weaker impression than the black itself. From white to black there is a scale of continuously graduated brightness and the deepest black is the pure black of the eye. If I now ask myself where this scale would lead if I were to think of it as continuing below black, I believe that one is led to the indistinct impression of memory and fantasy images.
With all my efforts, I cannot reproduce colours in the memory images of coloured objects, or only in fleeting, doubtful appearances when recalling very striking impressions (for example, when I think of cut eggs on spinach, where the white, yellow and green stand out very sharply against each other) while I receive vivid coloured after-images in the open as well as the closed eye. I also never dream in colours, but all my experiences in dreams seem to me to proceed in a kind of twilight or night.
I am not able to recall even the most familiar memory-images.
It is not possible to hold on to the image steadily, even for a short time, but in order to look at it longer, it must, so to speak, always be recreated anew; it does not both change of its own accord and disappear again and again of its own accord. If, however, I want to reproduce it often one after the other with the same intention, it soon no longer succeeds at all, for the attention or activity of production soon dulls. This, however, is not a dulling of memory activity in general; for I am not prevented—and this seems to me worthy of attention—from immediately imagining another familiar memory image instead, as clearly as it is at all possible for me to do so, and, when attention or production activity has also exhausted itself for this one, to return to the first image where I can produce it again with the initial clarity. This is true even of quite related pictures; as, for example, I have often attempted with two portrait figures on the same photograph or portraits hanging next to each other in my living room, neither of which I can often reproduce in memory one after the other, but both in repeated alternation. If, however, I continue this alternation somewhat quickly and often one after the other, I finally find myself dulled for both pictures, but can pass on to a third picture with success.
I cannot change after-images at all by will.([21], pp. 4–5)
“(1) Sometime after the creation, the figures disappear or change into others without my being able to prevent this. (Fechner’s report of figures disappearing and changing into others without control matches the phenomena of metamorphosis described later in this paper).
(2) If the colour does not belong integrally to an object, I do not always have it completely under my control. A face, for example, never appears blue to me, but always in its natural colour, whereas instead of the imaginary red cloth, a blue one can appear at times; in general, the production of a certain colour is more difficult than that of a certain shape, and the first one succeeded in my p. 485
I did not succeed in the first attempts, since I had already succeeded in the last.
(3) I have succeeded a few times in seeing pure colours without objects; they then filled the entire field of vision.
(4) Objects that are not familiar to me, i.e., mere fantasy images, I often do not see, and instead of them, familiar objects of the same kind appear to me; for example, I once wanted to see a brass sword handle with a brass basket, but instead I saw the more familiar image of a rapping basket.
(5) Most of these subjective appearances, especially if they were bright, leave after-images if the eyes are opened quickly during the dwelling of the appearance; for example, I thought of a silver stirrup, and after looking at it for a while, I opened my eyes and saw the dark after-image of it for a long time.” (Fechner’s report of the after-imagery of memory imagery has been verified by later observers, e.g., [22,23]).[21]
“Goethe says in Contributions to Morphology and Natural Science: “I have the gift, when I close my eyes and, with my head bowed down, think of a flower in the center of my visual organ, it does not remain for a moment in its first form, but it spreads out and from within it unfolds again new flowers of coloured, even green, leaves; they are not natural flowers, but fantastic, but regular, like the rosettes of the sculptors. It is impossible to foresee the sprouting creation, but it lasts as long as I like, does not tire and does not intensify. I can produce the same if I think of the ornament of a colourfully painted disk, which then also changes continuously from the center to the periphery, completely like the kaleidoscopes.”.([21], p. 18)
“One painter, who had inherited a large part of the clientele of the famous Sir Joshua Reynolds, and believed him to be of superior talent to his own, was so busy that he confessed to me, says Wigan, that he had painted 300 portraits, large and small, in one year. This fact seems physically impossible; but the secret of his speed and astonishing success was this: he needed only one sitting to represent the model. I saw him execute before my eyes in less than eight hours the miniature portrait of a gentleman whom I knew very well; it was done with the greatest care and a perfect likeness.
I asked him to give me some details of his process, and this is what he replied: “When a model came along, I looked at it attentively for half an hour, sketching on the canvas from time to time. I didn’t need any longer. I would remove the canvas and move on to another person. When I wanted to continue the first portrait, I took the man in my mind, I put him on the chair, where I saw him as clearly as if he were ‘616’ written in the sky; and I can even add with sharper and more vivid shapes and colours. I looked from time to time at the imaginary figure, and I began to paint; I suspended my work to examine the pose, absolutely as if the original had been before me; every time I cast my eyes on the chair, I saw the man.”([21], pp. 18–19])
- (i)
- Wide individual differences were evident in both vividness and colouration;
- (ii)
- Some people reported stronger imagery with their eyes open, others with their eyes closed and others reported imagery of equal strength with their eyes open or closed;
- (iii)
- Fechner’s participants reported an impression of pressure, contraction or tension in generating VMI;
- (iv)
- In all seven cases, VMI was projected into external space, corresponding to normal vision;
- (v)
- In four cases, including Fechner himself, solid-looking, three-dimensional images could be formed;
- (vi)
- In the same four cases, multi-sensory imagery spontaneously arose;
- (vii)
- The cases Fechner presented comprised seven intellectuals, six men and one woman. As Fechner was aware, larger, more diverse samples would be required to form more definitive conclusions. The VMI characteristics in this study were evoked under Fechner’s particular instructions and may not generalize to other procedures for inducing VMI, e.g., spontaneous VMI while reading, listening or thinking.
2.2. Galton’s Breakfast Table Questionnaire
“Before addressing yourself to any of the Questions on the opposite page, think of some definite object—suppose it is your breakfast-table as you sat down to it this morning—and consider carefully the picture that rises before your mind’s eye.(p. 302)
1. Illumination.—Is the image dim or fairly clear? Is its brightness comparable to that of the actual scene?
2. Definition.—Are all the objects pretty well defined at the same time, or is the place of sharpest definition at any one moment more contracted than it is in a real scene?
3. Colouring.—Are the colours of the china, of the toast, bread-crust, mustard, meat, parsley, or whatever may have been on the table, quite distinct and natural?”
1. Brilliant, distinct, never blotchy.
2. Quite comparable to the real object. I feel as though I was dazzled, e.g., when recalling the sun to my mental vision.
3. In some instances quite as bright as an actual scene.
46. Fairly clear and not incomparable in illumination with that of the real scene, especially when I first catch it. Apt to become fainter when more particularly attended to.
47. Fairly clear, not quite comparable to that of the actual scene. Some objects are more sharply defined than others, the more familiar objects coming more distinctly in my mind.
48. Fairly clear as a general image; details rather misty.
98. No. My memory is not of the nature of a spontaneous vision, though I remember well where a word occurs in a page, how furniture looks in a room. The ideas are not felt to be mental pictures, but rather the symbols of facts.
99. Extremely dim. The impressions are in all respects so dim, vague and transient, that I doubt whether they can reasonably be called images. They are incomparably less than those of dreams.
100. My powers are zero. To my consciousness there is almost no association of memory with objective visual impressions. I recollect the breakfast table, but do not see it.
- (i)
- Similar to Fechner’s data, Galton’s samples reported wide individual differences in the vividness and colourfulness of their VMI;
- (ii)
- Also in line with Fechner’s data, some people reported stronger imagery with their eyes open, others with their eyes closed;
- (iii)
- Consistent with Fechner’s findings, in a large majority of cases, mental images were localized in external space, corresponding to normal vision;
- (iv)
- In the majority of cases, the apparent field of view in mental imagery was enlarged or the same as normal vision;
- (v)
- In several cases, three-dimensional visual imagery could be formed, again confirming Fechner’s findings;
- (vi)
- In at least some cases, multi-sensory images were formed.
2.3. Armstrong’s Replication of Galton’s Studies
2.4. Fernald’s Studies
- (i)
- The range of individual differences was large. However, every one of the eleven participants reported spontaneous illustrative mental imagery while reading;
- (ii)
- Even participants who reported scant or minimal amounts of illustrative imagery still experienced reading as illustrated by mental imagery of at least three kinds;
- (iii)
- The high incidence of tactile, organic or visuo-motor imagery, which was reported by all participants, was striking;
- (iv)
- Visuo-motor imagery was prevalent, with only one of the eleven participants reporting an absolute lack of visuo-motor illustrative imagery;
- (v)
- In line with (iv), coloured imagery was present for ten of the eleven participants;
- (vi)
- Auditory imagery was present in all but three cases (H, S and Sun) but, overall, less frequently than visual imagery;
- (vii)
- The sample size was limited, and potential gender differences could not be statistically tested with the data from this study.
2.5. Early Studies of Eidetic R. Imagery
“Optical perceptual (or eidetic) images are phenomena that take up an intermediate position between sensations and images. Like ordinary physiological after-images, they are always seen in the literal sense. They have this property of necessity and under all conditions, and share it with sensations. In other respects they can also exhibit the properties of images (Vorstellungen). In those cases in which the imagination has little influence, they are merely modified afterimages, deviating from the norm in a definite way, and when that influence is nearly, or completely zero, we can look upon them as slightly intensified after-images. In the other limiting case, when the influence of the imagination is at its maximum, they are ideas that, like after-images, are projected outward and literally seen.”([31], pp. 1–2)
“For the great majority of adults there is an unbridgeable gulf between sensations and images. It has always been known that for a few individuals this is not true. Some people have peculiar ‘ intermediate experiences ’ between sensations and images. From the description that such people have given of these experiences, and from the characterization we have just given of eidetic images, we must conclude that their ‘ experiences ’ are due to eidetic images. These phenomena, it is true, are rare among average adults.”([31], pp. 3–4)
3. The Middle Period: 1930–1999
3.1. The Myth of Eidetic Imagery as “Photographic” Memory
3.2. Cross-Cultural Study with Participants from Five African Countries
lBO CULTIVATOR: I see human beings. (How many are there, can you count them?) Yes, four [five].
KAMBA WOMAN: I see some people and motor cars, one man on top, with goods on top. (What is the color of the bus?) Looks like red and green [brownish and white]. (What else do you see?) Many people.(Do you see any trees?) Yes. (Where?) [Points correctly]. (Do you see anything else?) I see nothing more. (Can you see the license plates on the cars?) No.
MASAI HERDER: (Can you see their trousers?) No, I can’t see them. (What do you see on the screen now?) I still can see that person, but it is not now very clear.
SWAHILI CULTIVATOR: I see some numbers, an elephant, a man. (Do you see them clearly?) I see them. (Can you see the numbers?) I see the numbers clearly. (Can you read them?) I can read them. (Would you read them, please? Tell us what numbers you see on the screen now.) 0 [pause of 7 s] 2 [5 s] 2 [4 s] 1 [5 s] 7 [6 s] 0 again [actually: 0714653282760].([41], pp. 22–23)
- (i)
- The incidence of eidetic imagery is not significantly higher or lower in African societies than in European or US samples;
- (ii)
- A high degree of variability was evident within each sample and “the attributes and characteristics of eidetic imagery when they do appear do not vary from society to society and, in fact, are no different from those found in Europe and America” ([41], p. 29);
- (iii)
- As was the case in the Western laboratory studies, the differences within groups appeared much greater than those between groups.
3.3. A Rekindling of Phenomenological Research on VMI
One of the twenty subjects, YK, could see inside of the circle vivid images of concrete shape and colour, not mere colour image, at any time when a certain colour name was given to her. She gave a signal by tapping the desk with her right-hand forefinger, every time such an eidetic image appeared or it changed in its figure. She could also scan the images as if she were looking at paintings or photographs.[42]
Various experimental evidences given by a twenty-year-old female of extremely high eidetic ability shows that eidetic imagery is possessed of the constructive character. The word “constructive” means not only the fact that different features from the original stimulus appear in the image, but also, more positively speaking, that eidetic imagery has an aspect of being constructed like any other ordinary memory imagery. In this regard, it deserves emphasis that an eidetic image belongs to “imagery” and that it should not be construed merely as a photographic image, that is, an accurate copy of the original stimulus, or as a photographic memory, that is, an accurate retention of the original stimulus in visual memory.
3.3.1. Spontaneous Eidetic Imagery Not Based on a Stimulus Presentation
3.3.2. Eidetic Imagery Elicited from Stimulus Presentation
- (i)
- Gradual Development and Fading;
- (ii)
- Attentional Effort;
- (iii)
- Supplementation: “new features, which the stimulus pictures did not contain, were added to the images”;
- (iv)
- Grounding: “where images lacked a particular part, such part was not left entirely blank but suffused as some kind of ground in the image”;
- (v)
- Metamorphosis: dramatic and sudden changes in eidetic imagery content;
- (vi)
- Re-emergence;
- (vii)
- Replication: e.g., “an orange square was presented and the same colour image appeared”;
- (viii)
- Figure–Ground Colour Reversal.
3.3.3. Eidetic Imagery Reproduced after a Lapse of Time
3.3.4. Eidetic Imagery Projected on the Surfaces with Complicated Patterns
3.3.5. Eidetic Imagery Evoked from Complex and Abstract Stimulus Figures
- (i)
- EI is a constructive process of agency involving the participant’s attentional efforts, force of will and intentions. This point is reminiscent of Fechner’s and Galton’s findings;
- (ii)
- EI is a flexible and fluid process with gradual development and fading, attentional effort, supplementation, grounding, metamorphosis and figure–ground colour reversal;
- (iii)
- As suggested by Fechner, there is a dynamic interaction between the after-image and the eidetic image.
3.4. Replication of Hatakeyama’s Findings
- (i)
- Eidetic imagery is a vivid, fluid and flexible process;
- (ii)
- Eidetic imagery is a constructive process, not a reproductive or “photographic” one;
- (iii)
- Eidetic imagery can be voluntarily controlled by the participant’s focus of attention;
- (iv)
- Like all other kinds of VMI, there are wide individual differences;
- (v)
- In its weakest, spontaneous form, eidetic imagery is available to the entire population.
4. The Recent Period: 2000–2023
Mental Imagery in People with Intellectual Disabilities
- (i)
- People with ID experience and engage with mental imagery across different sensory modalities;
- (ii)
- The clarity, detail and richness of the images is notable. As well as creating mental images, participants described changing and manipulating these images with VMI metamorphosis as observed by previous investigators described above;
- (iii)
- Images could be “surprising, extraordinary and humorous”;
- (iv)
- Almost all participants described feelings associated with mental imagery, which “could be strong and powerful and encompassed a wide range of different emotions, such as surprise, delight, disgust and fear”;
- (v)
- There is a continuum of “mastery over mental imagery”, with wide individual differences, as observed in all of the VMI studies reviewed here.
5. Synthesis of Findings
6. Discussion
7. Strengths and Limitations
8. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Tye, M. Qualia. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2021. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qualia/ (accessed on 14 October 2023).
- Aristotle. “De Anima” (III, 7, 431a, 14–17). Available online: https://academic.oup.com/book/12823/chapter-abstract/163063885?redirectedFrom=fulltext (accessed on 14 October 2023).
- Merleau-Ponty, M. Phenomenology of Perception; Smith, C., Translator; Routledge & Kegan Paul: Oxfordshire, UK, 1962. [Google Scholar]
- Nanay, B. “Mental Imagery”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2021 Edition), Zalta, E.N., Ed. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mental-imagery/ (accessed on 14 October 2023).
- Giorgi, A. Reflections on the Status and Direction of Psychology: An External Historical Perspective. J. Phenomenol. Psychol. 2013, 44, 244–261. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Neisser, U. Cognitive Psychology; Appleton Century Crofts: New York, NY, USA, 1967. [Google Scholar]
- Sheehan, P.W. (Ed.) The Function and Nature of Imagery; Academic Press: New York, NY, USA, 1972. [Google Scholar]
- Kosslyn, S.M. The medium and the message in mental imagery: A theory. Psychol. Rev. 1981, 88, 46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pylyshyn, Z.W. The imagery debate: Analogue media versus tacit knowledge. Psychol. Rev. 1981, 88, 16. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Farah, M.J. The neurological basis of mental imagery: A componential analysis. Cognition 1984, 18, 245–272. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Paivio, A. Mental imagery in associative learning and memory. Psychol. Rev. 1969, 76, 241–263. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Shepard, R.N.; Metzler, J. Mental Rotation of Three-Dimensional Objects. Science 1971, 171, 701–703. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- McKelvie, S.J. The VVIQ and beyond: Vividness and its measurement. J. Ment. Imag. 1995, 19, 197–252. [Google Scholar]
- Cumming, J.; Eaves, D.L. The Nature, Measurement, and Development of Imagery Ability. Imagin. Cogn. Pers. 2018, 37, 375–393. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Marks, D.F. The Action Cycle Theory of Perception and Mental Imagery. Vision 2023, 7, 12. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Richardson, A. Defining mental imagery. In Mental Imagery; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 1969; pp. 1–12. [Google Scholar]
- Binet, A. Mental imagery. Fortnightly 1892, 52, 95–104. [Google Scholar]
- Charcot, J.M.; Bernard, D. Un cas de suppression brusque et isolée de la vision mentale des signes et des objets (formes et couleurs). Le Progrès Médical 1883, 11, 568–571. [Google Scholar]
- Piaget, J.; Inhelder, B. Mental images. In Experimental Psychology Its Scope and Method: Volume VII (Psychology Revivals): Intelligence; Psychology Press: London, UK, 2014; p. 85. [Google Scholar]
- Fechner, G. Elements of Psychophysics (Volume 1) 1860; Howes, D.H., Boring, E.G., Eds.; Adler, H.E., Translator; Holt, Rinehart and Winston: Washington, DC, USA, 1966. [Google Scholar]
- Marks, D.F. Gustav Fechner’s observations on his own and others’ visual mental imagery. J. Educ. Psychol. Res. 2023, 5, 651–675. [Google Scholar]
- Weiskrantz, L. An unusual case of after-imagery following fixation of an “imaginary” visual pattern. Q. J. Exp. Psychol. 1950, 2, 170–175. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kunzendorf, R.G. After-images of eidetic images: A developmental study. J. Ment. Imag. 1989, 13, 55–62. [Google Scholar]
- Galton, F.I. Statistics of mental imagery. Mind 1880, 5, 301–318. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Galton, F. Inquiries into Human Faculty and Its Development, 2nd ed.; Macmillan: New York, NY, USA, 1883; 1907 by J. M. Dent & Co. (Everyman) First Electronic Edition, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Brewer, W.F.; Schommer-Aikens, M. Scientists are not deficient in mental imagery: Galton revised. Rev. Gen. Psychol. 2006, 10, 130–146. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Armstrong, A.C., Jr. The imagery of American students. Psychol. Rev. 1894, 5, 496. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fernald, M.R. The diagnosis of mental imagery. Psychol. Monogr. 1912, 14, i-169. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Watson, J.B. Image and Affection in Behavior. J. Philos. Psychol. Sci. Methods 1913, 10, 421. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McKellar, T.P.H. Imagination and Thinking. A Psychological Analysis; Cohen & West: London, UK, 1957. [Google Scholar]
- Jaensch, E.R. Über den Aufbau der Wahrnehmungswelt und die Grundlagen der Menschlichen Erkenntnis, 2nd ed.; Barth: Leipzig, Germany, 1923. [Google Scholar]
- Jaensch, E.R. Eidetic Imagery and Typological Methods of Investigation; Harcourt: New York, NY, USA, 1930. [Google Scholar]
- Allport, G.W. Eidetic imagery. Br. J. Psychol. 1924, 15, 19–120. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Klüver, H. Eidetic phenomena. Psychol. Bull. 1932, 29, 181–203. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gengerelli, J.A. Some Quantitative Experiments with Eidetic Imagery. Am. J. Psychol. 1930, 42, 399. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Haber, R.N.; Haber, R.B. Eidetic imagery: I. Frequency. Percept. Mot. Ski. 1964, 19, 131–138. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Haber, R.N. Twenty years of haunting eidetic imagery: Where’s the ghost? Behav. Brain Sci. 1979, 2, 583–594. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Photographic Memories Do Exist. The Harvard Crimson. Available online: https://www.thecrimson.com/article/1970/3/24/photographic-memories-do-exist-ptwo-harvard/ (accessed on 14 October 2023).
- Stromeyer, C.F.; Psotka, J. The Detailed Texture of Eidetic Images. Nature 1970, 225, 346–349. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Merritt, J.O. None in a million: Results of mass screening for eidetic ability using objective tests published in newspapers and magazines. Behav. Brain Sci. 1979, 2, 612. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Doob, L.W. Eidetic Imagery: A Cross-Cultural Will-O’-The-Wisp? J. Psychol. 1966, 63, 13–34. [Google Scholar]
- Hatakeyama, T. The process of having identified an adult eidetic person and her eidetic experiences in everyday life. Tohoku Psychol. Folia 1974, 33, 102–118. [Google Scholar]
- Hatakeyama, T. The constructive character of eidetic imagery. Tohoku Psychol. Folia 1975, 34, 38–51. [Google Scholar]
- Marks, D.F.; McKellar, P. The nature and function of eidetic imagery. J. Ment. Imag. 1982, 6, 1–124. [Google Scholar]
- Matsuoka, K.; Onizawa, T.; Hatakeyama, T. Incidence of young adult eidetikers, and two kinds of eidetic imagery. Tohoku Psychol. Folia 1987, 46, 62–74. [Google Scholar]
- Brown, R.I.; Bullitis, E. The process of mental imagery in persons with or without intellectual disability: An exploratory project. J. Dev. Disabil. 2006, 12, 1–18. [Google Scholar]
- Hewitt, O.M.; Langdon, P.E.; Hales, S.A.; Larkin, M. The phenomenology of mental imagery in people with intellectual disabilities. Psychol. Psychother. Theory, Res. Pract. 2022, 96, 25–39. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Marks, D.F. Visual imagery differences in the recall of pictures. Br. J. Psychol. 1973, 64, 17–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Smith, J.A.; Flowers, P.; Larkin, M. Interpretative Phenomenological Analysis: Theory, Method and Research; Sage: London, UK, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Syed, A.A.; Neelofur, S.; Moran, A.; O’Reilly, G. Exploring the vividness of mental imagery and eidetic imagery in people with intellectual disability (ID) in comparison with typically developing (TD) individuals. Heliyon 2020, 6, e05429. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Marks, D.F. Individual differences in the vividness of visual imagery and their effect on function. In The Function and Nature of Imagery; Sheehan, P.W., Ed.; Academic Press: New York, NY, USA, 1972; pp. 83–108. [Google Scholar]
- Marks, D.F. I Am Conscious, Therefore, I Am: Imagery, Affect, Action, and a General Theory of Behavior. Brain Sci. 2019, 9, 107. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Holmes, E.A.; Blackwell, S.E.; Heyes, S.B.; Renner, F.; Raes, F. Mental imagery in depression: Phenomenology, potential mechanisms, and treatment implications. Annu. Rev. Clin. Psychol. 2016, 12, 249–280. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Wu, F.-G.; Chang, E.; Lee, Y.-J. Manifestation of depressive tendency in color perception and colors utilized in creating a self-portrait. Color Res. Appl. 2008, 34, 84–92. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Reece, A.G.; Danforth, C.M. Instagram photos reveal predictive markers of depression. EPJ Data Sci. 2017, 6, 15. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zeman, A.; Dewar, M.; Della Sala, S. Lives without imagery–Congenital aphantasia. Cortex 2015, 73, 378–380. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Blomkvist, A.; Marks, D.F. Defining and ‘diagnosing’ aphantasia: Condition or individual difference? Cortex, 2023; in press. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Identity | Age | Rank * | Easier with Eyes Open or Closed ** | Vividness to Some Degree | Colour to Some Degree | Feelings of Pressure or Contraction or Effort *** | Project to An External Location | 3 D | Multi- Sensory |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
G Fechner | 59 | =6 | Open | Dim | Fleeting | + | + | + | + |
H Weisse | 59 | =6 | Open | Faint | Little | ? | + | ? | ? |
A W Volkmann | 59 | 5 | = | Faint | Faint | + | + | ? | ? |
W Hankel | 46 | 4 | Open | Yes | + | + | + | ? | ? |
M W Robisch | 50s | 3 | = | High | + | + | + | + | + |
C M Fechner | 51 | 2 | Closed | High | + | + | + | + | + |
M Busch | 39 | 1 | ? | Very high | + | + | + | + | + |
Total | - | - | - | 7/7 | 7/7 | 6/6 | 7/7 | 4/4 | 4/4 |
Sample | Complete or Partial Vividness | Colour Relatively Distinct and Natural | Extent of Field of View Larger Than, or Same as, Normal | External Projection Corresponded to Reality, or in Front of Eyes, at Least on Some Occasions |
---|---|---|---|---|
Galton’s 100 men of science | 97/100 | 97/100 | 75/100 | Missing data |
Galton’s sample of schoolboys | 167/172 ^ | 167/172 ^ | 47/121 * | 126/160 ** |
Sub-totals | 264/272 97.0% | 264/272 97.0% | 122/221 55.2% | 126/160 78.8% |
Armstrong’s US students | 183/188 97.3% | 183/188 97.3% | 95/188 50.5% | 153/188 81.4% |
Totals | 447/460 97.2% | 447/460 97.2% | 217/409 53.0% | 279/348 80.2% |
ID | Gender | Individual’s Overall Imagery Ability, as Rated by the Investigator | Tactile, Organic or Visceral Imagery | Visuo-Motor Imagery | Colour | Olfactory | Auditory Imagery | Temperature | Totals |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
A | Man | Minimum of illustrative imagery | + | + | + | + | + | No | 5/6 |
Ad | Man | Minimal | + | + | + | + | + | + | 6/6 |
C | Woman | Profuse visual imagery. Other imagery moderate. | + | + | + | + | + | No | 5/6 |
G | Woman | Moderate amount of illustrative imagery | + | + | + | + | + | No | 5/6 |
Hs | Man | Abundant imagery | + | + | + | + | + | No | 5/6 |
H | Woman | Minimal | + | No | + | + | No | No | 3/6 |
P | Man | Fair amount, but vague and indefinite | + | + | + | + | + | No | 5/6 |
S | Man | Profuse, vivid and detailed | + | + | + | No | No | + | 4/6 |
Sun | Woman | Scanty | + | + | No | + | No | + | 4/6 |
T | Woman | Scanty, lack of detail, not vivid | + | + | + | No—only sniffed | + | + | 5/6 |
V | Woman | Profusion of non-visual imagery | + | + | + | + | + | + | 6/6 |
TOTALS | 11/11 | 10/11 | 10/11 | 9/11 | 8/11 | 5/11 | 53/66 |
Study | A | B | C | D | E | F | G | H | I | J | K | L | M | N | O | P |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Fechner [21] | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | - | ✓ | ✓ |
Galton [24] | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | - | - | ✓ |
Armstrong [27] | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | - | - | ✓ |
Fernald [28] | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ |
Haber [36,37] | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ |
Doob [41] | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ |
Hatakeyama [42,43] | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ |
Marks and McKellar [44] | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ |
Brown and Bullitis [46] | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ |
Hewitt et al. [47] | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ |
TOTALS | 10 | 10 | 10 | 10 | 10 | 10 | 10 | 10 | 10 | 10 | 10 | 10 | 10 | 7 | 8 | 10 |
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Marks, D.F. Phenomenological Studies of Visual Mental Imagery: A Review and Synthesis of Historical Datasets. Vision 2023, 7, 67. https://doi.org/10.3390/vision7040067
Marks DF. Phenomenological Studies of Visual Mental Imagery: A Review and Synthesis of Historical Datasets. Vision. 2023; 7(4):67. https://doi.org/10.3390/vision7040067
Chicago/Turabian StyleMarks, David F. 2023. "Phenomenological Studies of Visual Mental Imagery: A Review and Synthesis of Historical Datasets" Vision 7, no. 4: 67. https://doi.org/10.3390/vision7040067
APA StyleMarks, D. F. (2023). Phenomenological Studies of Visual Mental Imagery: A Review and Synthesis of Historical Datasets. Vision, 7(4), 67. https://doi.org/10.3390/vision7040067