In Defense of Literary Truth: A Response to Truth, Fiction, and Literature by Peter Lamarque and Stein Haugom Olsen to Inquire into No-Truth Theories of Literature, Pragmatism, and the Ontology of Fictional Objects
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. On the Rejection of Pro-Truth Theories of Literature
2.1. The Theory of Novelistic Truth
2.2. Metaphorical Truth
2.3. The Subjective Knowledge Theory of Cognitive Value
2.4. Literature as Moral Philosophy
2.5. The Propositional Theory of Literary Truth
2.6. Conclusion on Literary Value without Truth
3. Confusing the Ontology of Literature with Matters of Literary Criticism
4. On Richard Rorty and the Theory of the Ubiquity of Fiction
4.1. Metaphysics and Literature
4.2. Contradictions in Rorty’s Pragmatism
5. On the Ontology of Fiction22
6. Conclusions
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | The reader may ask, why choose this book from 1994 as representative of a common outlook in literary theory today? The answer rests on two considerations: (1) it remains one of the most comprehensive analyses of the different waves in literary theory and thus provides an effective platform for a broad understanding of the field, and (2) the framework it outlines is still highly influential. For example, on its basis, Peter Lamarque wrote the subsequent The Philosophy of Literature (Lamarque 2008), a textbook used in philosophy of literature syllabi all over the world. And more importantly, as Roger Marples writes in “Art, knowledge and moral understanding” (Marples 2017), it is still a fact that the “view that art is incapable of providing us with knowledge is sufficiently widely held as to merit a serious attempt at refutation” (243). In this sense, the influence of Lamarque’s work is visible in many contemporary studies. Margit Sutrop’s “Imagination and the Act of Fiction-Making” (Sutrop 2002) quotes it in arguing that “lack of reference and truth-value” (332) are necessary conditions to establish the fictionality of a work of art. And so does Rafe McGregor, in both “Narrative Representation and Phenomenological Knowledge” (McGregor 2016) and “The Ethical Value of Narrative Representation” (McGregor 2017), contend that narrative representations can provide knowledge and ethical value, “regardless of their truth value” (327). Robert Eaglestone’s “Navigating an Ancient Problem: Ethics and Literature” (Eaglestone 2003) mentions Lamarque as one of many theorists who made it possible to talk about ethics in literature without referring to truth value. And Eleonora Belfiore and Oliver Bennett, in “Researching the social impact of the arts: literature, fiction and the novel” (Belfiore and Bennett 2009), quote the book repeatedly in constructing their institutional view of literature. Finally, there are also works that, like the present one, deem it necessary to criticize Lamarque and Olsen, e.g., Christopher Mole’s “The Matter of Fact in Literature” (Mole 2009) and Alan Goldman’s Philosophy and the Novel (Goldman 2013). Especially Goldman’s work, in fact, establishes a precedent for one of the arguments below by asserting that neither Lamarque and Olsen’s theory that literary truth is irrelevant to literary value nor the opposite view that literary value depends on the assertion of moral truths are viable. |
2 | In using “literature” as an evaluative term, Lamarque and Olsen follow Colin Lyas’s “The Semantic Definition of Literature” (Lyas 1969) and Terry Eagleton’s Literary Theory (Eagleton [1983] 2008). They also extend its evaluative significance beyond the aesthetic into the cultural. |
3 | E.g., Henry James explicitly said: “the novel is history” (James 1948, p. 5). |
4 | In Myth, Truth and Literature: Towards a True Postmodernism (Falck 1989), for example, Colin Falck writes that “literature…gives us our purest and most essential way of grasping reality or truth” (ibid. xii), and that “the connection between art and ontological truth [is] a necessary and definitional one” (ibid., p. 74). Lamarque and Olsen show why claims such as these are unfounded and unfoundable. |
5 | As non-naïve defenders of scientific rationality, the logical positivists knew that causality, other minds, natural laws, etc. (and myriad other ideas taken for granted) are not facts but metaphysical theories, i.e., interpretations of what appears. |
6 | On Tolstoy’s ideal of truth-embodiment in literature see also (Pitari 2021a). For the same framework applied to Jean-Paul Sartre and David Foster Wallace see (Pitari 2020). |
7 | On the influence of Aeschylus throughout western culture see (Pitari 2022). |
8 | The modern origin of these theories resides in the influential work done by Immanuel Kant in Critique of Judgment (Kant [1790] 1987) regarding the connection between aesthetic judgment and moral feeling. |
9 | Despite the fact that Nussbaum and Putnam are by no means the only ones to argue for a thesis of this kind. Berys Gaut, for example, argues in “The Ethical Criticism of Art” (Gaut 1998) for “literary ethicism”: i.e., the idea that literary value is a matter of “ethical assessment”; that “if a work manifests ethically commendable attitudes, it is to that extent aesthetically meritorious” (182). The absurdity of this thesis is readily demonstrated by the fact that, according to Gaut’s theory, the literary value of, say, Lolita (Nabokov [1955] 2011), depends on whether the novel morally condemns its protagonist. |
10 | On the same note, Robert Grant argues in “Fiction, Meaning, and Utterance” (Grant 2001) that authorial “’intention’…is public, in the work. Fictions are utterances of a curious kind… Their logical form is actually this: ‘I [author] invite you [reader] to imagine that S [content].’ This prescribes no response, nor claims to describe the ‘real’ world, even though it may elicit a response appropriate to real-life events” (389). And Knapp and Michaels write in “Against Theory” (Knapp and Michaels 1982) that the fundamental and mistaken premise of all literary theory is the inability to see that “the meaning of a text is simply identical to the author’s intended meaning” (724). |
11 | A view shared by Emmanuel Lévinas who wrote in Otherwise than Being or Beyond Essence (Lévinas [1974] 1978): “we suppose that there is in the transcendence involved in language a relationship that is not empirical speech, but responsibility” (120). |
12 | In the most famous work of literary phenomenology, entitled The Literary Work of Art (Ingarden [1931] 1973), Roman Ingarden presents literary texts as doubly intentional objects, where both the author’s intention to create meaning and the reader’s intention to decode meaning collaborate in the establishment of the object’s substance. It is interesting to see how this phenomenological approach coheres with the Wittgensteinian view. It is also worth noting that works such as Toril Moi’s Revolution of the Ordinary (Moi 2017) and James Conant’s “Freedom, Cruelty, and Truth. Rorty versus Orwell” (Conant 2000) present a Wittgensteinian point of view that challenges some of the arguments in this article and are worth reading for a nuanced take on meaning in literature and its logical relation to truth (as an anonymous reviewer kindly suggested). |
13 | The assumption of the necessity of literary truth for literary value can also be seen in Jerome Bump’s analysis of George Eliot’s The Mill on the Floss (Eliot [1860] 2015) in “The Value of Literature, Today and Tomorrow” (Bump 2022). Bump writes that “one of the chief accomplishments of the nineteenth-century ethical aesthetic was George Eliot’s attempts in her novels to teach ‘humanism’, a secular version of ‘love your neighbor’” (3). Significantly, Bump specifies that—citing Eliot herself—the possibility of such ethical value in literature depends on the author’s ability to “plung[e] into ‘the mysterious complexity of our life’” (ibid., p. 14) and to be “inspired by ‘the growing insight and sympathy of a life vivid and intense enough to have created a wide fellow-feeling with all that is human” (ibid.). These passages show that Eliot herself thought of literary truth as necessary for literary value, and that Bump interpreted her work accordingly. She wrote of “insight” into the complexity of “our life” as necessary for the creation of sympathy, and according to the Oxford English Dictionary “insight” means “an instance of apprehending the true nature of a thing”, or “faculty of seeing into inner character of underlying truth” (Hornby 2013). Eliot’s thinking was perfectly logical because understanding and sharing the feelings of others would be impossible without the ability to grasp their true contents, and consequently, literature would be unable to represent the inner worlds of humans if it were unable to grasp their true contents. |
14 | “How does an individual understand her or his position in the world? Are we determined by our genetic heritage, social circumstances and cultural preferences—and only tricked into believing that we make our own choices? By whom? Other individuals who have been determined similarly? Or are we autonomous—wholly or partly—and, if so, then to what degree? Are we or are we not autonomous enough to control and change the legacy fate has landed us with? How does selfhood emerge? Does it follow the same pattern of development in all people, all cultures, all ages? Or is it itself a socio-cultural construction that should be viewed in its historical context? If so, then what is happening right now—are the patterns of selfhood changing in the present world? Does contemporary technology allow us more autonomy—or does it tempt us to give up the freedoms we have? A host of questions...All the dilemmas from which they arise could be plotted on the same axis—one end of which is designated by fate and determination and the other by choice and freedom” (Bauman and Raud 2015, vii–viii). |
15 | Especially if one agrees with Aristotle’s Poetics (Aristotle [335 BC] 1987) that “poetry is something more scientific and serious than history, because poetry tends to give general truths while history gives particular facts” (1451b). |
16 | Lamarque and Olsen here align with what E.D. Hirsch writes in “What Isn’t Literature?” (Hirsch 1978): “to regard literature as primarily aesthetic is not only a mistake; it is also a very unfortunate narrowing of our responses to literature, and our perceptions of its breadth and possibilities” (p. 28). |
17 | In the twentieth century, critics such as Richard Wollheim in Art and its Objects (Wollheim [1968] 1980), Monroe Beardsley in “The Concept of Literature” (Beardsley 1973), John Searle in “The Logical Status of Fictional Discourse” (Searle 1975), J.O. Urmson’ in “Literature” (Urmson 1977), and Gregory Currie in “What is Fiction?” (Currie 1985) knew that all criticism must always presuppose a certain ontology even merely by virtue of adopting a certain logic. Therefore, they knew that critics should address these ontological concerns to ground their analyses. |
18 | Many scholars argue against Lamarque and Olsen here, e.g., Lionel Trilling in “The Poet as Hero; Keats in his Letters” (Trilling [1951] 1980), M.W. Rowe in “Lamarque and Olsen on Literature and Truth” (Rowe [1997] 2004), and Piero Boitani in Letteratura e verità (Literature and Truth, (Boitani 2013)). Writers, too, generally evaluate their work in terms of truth-value. For example, W.H. Auden wrote the following about the famous line, “We must love one another or die”, in his poem “September 1, 1939” (Auden 1979): “I said to myself ‘That’s a damned lie! We must die anyway.’ So, in the next edition, I altered it to ‘We must love one another and die.’ This didn’t do either, so I cut the stanza. Still no good! The whole poem, I realized, was infected with an incurable dishonesty and must be scrapped” (Mendelson 1981, pp. 326–27). |
19 | We explored Middlemarch, but we could have looked at any other classic. The statement that “criticism has indeed always been concerned with the truth-value of literary propositions” simply means that we, as readers, are interested in literary artifacts not as pure forms but as bearers of meanings whose truth-value we care about. For example, in Shakespearean Criticism, S. T. Coleridge wrote that in Hamlet “Shakespeare wished to impress upon us the truth, that action is the chief end of existence” (Coleridge 1960, vol. ii, p. 154). In Shakespeare’s Tragic Heroes (2009), L. B. Campbell argued that Hamlet is “rather obviously constructed to show the profound truth of its dominant idea” that human beings are slaves to their own passions (Campbell 2009, p. 109). And in “Hamlet: Philosophy and the Intruder”, M. Weitz said that in Hamlet “life is and remains a mystery” (Weitz 1963b, p. 67) and that Shakespeare is a “philosophical artist” who “dramatizes the denial of any convincing solution to the mystery” (ibid.). These critics disagreed about the character of Hamlet’s truths, but they agreed on the basic premise that the play does embody certain truths, whatever they are. In this sense, another exemplary classic would be Voltaire’s Candide (Voltaire [1759] 1958), that great novelistic affirmation of Enlightenment ideals. The novel’s maxim is “il faut cultiver notre jardin” (p. 106): that is, humankind must work to improve living conditions on earth, it is our responsibility to do so, and no god will help us. Jeffrey Hart wrote in Smiling Through the Cultural Catastrophe (Hart 2001) that Candide is the enemy of “junk thought.” On the contrary, George Orwell in “Politics vs. Literature” (Orwell [1946] 1968) preferred Gulliver’s Travels and its representation of “the horror of existence” (p. 222) over Candide’s illusions of human sovereignty. But once again, what interests us is that, beneath their disagreement, Hart and Orwell agreed that the point of reading and judging the novel is grasping its intended meaning and evaluating its truth value. |
20 | For this reason, both this article and Lamarque and Olsen may be incorrectly accused of attributing to Rorty the Theory of the Ubiquity of Fiction when he himself granted that we can tell what is true from false. The fact is that the inconsistency resides in Rorty himself: it is Rorty who affirms the Theory of the Ubiquity of Fiction and then contradicts himself by allowing objectivity. |
21 | Likewise, the Theory of the Ubiquity of Fiction entails the absolute freedom of interpretation and the radical pluralism of works such as Paul de Man’s Blindness and Insight (De Man [1971] 1983), J. Hillis Miller’s “Tradition and Difference” (Hillis Miller 1972), and E.D. Hirsch “Three Dimensions of Hermeneutics” (Hirsch 1972). For oppositions to radical pluralism see Stanley Fish’s “How Ordinary is Ordinary Language” (Fish [1973] 1980a) and “Is There a Text in This Class?” (Fish 1980b), Alexander Nehamas’s “The Postulated Author: Critical Monism as a Regulative Ideal” (Nehamas 1981), Robert Stecker’s “Art Interpretation” (Stecker 1994), and Umberto Eco’s “On Some Functions of Literature” (Eco [2004] 2006). |
22 | This section offers an indication of how a coherent starting point for a theory of fictional objects might be outlined; developing a truly demonstrative argument for such a theory would require a much lengthier work. |
23 | There are many further complications regarding the matter of defining modes of existence. When examining common sense, e.g., it is not clear what is fictional and what is not. For example, in Narrative and the Self (Kerby 1991), Anthony Kerby—reiterating Paul Ricoeur’s argument in “History as Narrative and Practice” (Ricoeur 1979)—writes that “it is as a character in our (and other people’s) narratives that we achieve an identity” (p. 40). This is a common outlook in the humanities today: we think of our identities as fictional characters. But should this entail that our identities are not? Are not real? Are nothing? This example shows with clarity the paradoxes our current theory runs into, given how consequential our perceived identities are in our everyday lives. |
24 | Alexius Meinong’s “The Theory of Objects” (Meinong [1904] 1981) might represent a first step toward the recognition of the reality of fictional objects. Meinong expresses the self-evidence of the Parmenidean principle and on that basis affirms that non-material objects such as the “golden mountain”—since they do appear to human consciousness—possess “being.” In this sense, he sees that fictional objects are real. But on the other hand, being influenced by empiricism, he attributes “existence” only to empirical objects, differentiating “being” from “existence.” This differentiation might work if “existence” were interpreted as only one possible mode of being. But if granting “existence” only to empirical objects entails the nothingness of fictional objects, then we are back to violating the principle of non-contradiction. The distinction is thus likely to cause confusion. The recognition that everything that appears is, and appears in experience, must lead to the awareness that there is no difference between “being” and “existence”, and that everything is empirical precisely because everything appears in experience (consciousness), including fictional objects. Therefore, the “golden mountain” both is and exists. Again: if it was but did not exist, it would not appear, and we could neither think nor speak about it nor mistakenly affirm its non-existence. |
References
- Aristotle. [335 BC] 1987. The Poetics of Aristotle. Translated by Stephen Halliwell. Chapel Hill: UNC Press. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. 1998. Metaphysics. Translated by Hughes Lawson-Tancred. London: Penguin. [Google Scholar]
- Auden, Wystan Hugh. 1979. September 1, 1939. In Auden. Selected Poems: New Edition. Edited by Edward Mendelson. New York: Vintage Books. [Google Scholar]
- Bauman, Zygmunt, and Rein Raud. 2015. Practices of Selfhood. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
- Beardsley, Monroe. 1973. The Concept of Literature. In Literary Theory and Structure: Essays in Honor of William K. Wimsatt. Edited by Frank Brady. New Haven: Yale UP, pp. 23–39. [Google Scholar]
- Belfiore, Elena, and Oliver Bennett. 2009. Researching the social impact of the arts: Literature, fiction and the novel. International Journal of Cultural Policy 15: 17–33. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Boitani, Piero. 2013. Letteratura e Verità. Roma: Studium. [Google Scholar]
- Booth, Wayne Clemens. 1988. The Company We Keep. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bump, Jerome F. A. 2022. The Value of Literature, Today and Tomorrow. Literature 2: 1–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Campbell, Lily Bess. 2009. Shakespeare’s Tragic Heroes: Slaves of Passion. Cambridge: Cambridge UP. [Google Scholar]
- Carroll, Noël. 1992. Art, Intention, and Conversation. In Intention & Interpretation. Edited by Gary Iseminger. Philadelphia: Temple UP, pp. 97–131. [Google Scholar]
- Coleridge, Samuel Taylor. 1960. Shakespearean Criticism. London: Dent. [Google Scholar]
- Conant, James. 2000. Freedom, Cruelty, and Truth. Rorty versus Orwell. In Rorty and His Critics. Edited by Robert B. Brandom. Malden: Blackwell, pp. 268–343. [Google Scholar]
- Currie, Gregory. 1985. What Is Fiction? The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 43: 385–92. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- De Man, Paul. 1983. Blindness and Insight: Essays in the Rhetoric of Contemporary Criticism. Oxford: Routledge. First published 1971. [Google Scholar]
- Descartes, René. 2017. Meditations on First Philosophy: With Selections from the Objections and Replies. Edited by John Cottingham. Cambridge: Cambridge UP. First published 1641. [Google Scholar]
- Eaglestone, Robert. 2003. Navigating an Ancient Problem: Ethics and Literature. European Journal of English Studies 7: 127–36. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Eagleton, Terry. 2008. Literary Theory: An Introduction. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. First published 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Eco, Umberto. 2006. On Some Functions of Literature. In Eco. On Literature. London: Vintage Books. First published 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Eliot, George. 2003. Middlemarch. London: Penguin. First published 1871. [Google Scholar]
- Eliot, George. 2015. The Mill on the Floss. Oxford: Oxford UP. First published 1860. [Google Scholar]
- Falck, Colin. 1989. Myth, Truth and Literature: Towards a True Postmodernism. Cambridge: Cambridge UP. [Google Scholar]
- Fish, Stanley. 1980a. How Ordinary Is Ordinary Language? In Fish. Is There a Text in This Class? The Authority of Interpretive Communities. Cambridge: Harvard UP, First publish 1973. [Google Scholar]
- Fish, Stanley. 1980b. Is There a Text in This Class? In Fish. Is There a Text in This Class? The Authority of Interpretive Communities. Cambridge: Harvard UP. [Google Scholar]
- Gaut, Berys. 1998. The Ethical Criticism of Art. In Aesthetics and Ethics: Essays at the Intersection. Cambridge Studies in Philosophy and the Arts. Edited by Jerrold Levinson. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, pp. 182–203. [Google Scholar]
- Goldman, Alan H. 2013. Philosophy and the Novel. Oxford: Oxford UP. [Google Scholar]
- Goodman, Nelson. 1984. Of Mind and Other Matters. Cambridge: Harvard UP. [Google Scholar]
- Grant, Robert. 2001. Fiction, Meaning, and Utterance. Inquiry 44: 389–403. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hart, Jeffrey. 2001. Smiling Through the Cultural Catastrophe: Toward the Revival of Higher Education. New Haven: Yale UP. [Google Scholar]
- Hillis Miller, Joseph. 1972. Tradition and Difference. Diacritics 2: 6–13. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hirsch, Eric Donald. 1972. Three Dimensions of Hermeneutics. New Literary History 3: 245–61. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hirsch, Eric Donald. 1978. What Isn’t Literature. In What Is Literature? Edited by Paul Hernadi. Bloomington: Indiana UP. [Google Scholar]
- Hornby, Albert Sydney. 2013. Oxford Advanced Learner’s Dictionary. Oxford: Oxford UP. [Google Scholar]
- Ingarden, Roman. 1973. The Literary Work of Art: An Investigation on the Borderlines of Ontology, Logic, and Theory of Literature. Evanston: Northwestern UP. First published 1931. [Google Scholar]
- James, Henry. 1948. The Art of Fiction. In “The Art of Fiction” and Other Essays. New York: Oxford UP. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, Immanuel. 1987. Critique of Judgment. London: Hackett Publishing. First published 1790. [Google Scholar]
- Kerby, Anthony Paul. 1991. Narrative and the Self. Bloomington: Indiana UP. [Google Scholar]
- Knapp, Steven, and Walter Benn Michaels. 1982. Against Theory. Critical Inquiry 8: 723–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Lamarque, Peter. 2008. The Philosophy of Literature. London: Wiley. [Google Scholar]
- Lamarque, Peter, and Stein Haugom Olsen. 2002. Truth, Fiction, and Literature: A Philosophical Perspective. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Leavis, Frank Raymond. 1975. The Living Principle: “English” as a Discipline of Thought. London: Chatto and Windus. [Google Scholar]
- Lévinas, Emmanuel. 1978. Otherwise than Being or Beyond Essence. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. First published 1974. [Google Scholar]
- Lewis, David. 1978. Truth in Fiction. American Philosophical Quarterly 15: 37–46. [Google Scholar]
- Lyas, Colin A. 1969. The Semantic Definition of Literature. The Journal of Philosophy 66: 81–95. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Marples, Roger. 2017. Art, knowledge and moral understanding. Ethics and Education 12: 243–58. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McGregor, Rafe. 2016. Narrative Representation and Phenomenological Knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 94: 327–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McGregor, Rafe. 2017. The Ethical Value of Narrative Representation. Journal of Aesthetics and Phenomenology 4: 57–74. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Meinong, Alexius. 1981. The Theory of Objects. In Realism and the Background of Phenomenology. Edited by Roderick Chisholm. Translated by Isaac Levi, D. B. Terrell, and Roderick M. Chisholm. Atascadero: Ridgeview, pp. 76–117. First published 1904. [Google Scholar]
- Mendelson, Edward. 1981. Early Auden. New York: Viking Press. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 1974. The Prose of the World. Edited by Lefort Claude. Translated by John O’Neill. London: Heinemann. First published 1969. [Google Scholar]
- Mill, John Stuart. 1981. Autobiography and Literary Essays. In Collected Works: Vol. 1. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. First published 1873. [Google Scholar]
- Moi, Toril. 2017. Revolution of the Ordinary. Literary Studies after Wittgenstein, Austin and Cavell. Chicago: Chicago UP. [Google Scholar]
- Mole, Christopher. 2009. The Matter of Fact in Literature. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 17: 489–508. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nabokov, Vladimir. 2011. Lolita. London: Penguin. First published 1955. [Google Scholar]
- Nehamas, Alexander. 1981. The Postulated Author: Critical Monism as a Regulative Ideal. Critical Inquiry 8: 131–49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nussbaum, Martha. 1990. Love’s Knowledge: Essays on Philosophy and Literature. New York: Oxford UP. [Google Scholar]
- Orwell, George. 1968. Politics vs. Literature: An Examination of Gulliver’s Travels. In The Collected Essays, Journalism, and Letters of George Orwell. Edited by Sonia Orwell and Ian Angus. London: Secker and Warburg. First published 1946. [Google Scholar]
- Parmenides. 1965. Parmenides. A Text with Translation, Commentary, and Critical Essays. Edited by Leonardo Tarán. Princeton: Princeton UP. [Google Scholar]
- Pevear, Richard. 1995. Preface. In Tolstoy. What Is Art? London: Penguin Classics. [Google Scholar]
- Pitari, Paolo. 2020. The Influence of Sartre’s ‘What Is Literature?’ On David Foster Wallace’s Literary Project. Critique: Studies in Contemporary Fiction 61: 423–39. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pitari, Paolo. 2021a. The Influence of Leo Tolstoy’s What Is Art? On David Foster Wallace’s Literary Project. Critique: Studies in Contemporary Fiction 62: 69–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pitari, Paolo. 2021b. The Problem of Literary Truth in Plato’s Republic and Aristotle’s Poetics. Literature 1: 14–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pitari, Paolo. 2022. Aeschylus at the Origin of Philosophy: Emanuele Severino’s Interpretation of the Aeschylean Tragedies. Literature 2: 106–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Proust, Marcel. 1941. Remembrance of Things Past. London: Chatto & Windus. [Google Scholar]
- Putnam, Hilary. 1976. Literature, Science, and Reflection. New Literary History 7: 483–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ricoeur, Paul. 1979. History as Narrative Practice. Philosophy Today 29: 213–22. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Rorty, Richard. 1982. Problem about Fictional Discourse? In Consequences of Pragmatism: Essays 1972–1980. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rorty, Richard. 1989. Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. Cambridge: Cambridge UP. [Google Scholar]
- Rowe, Michael W. 2004. Lamarque and Olsen on Literature and Truth. In Rowe. Philosophy and Literature: A Book of Essays. Farnham: Ashgate. First published 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Russell, Bertrand. 1995. An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth. London: Routledge. First published 1950. [Google Scholar]
- Russell, Bertrand. 2004. History of Western Philosophy. London: Routledge. First published 1945. [Google Scholar]
- Searle, John. 1975. The Logical Status of Fictional Discourse. New Literary History 6: 319–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Shakespeare, William. 2013. Hamlet. Oxford: Oxford World’s Classics. First published 1603. [Google Scholar]
- Shestov, Lev. 1969. Dostoevsky, Tolstoy and Nietzsche. Translated by Spencer Roberts. Athens: Ohio UP. [Google Scholar]
- Stecker, Robert. 1994. Art Interpretation. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 52: 193–206. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stecker, Robert. 1996. What Is Literature? Revue Internationale de Philosophie 50: 681–94. [Google Scholar]
- Sutrop, Margit. 2002. Imagination and the Act of Fiction-Making. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 80: 332–44. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tolstoy, Leo. 2001. Anna Karenina. London: Penguin Books. First published 1877. [Google Scholar]
- Trilling, Lionel. 1980. The Poet as Hero; Keats in his Letters. In Trilling. The Opposing Self: Nine Essays in Criticism. Oxford: Oxford UP. First published 1951. [Google Scholar]
- Urmson, James Opie. 1977. Literature. In Aesthetics: A Critical Anthology. Edited by Dickie and Sclafani. New York: St Martin’s Press. [Google Scholar]
- Voltaire. 1958. Candide, ou, L’Optimisme. London: Hodder and Stoughton. First published 1759. [Google Scholar]
- Walsh, Dorothy. 1969. Literature and Knowledge. Middletown: Wesleyan UP. [Google Scholar]
- Weitz, Morris. 1963a. A la Recherche du Temps Perdu: Philosophy as Artistic Vision. In Weitz. Philosophy in Literature. Detroit: Wayne State UP. First published 1913–1927. [Google Scholar]
- Weitz, Morris. 1963b. Hamlet: Philosophy and the Intruder. In Weitz. Philosophy in Literature. Detroit: Wayne State UP. [Google Scholar]
- Wilson, Catherine. 1983. Literature and Knowledge. Philosophy 58: 489–96. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wollheim, Richard. 1980. Art and its Objects, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge UP. First published 1968. [Google Scholar]
- Woolf, Virginia. 1966. Mr. Bennett and Mrs. Brown. In Collected Essays: Volume I. London: Chatto and Windus. First published 1924. [Google Scholar]
- Woolf, Virginia. 1982. A Writer’s Diary. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. [Google Scholar]
- Woolf, Virginia. 1988. Modern Novels. In The Essays of Virginia Woolf. Vol 3, 1919–1924. London: Hogarth Press. First published 1919. [Google Scholar]
- Woolf, Virginia. 2000a. Mrs Dalloway. London: Penguin. First published 1925. [Google Scholar]
- Woolf, Virginia. 2000b. To the Lighthouse. London: Penguin. First published 1927. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Pitari, P. In Defense of Literary Truth: A Response to Truth, Fiction, and Literature by Peter Lamarque and Stein Haugom Olsen to Inquire into No-Truth Theories of Literature, Pragmatism, and the Ontology of Fictional Objects. Literature 2023, 3, 1-18. https://doi.org/10.3390/literature3010001
Pitari P. In Defense of Literary Truth: A Response to Truth, Fiction, and Literature by Peter Lamarque and Stein Haugom Olsen to Inquire into No-Truth Theories of Literature, Pragmatism, and the Ontology of Fictional Objects. Literature. 2023; 3(1):1-18. https://doi.org/10.3390/literature3010001
Chicago/Turabian StylePitari, Paolo. 2023. "In Defense of Literary Truth: A Response to Truth, Fiction, and Literature by Peter Lamarque and Stein Haugom Olsen to Inquire into No-Truth Theories of Literature, Pragmatism, and the Ontology of Fictional Objects" Literature 3, no. 1: 1-18. https://doi.org/10.3390/literature3010001
APA StylePitari, P. (2023). In Defense of Literary Truth: A Response to Truth, Fiction, and Literature by Peter Lamarque and Stein Haugom Olsen to Inquire into No-Truth Theories of Literature, Pragmatism, and the Ontology of Fictional Objects. Literature, 3(1), 1-18. https://doi.org/10.3390/literature3010001