Pruning of the People: Ostracism and the Transformation of the Political Space in Ancient Athens
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. The Process of Ostracism
Ostracism takes place as follows. (1) Before the eighth prytany, (2) the people vote on whether it is necessary to hold an ostracism. If it is necessary, the agora is fenced in with boards, leaving ten entrances, through which the people enter in their tribes, and deposit their sherds [ostraka] with the writing facing downwards. (3) The nine archons and the council oversee the process. (4) When the sherds have been counted to determine who has the most votes (and not less than 6000), (5) then this person must, after settling his personal commitments, leave the city within ten days, for a period of ten years (this was later reduced to five years). He is allowed to receive income from his possessions, but he must not come nearer [to Athens] than Geraestum, the headland on [the coast of] Euboea. (Philoch. Frag. 79b)[4].
3. The Aristotelian Concept of Ostracism
If, however, there be some one person, or more than one…whose virtue is so pre-eminent that the virtues or the political capacity of all the rest admit of no comparison with his or theirs, he or they can be no longer regarded as part of a state; for justice will not be done to the superior, if he is reckoned only as the equal of those who are so far inferior to him in excellence and in political capacity. Such a man may truly be deemed a God among men. Hence we see that legislation is necessarily concerned only with those who are equal in birth and in capacity; and that for men or pre-eminent excellence there is no law—they are themselves a law. Anyone would be ridiculous who attempted to make laws for them […] And for this reason democratic states have instituted ostracism; equality is above all things their aim, and therefore they ostracized and banished from the city for a time those who seemed to predominate too much through their wealth, or the number of their friends, or through any other political influence. (3.13, 1284a)
4. The Expulsive View: Benjamin Constant to Militant Democrats
No-one has the right to exile a citizen unless he is legally convicted by a regular court, following a law which explicitly assigns the penalty of exile for the action of which he is guilty. No-one has the right to tear the citizen from his county, the owner from his possessions, the merchant from his trade, the husband from his wife, the father from his children, the writer from his studious meditations, the old man from his accustomed way of life. All political exile is a political abuse. Any exile pronounced by an assembly for alleged reasons of public good is a crime that this assembly commits against the public good, which resides only in respect for the laws, in the observance of forms, and in the maintenance of safeguards[18].
5. Doing Democracy: Individual Reform and Ritual Ostrakophoria
5.1. Reform, Return, and Recall of Leaders
For the banishment by ostracism was not a chastisement of evil character. Whereas euphemistically called a lessening and curtailing of overbearing pride and power, it was in fact a humane consolation of resentment (φθόνου), which thus vented its malignant desire to injure not in some irreparable evil, but in a mere removal for ten years. (Plut. Arist. 7.2)[39].
Indeed, in reckoning up a man’s virtue it is a far greater and nobler thing to be sent into exile and then recalled than not to be sent into exile at all… It is jealousy [that] would seem to have been responsible for Cimon’s being expelled and becoming an exile, but one cannot attribute being recalled and summoned to help to anything other than the virtue that made the Athenians feel ashamed before him even in his absence and convinced that they would benefit from his presence. (Aristid. Or. 148)
5.2. Democracy in Action: Ostrakophoria as a Moment of Collective Expression
6. Conclusions
“[Cleisthenes realized that] it was necessary to create in the multitude, and through them to force upon the leading ambitious men, that rare and difficult sentiment which we may term a constitutional morality… Next, through such tranquil working of the democratical forms [i.e., ostracism], a constitutional morality quite sufficiently complete was produced among the leading Athenians, to enable the people after a certain time to dispense with that exceptional security which the ostracism offered. To the nascent democracy, it was absolutely indispensable; to the growing yet militant democracy, it was salutary; but the full-grown democracy both could and did stand without it”[77] (pp. 155, 160).
[The Athenian constitutional framers] devised an instrument that endured…and one nicely adapted to the political conditions of democratic Greek polis. Behind it was a recognition that what was most to be feared was not ideas or policies but men. The institution worked well because it was adapted to a system of politics in which political ties were in the first instance personal ties. As long as this was the case the removal of the leader would dissolve or at least temporarily incapacitate the group. Ostracism would tend, as Plutarch once phrased it, to ‘undo the hetaireia’ by dissolving the ties which held it together.
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Only male citizens in Athens were subject to being ostracized. |
2 | |
3 | All dates are Before Common Era, unless otherwise noted. |
4 | As the venerable Greek historian George Grote states: “[Ostracism] was not likely to be invoked at all, there-fore, until exasperation had proceeded so far as to render both parties insensible to this chance, the precise index of that growing internecine hostility, which the ostracism prevented from coming to a head […] It was in this way that security was taken not only for making the ostracism effectual in protecting the constitution, but to hinder it from being employed for any other purpose.” [7] (p. 376) |
5 | In brief, though only male citizens participated in the ostrakophoria, it is likely that others participated “de-bating” who should be ostracized in a given year (if an ostracism were to occur at all). |
6 | Grote claims that the “very essence” of ostracism is the secret voting. He also finds that “the process of ostra-cizing included no meeting and haranguing—nothing but simple deposit of the shells in a cask.” [7] (p. 209). |
7 | To be sure, Aristotle makes distinction here between those who have more virtue simpliciter and those who have other qualities which democracies tend to try to equalize. Nevertheless, for Aristotle, the ideas are alike: a person with an excess of virtue/power/wealth/status/etc. is conceptualized as being “not a part of the state,” for better or for worse. |
8 | See also: Andreas Kalyvas, who suggests that: “Ostracism provides a safety-valve to protect the democratic city from individual over-ambition, immoderate self-love, the reckless quest for superiority and hubris” [13] (p. 29). Forsdyke also calls ostracism a “safety valve” in [8] (p. 56) Cf. Friedrich Nietzsche, who claims that “original function of this peculiar institution [ostracism]…is not that of a safety valve but that of a stimulant” [14] (p. 55). |
9 | Obviously Athenian democracy was quite participatory, but many opportunities for participation were based on lot. Moreover, because of ostracism’s high participation quorum, not only did it require active participa-tion by the people, but it also meant that many people had to participate for an ostracism even to occur. |
10 | Largely following Forsdyke’s model of ostracism as a “political tool” of the people, Josiah Ober views ostra-cism as an institution “designed to focus voters’ attention on a calculation of expected public gains and loss-es” of expelling an individual, rather than on the individual’s presumed wrongdoing or past actions (Ober, Democracy and Knowledge: 161). Hence, he characterizes ostracism as a sort of ancient “prediction market” on aggregating opinions about possible future scenarios. Ober’s analysis, like that of militant demo-crats, is largely focused on the demos’ epistemic ability to “identify and eliminate possible internal threats to civic order”[22] (p. 174). A similar view is articulated in [23] George Tridimas, “Conflict, democracy and vot-er choice: a public choice analysis of the Athenian ostracism,” Public Choice 169, no. 1–2 (2016). |
11 | In particular, Müller [29] worries that institutions like ostracism depend on deeming individuals too “un-teachable” to be (re-)integrated into the polity (258). |
12 | Rosenbloom writes that “[a]n ostrakophoria allowed farmers to take over the space of the agora, to vent their anger upon elite citizens, and to drive one into exile” [33] (p. 35.) |
13 | Although Hesiod was not himself Athenian, his work certainly influenced Athenian political thought both before and after the democratic revolution, likely through rhapsodic performances in Athens and perhaps the city’s educational curriculum. See [43]. |
14 | More closely connected to the project of reform, however, is Plato’s treatment of the sophronisterion—the prison for not-incorrigible prisoners. See: (Pl. Leg. 854d5, 907d-909a); for a discussion, see [46] (p. 291). |
15 | There are other instances too in Plato’s thought where notions of pure punishment, as opposed to civic disci-pline, are connected to moral reformation Cf. Pl. Grg. 480b7-d7, Pl. Crit. 121-2. For the relation between Plato’s idea of law and the Athenian conception, see [47] (p. 216). |
16 | One reason attested for Cimon’s ostracism was his pro-Lacedaemonian political stance. But, after he had gone to Tanagra in 457 to fight with the Athenians against the Spartans, the Athenians “did not long abide by their displeasure against Cimon, partly because, as was natural, they remembered his benefits, and partly because the turn of events favored his cause.” (Plut. Cim. 17.6) For more on Cimon’s recall: Theopomp. FGrH. 115 F 88; Plut. Per. 10.3-4. |
17 | Aelius Aristides is a later source, but seems to have had access to primary documents about earlier ostracism. See: ref. [57]. |
18 | In this regard, elites’ tolerance for ostracism bears similarities to Adam Przeworski’s minimalist defense of democracy. To him, electoral democracy is the optimal form of government insofar as it best reduces conflict. Voting and elections, in short, make losers incentivized to just wait until next opportunity for political access (i.e. election) to have power, rather than resorting to war, while voting, understood as an empirical measure of force, compels people to obey the results. See: ref. [58]. |
19 | Kaltwasser calls this the “boomerang effect,” i.e. where anti-democrats (especially populists), once pushed out of the political fray, come to “challenge the very legitimacy of unelected institutions to make decisions” and gain an additional following through increased publicity. See: ref. [61]. |
20 | With the notable exception of EXIT-Deutschland, which aims to help disengage, deradicalize, and reintegrate right-wing extremists in Germany. According to Bercyzk and Vermeulen, “The EXIT team arranges contacts with various state institutions and civil society actors, provides practical advice and helps to strengthen the individual’s skills and competencies. It also attempts to address concerns regarding social problems, personal safety and individual reappraisal. In sum, EXIT assists defectors in restructuring their lives.” See: ref. [60] (p. 98). |
21 | With perhaps the exception of Hyperbolus, the exception to break the rule. See: ref. [33] (p. 243). |
22 | Some, such as Rosenbloom [33] and Carcopino [53], have tried to argue that the ostrakophoria took place in the agora for purely practical reasons, but these analyses seem to completely ignore the implicit and overt pro-democratic symbols that were spread throughout the public marketplace. Moreover, their analyses might not stand up to factual critique. For a critique, see: ref. [32] (p. 145). |
23 | Pierre Rosanvallon defined le politique, or “the political,” as “a mode of existence of life in common as well as a form of collective action…. To speak of ‘the political’—as opposed to ‘politics’ (la politique)—is to speak of power and law, state and nation, equality and justice, identity and difference, citizenship and civility, in short of everything that makes up a polity beyond the immediate field of partisan conflict for power, governmental conflict from day to day, and the ordinary activity of institutions.” See: ref. [66] (p. 11). |
24 | Furthermore, Mann writes that “[f]rom a thematic point of view, moral deviations and economic resources prevail along with the specific status symbols of the aristocracy. Conversely, antagonism among political leaders is of no importance in the ostraka themselves.” In: ref. [17] (p. 66). |
25 | Gauthier’s evidence of such is that the figure of 6000 was preserved over time regardless of the actual num-ber of citizens. A quorum of 6000 was also required for other procedures, including the granting of immunity from legal prosecution (ex. adeia and the granting of citizenship). Ref. [67]. |
26 | For example, Solon made ‘speaking badly’ a punishable offense in the 4th cent (fr. 32f. Ruschenbusch). In Pla-to’s Laws the Athenian Stranger also identifies the agora as a place where such slander occurs if not for official oversight. (Leg. 7.817; 11.935). |
27 | As example of the former is Germany’s Initiative Demokratie Stärken (“strengthening democracy initiative”), whose “priority is to finance educational and intercultural approaches mainly aimed at strengthening young people’s resilience against radical influences” (97). An example of the latter is Germany’s Mobiles Beratungsteam gegen Rechtsextremismus (MBT), (“Counselling Team against Right-Wing Extremism”) which both increases community knowledge of right-wing extremism and also emphasizes the role of local democ-racy in protecting human rights and preventing xenophobia. In: ref. [60] (pp. 97–100). |
References
- Raaflaub, K.A. The Alleged Ostracism of Damon. In Gestures: Essays in Ancient History, Literature, and Philosophy Presented to Alan L Boegehold; Bakewell, G.W., Sickinger, J.P., Eds.; Oxbow Books: Oxford, UK, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Olsen, T.V. The elitist defence of democracy against populists using education and money. Crit. Rev. Int. Soc. Political Philos. 2022, 1–12. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pedahzur, A. The defending democracy and the extreme right: A comparative analysis. In Western Democracies and the New Extreme Right Challenge; Eatwell, R., Mudde, C., Eds.; Routledge: London, UK, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Jones, N.F. Philochoros of Athens (328); Brill’s New Jacoby: Online, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Malkopoulou, A. Ostracism and democratic self-defense in Athens. Constellations 2017, 24, 623–636. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ober, J. Democracy and Knowledge: Innovation and Learning in Classical Athens; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Grote, G. A History of Greece: Volume III; Harper & Brothers: New York, NY, USA, 1880. [Google Scholar]
- Forsdyke, S. Exile, Ostracism, and Democracy: The Politics of Expulsion in Ancient Greece; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Rosivach, V.J. Some Fifth and Fourth Century Views on the Purpose of Ostracism. TYCHE—Contrib. Anc. Hist. Papyrol. Epigr. 1988, 2, 161–171. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hall, L.G. Remarks on the law of Ostracism. TYCHE—Contrib. Anc. Hist. Papyrol. Epigr. 1990, 4, 10. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Everson, S. (Ed.) Aristotle: The Politics and the Constitution of Athens; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Raubitschek, A.E. The Origin of Ostracism. Am. J. Archaeol. 1951, 55, 221–229. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kalyvas, A. The Democratic Narcissus: The Agonism of the Ancients Compared to that of the (Post)Moderns. In Law and Agonistic Politics; Schaap, A., Ed.; Routledge: London, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Nietzsche, F. Homer’s Contest. In Political Writings of Friedrich Nietzsche: An Edited Anthology; Cameron, F., Dombowsky, D., Eds.; Springer: Basingstoke, UK, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Barbato, M. ‘For Themistocles of Phrearrhior, on Account of Honour’: Ostracism, honour, and the Nature of Athenian Politics. Class. Q. 2021, 71, 500–519. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Siewert, P. Accuse contro i «candidati» all’ostracismo per la loro condotta politica e morale. In L’Immagine Dell’uomo Politico: Vita Pubblica e Morale Nell’antichità; Sordi, M., Ed.; Vita E Pensiero: Milan, Italy, 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Mann, C. Potere del popolo—Disciplinamento dell’aristocrazia—Sulla funzione dell’ostracismo ateniese. In Die Sprache des Politischen in Actu: Zum Verhältnis von Politischem Handeln und Politischer Sprache von der Antike bis ins 20. Jahrhundert; De Benedictis, A., Corni, G., Mazohl, B., Schorn-Schütte, L., Eds.; Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co.: Göttingen, Germany, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Constant, B. The Liberty of the Ancients Compared with That of the Moderns. Early Modern Texts, Last Modified April 2010. Available online: https://www.earlymoderntexts.com/assets/pdfs/constant1819.pdf (accessed on 22 July 2022).
- Williams, K.D.; Gerber, J. Ostracism. Interact. Stud. 2005, 6, 359–374. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Roberts, J.T. Athens on Trial: The Antidemocratic Tradition in Western Thought; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Forsdyke, S. Exile, Ostracism and the Athenian Democracy. Class. Antiq. 2000, 19, 232–263. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ober, J. The Rise and Fall of Classical Greece; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Tridimas, G. Conflict, democracy and voter choice: A public choice analysis of the Athenian ostracism. Public Choice 2016, 169, 137–159. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zhang, A. Ostracism and Democracy. N. Y. Univ. Law Rev. Online 2021, 96, 235. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Malkopoulou, A. De-presentation rights as a response to extremism. Crit. Rev. Int. Soc. Political Philos. 2016, 19, 301–319. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Müller, J.-W. Individual Militant Democracy. In Militant Democracy and Its Critics: Populism, Parties, Extremism; Malkopoulou, A., Kirshner, A.S., Eds.; Edinburgh University Press: Edinburgh, UK, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Kirshner, A.S. Legitimate Opposition, Ostracism, and the Law of Democracy in Ancient Athens. J. Politics 2016, 78, 1094–1106. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kirshner, A.S. A Theory of Militant Democracy: The Ethics of Combatting Political Extremism; Yale University Press: New Haven, CT, USA, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Müller, J.-W. Protecting Popular Self-Government from the People? New Normative Perspectives on Militant Democracy. Annu. Rev. Political Sci. 2016, 19, 249–265. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Malkopoulou, A. Flipped Elections: Can Recalls Improve Democracy? The Conversation, Last Modified 14 October 2015. Available online: https://theconversation.com/flipped-elections-can-recalls-improve-democracy-46395 (accessed on 22 July 2022).
- Ginsburg, T.; Huq, A.Z.; Landau, D. The Law of Democratic Disqualification. Calif. Law Rev. 2023, 111, 791. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kosmin, P.J. A Phenomenology of Democracy. Class. Antiq. 2015, 34, 121–162. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rosenbloom, D.S. Poneroi vs. Chrestoi: The Ostracism of Hyperbolos and the Struggle for Hegemony in Athens after the Death of Perikles. Trans. Am. Philol. Assoc. 2004, 134, 55–105. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. Laws; Bury, R.G., Translator; William Heinemann: London, UK, 1914. [Google Scholar]
- Kuokkanen, S. Ostracism, Inner Change and the Dynamics of Reintegration in Classical Athens. In Political Refugees in the Ancient Greek World: Literary, Historical and Philosophical Essays; Loddo, L., Ed.; Presses Universitaires du Midi: Toulouse, France, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Møller, B. Punitive and/or Preventative Confinement. In Refugees, Prisoners and Camps: A Functional Analysis of the Phenomenon of Encampment; Springer: Basingstoke, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Gray, B.D. Stasis and Stability: Exile, the Polis, and Political Thought, C. 404–146 B.C.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Ostwald, M. The reform of the Athenian state by Cleisthenes. In The Cambridge Ancient History: Plates to Volume IV: Persia, Greece and the Western Mediterranean c.525 to 479 B.C.; Boardman, J., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1988; pp. 303–346. [Google Scholar]
- Plutarch’s Lives; Perrin, B., Translator; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1914. [Google Scholar]
- Allen, D.S. The World of Prometheus: The Politics of Punishing in Democratic Athens; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Hesiod. Theogony and Works and Days; West, M.L., Translator; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Graziosi, B. Hesiod in classical Athens: Rhapsodes, orators, and Platonic discourse. In Plato and Hesiod; Boys-Stones, G.R., Ed.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Lye, S. The Goddress Styx and the Mapping of World Order in Hesiod’s “Theogony”. Rev. Philos. Ancienne 2009, 27, 3–31. [Google Scholar]
- Tripkovic, M. Punishment and Citizenship: A Theory of Criminal Disenfranchisement; Oxford University Press: London, UK, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Rademaker, A. Sophrosyne and the Rhetoric of Self-Restraint: Polysemy & Persuasive Use of an Ancient Greek Value Term; BRILL: Leiden, The Netherlands, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Cohen, D. Law, Sexuality, and Society: The Enforcement of Morals in Classical Athens; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1994. [Google Scholar]
- Lonis, R. ‘La condition des réfugiés politiques en Grèce: Statut et privilèges’, in Mactoux and Geny. In Hellènika symmikta: Histoire, Archéologie, Épigraphie, Vol. VII; Goukowsky, P., Brixhe, C., Eds.; Presses Université de Nancy: Nancy, France, 1995; Volume 491, pp. 209–225. [Google Scholar]
- Sacco, L. Il pharmakos nelle fonti antiche e nella Storia delle religioni. Alcune valutazioni critiche. Mythos 2018, 12, 103–115. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vernant, J.-P.; Vidal-Naquet, P. Mythe et Tragédie en Grèce Ancienne; François Maspero: Paris, France, 1972. [Google Scholar]
- Compton, T. The Pharmakos in Archaic Greece. In Victim of the Muses: Poet as Scapegoat, Warrior, and Hero in Greco-Roman and Indo-European Myth and History; Harvard University Center for Hellenic Studies: Cambridge, UK, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Parker, R.A. Miasma: Pollution and Purification in Early Greek Religion; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Figueira, T.J. Residential Restrictions on the Athenian Ostracized. Greek Rom. Byzantine Stud. 1987, 28, 281–305. [Google Scholar]
- Carcopino, J. Histoire de L’ostracisme Athénien; Alcan: Paris, France, 1935. [Google Scholar]
- Rhodes, P. Theseus the Democrat. Misc. Anthropol. Sociol. 2014, 15, 98–118. [Google Scholar]
- Cawkwell, G. The Fall of Themistocles. In Auckland Classical Essays Presented to E. M. Blaiklock; Harris, B.F., Ed.; Auckland University Press: Auckland, New Zealand, 1970. [Google Scholar]
- Orations, Vol. II; Trapp, M., Translator; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Johansson, M. Plutarch, Aelius Aristides and the Inscription from Troizen. Rheinisches Mus. Philol. 2004, 147, 343–354. [Google Scholar]
- Przeworski, A. Minimalist Definition of Democracy: A Defense. In Democracy’s Values; Shapiro, I., Hacker-Cordón, C., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Węcowski, M. Athenian Ostracism and Its Original Purpose: A Prisoner’s Dilemma; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2022. [Google Scholar]
- Berczyk, J.; Vermeulen, F. Prevent abroad: Militant democracy, right-wing extremism and the prevention of Islamic extremism in Berlin. In Counter-Radicalisation: Critical Perspectives; Baker-Beall, C., Heath-Kelly, C., Jarvis, L., Eds.; Routledge: London, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Kaltwasser, C.R. Militant Democracy Versus Populism. In Militant Democracy and Its Critics: Populism, Parties, Extremism; Malkopoulou, A., Kirshner, A.S., Eds.; Edinburgh University Press: Edinburgh, UK, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Brennan, G.; Lomasky’s, L. Democracy and Decision: The Pure Theory of Electoral Preference; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Connor, W.R. The New Politicians of Fifth-Century Athens; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1972. [Google Scholar]
- Tridimas, G. Homo Oeconomicus in Ancient Athens: Silver Bonanza and the Choice to Build a Navy. Homo Oeconomicus 2013, 30, 435–458. [Google Scholar]
- Hamlin, A.; Jennings, C. Expressive Political Behaviour: Foundations, Scope and Implications. Br. J. Political Sci. 2011, 41, 645–670. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rosanvallon, P. Democracy Past and Future; Moyn, S., Ed.; Columbia University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Gauthier, P. Quorum et participation civique dans lés democraties grecques’. In Du Pouvoir Dans l’Antiquité: Mots et Réalités; Nicolet, C., Ed.; Librairie Droz: Geneva, Switzerland, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Rhodes, P.J. The Ostracism of Hyperbolus. In Ritual, Finance, Politics: Athenian Democratic Accounts Presented to David Lewis; Osborne, R., Hornblower, S., Eds.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Simonton, M. Stability and Violence in Classical Greek Democracies and Oligarchies. Class. Antiq. 2017, 36, 52–103. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Millett, P. Encounters in the Agora. In Kosmos: Essays in Order, Conflict and Community in Classical Athens; Cartledge, P., Millett, P., Reden, S.V., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Gottesman, A. Politics and the Street in Democratic Athens; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Hölscher, T. Image and Political Identity: The Case of Athens. In Democracy, Empire, and the Arts in Fifth-Century Athens; Boedeker, D.D., Raaflaub, K.A., Eds.; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Ober, J. Tyrant Killing as Therapeutic Stasis: A Political Debate in Images and Texts. In Popular Tyranny: Sovereignty and Its Discontents in Ancient Greece; Morgan, K.A., Ed.; University of Texas Press: Austin, TX, USA, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Ma, J. Statues and Cities: Honorific Portraits and Civic Identity in the Hellenistic World; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Capoccia, G. Militant Democracy and the Study of Political Tolerance. In Militant Democracy and Its Critics: Populism, Parties, Extremism; Malkopoulou, A., Kirshner, A., Eds.; Edinburgh University Press: Edinburgh, UK, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Loewenstein, K. Militant Democracy and Fundamental Rights, I. Am. Political Sci. Rev. 1937, 31, 417–432. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Grote, G. A History of Greece, Vol. IV; Harper & Brothers: New York, NY, USA, 1880. [Google Scholar]
- Arendt, H. The Origins of Totalitarianism; Houghton Mifflin Harcourt: Orlando, FL, USA, 1973. [Google Scholar]
- Gray, B. From exile of citizens to deportation of non-citizens: Ancient Greece as a mirror to illuminate a modern transition. Citizsh. Stud. 2011, 15, 565–582. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gibney, M.J. Banishment and the pre-history of legitimate expulsion power. Citizsh. Stud. 2019, 24, 277–300. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sajo, A. From Militant Democracy to the Preventive State. Cardozo Law Rev. 2006, 27, 2255. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Salamanca, E. Pruning of the People: Ostracism and the Transformation of the Political Space in Ancient Athens. Philosophies 2023, 8, 81. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8050081
Salamanca E. Pruning of the People: Ostracism and the Transformation of the Political Space in Ancient Athens. Philosophies. 2023; 8(5):81. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8050081
Chicago/Turabian StyleSalamanca, Emily. 2023. "Pruning of the People: Ostracism and the Transformation of the Political Space in Ancient Athens" Philosophies 8, no. 5: 81. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8050081
APA StyleSalamanca, E. (2023). Pruning of the People: Ostracism and the Transformation of the Political Space in Ancient Athens. Philosophies, 8(5), 81. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8050081