Concerning the Epistemology of Design: The Role of the Eco-Cognitive Model of Abduction in Pragmatism
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Abduction and Pragmatism: The Bases for Scientific Praxis
The debate concerning the role of theory versus the role of experiment is an old one in the philosophy of science, and it has crystallized in the comparison between Theoretical Traditions (TT) and Experimental Traditions (ET). From the perspective of TT, the philosophy of science has fundamentally focused on theoretical models, on established laws and principles, and ultimately on the reconstruction of scientific theories, leaving experimentation to play a secondary role.[15] (pp. 3–4)
The conception that is emerging in the philosophy of science in ET is supported by the cognitive models that address motor cognition, and that we could see as one of the consequences of the interactive and dynamic vision proposed by Churchland, Ramachandran and Sejnowski in 1994.[15] (p. 11)
- Thesis of autonomy: Abduction is a type of inference different from deduction and induction.
- Thesis of inference: Abduction infers hypotheses that do not follow from its premises. Following the argumentation in this section, it may seem strange to affirm this Thesis 2: that abduction is an inference. However, it is important to see that the rejection of its inferential power is in relation to its premises and not as a genuine process. In this sense, abduction has the power to infer novel hypotheses.
- Thesis of purpose: The principal objective of an abduction is to generate and select new hypotheses. This implies, in turn, that the subsequent steps of implementation, testing, etc., of a hypothesis are not part of abduction.
- Thesis of comprehension: Taking a maximal point of view, abduction encompasses most of the operations through which knowledge is acquired.
Peirce’s rejection of incognisable things-in-themselves (5.452), owing to just this very critical restriction, leads him to the possibility—in fact the unavoidability—of a realist metaphysics, a metaphysics whose hypothetical postulates must all be fallible, but whose general concepts must be able to prove their objective validity “in the long”. This is because we cannot conceive the “real” to be anything other than that which is “cognizable” (5.275). By starting with a critique of meaning, Peirce makes room for a sweeping evolutionary metaphysics in the vein of Hegel and Schelling.
- (1)
- The world of pure experience—the experience that configures reality is structured from a continuous flow of information;
- (2)
- Fallibilism—continuous experience means that knowledge is always provisional to a certain degree, which forces us to review and adapt our beliefs in accordance with the changes we experience [23].
2.1. The Epistemological Taxonomy of Abductive Reasoning
The Eco-Cognitive Model of Abduction
- (1)
- Optimisation of the situation (contextualisation of cognitive processes).
- (2)
- Maximisation of the mutability between the different roles that the elements which constitute the context acquire.
- (3)
- Condition 1 is met because abduction meets the requirement of being a sensitive mechanism of constant absorption of information.
- (4)
- Contemplation of the inferential richness available to the human cognitive apparatus (multimodality) [24] (pp. 138–139).
- Knowledge of particularities (facts) presupposes knowledge of theories,
- Knowledge of theories presupposes knowledge of facts (particularities),
- Knowledge of facts presupposes knowledge of values,
- Knowledge of values presupposes knowledge of facts,
- Knowledge of facts presupposes knowledge of interpretations, and
- Knowledge of interpretations presupposes knowledge of facts.
3. Design Epistemology
Wholeness is the quality that characterizes a perfectly developed and healthy organism, or a complete and immaculately functioning mechanism: All the parts work well and in synergy with one another, and fulfill their purpose within the whole, so that the whole can function well and fulfill its purposes within even larger wholes.[52] (p. 3)
4. Pragmatism as the Epistemic Basis of Design Theory
The pragmatist philosophy of Dewey as an appropriate philosophical foundation for design theoretical reasoning, as it includes a distinctive theory of knowledge and research. It can integrate both the scientific methods, the reflective and interpretative methods of the social sciences and the humanities, but it cannot be fully understood in the light of one of these. It needs its own paradigm or epistemology.[54] (p. 11)
Design is a controlled creative action; design knowledge is a set of repertoires intended to enable the managing of problems, desires, values and puzzling situations, and the changing of an existing situation into a preferred one; a design problem is not a single and simple issue, but rather a complex situation where we want to improve or change something; and creativity is the dynamic capability to manage problems and situations, and to generate solutions that match expectations.[54] (p. 8)
- The implications for design of a pragmatic perspective (the theses of Östman and Dalsgaard that we are addressing in this section).
- The application of the concepts of pragmatism in various fields of the humanities [22].
5. Convergence between the EC Model and the Epistemology of Design
- The implications of a pragmatic perspective for design (the theses of Östman and Dalsgaard that we are considering in this section).
- The application of the concepts of pragmatism in diverse fields of the humanities [22].
5.1. Design Thinking Is an Abductive-Based Process
5.2. The Value of the Future for the Epistemology of Design
- (a)
- Our cognitive processes are mediated by the way we interact with our surroundings; and
- (b)
- Due to the fact that all the resources that we have available to understand what surrounds us act to make sense of what we experience through the abductive process.
6. Conclusions
Author Contributions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | The programme for the naturalisation of philosophy involves questioning a priori epistemology and a commitment towards taking the empirical results of the sciences into account when configuring epistemic and methodological models. As an example of this type of analysis, see Estany [5] on the debate between neutral and theory-laden observation. This is a noted example. |
2 | CP is the internationally recognised abbreviation for the Collected Papers of Peirce. |
3 | These explanations of the theses are ours, not those of Kapitan. Our objective is simply to introduce the basic notions for readers who are not familiar with the theory of abduction. |
4 | C.f., [21] p. 29–30. |
5 | The classic schematic representations of abduction are known as the AKM schema and the GW schema. With regard to the first, the A refers to Aliseda [34,35], the K to Kowalski [35], Kakas et al. [36] and Kuipers [37], and the M to Magnani [30] and Meheus [38]. Similarly, the second is named for Gabbay and Woods [27]. |
6 | We are referring here to inductive hypotheses or hypotheses that are to be tested, as propounded by Hempel, which have influenced the philosophy of science considerably [40] (ch. 2). |
7 | We use the term “cosmovision” to refer to the unified image of social and cultural interpretations of the world generated by human agents [43]. |
8 | That is, relativism that arises precisely because we do not start from a holistic perspective. |
9 | Design sciences are the result of a process of scientification and mechanisation of the arts, seen as practical activities and skills. H. Simon [49] refers to sciences such as engineering, medicine, architecture and education, the aim of which is not only to know how things are but how they need to be in order to achieve certain practical ends. |
10 | Although Östman applies it to architecture, the general principles and criteria for considering design epistemology suitable for the field of architecture are the same as those behind its suitability for medicine and research in the health sciences in general. For a case study in medicine see Estany [55]. |
References
- Goldman, A.I. Epistemology and Cognition; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1986. [Google Scholar]
- Giere, R.N. Explaining Science: A Cognitive Approach; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- Hanson, N.R. Patterns of Discovery; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1958. [Google Scholar]
- Grosser, M. The Discovery of Neptune; Dover Publications: New York, NY, USA, 1979. [Google Scholar]
- Estany, A. The Theory-Laden Thesis of Observation in the Light of Cognitive Psychology. Philos. Sci. 2001, 68, 203–217. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mahdjoubi, D. Epistemology of design. In Proceedings of the Integrated Design and Process Technology, Austin, TX, USA, December 2003; pp. 1–5. [Google Scholar]
- Laudan, H. Progress and Its Problems: Towards a Theory of Scientific Growth; University of California Press: Berkeley, CA, USA, 1977. [Google Scholar]
- Kuhn, T.S. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1962. [Google Scholar]
- Feyerabend, P.K. Against Method; Verso: New York, NY, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Hanson, N.R. Observation and Explanation: A Guide to Philosophy of Science; George Allen & Unwin: London, UK, 1971. [Google Scholar]
- Lakatos, I. The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes: Philosophical Papers; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1978. [Google Scholar]
- Peirce, C.S. Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce (1866–1913); Hartshorne, C., Weiss, P., Burks, A., Eds.; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1974; Volumes 1–8. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. Analytica Priora et Posteriora; Ross, W.D., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1957. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, I. Critique of Pure Reason; Guyer, P., Wood, A.W., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Estany, A. The Stabilizing Role of Material Structure in Scientific Practice. Philos. Study 2012, 2, 398–410. [Google Scholar]
- Marr, D. Vision: A Computational Investigation into the Human Representation and Processing of Visual Information; Freeman, W.H., Ed.; The MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1982. [Google Scholar]
- Churchland, P.S.; Ramachandran, V.S.; Sejnowski, T.J. A Critique of Pure Vision. In Large-Scale Neural Theories of the Brain; Koch, C., Ed.; The MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1994; pp. 23–60. [Google Scholar]
- Fann, K.T. Peirce’s Theory of Abduction; Martinus Nijhoff: The Hague, The Netherlands, 1970. [Google Scholar]
- Kapitan, T. Peirce and the structure of abductive inference. In Studies in the Logic of Charles Sanders Peirce; Houser, N., Roberts, D.D., van Evra, J., Eds.; Indiana University Press: Bloomington, IN, USA, 1997; pp. 477–496. [Google Scholar]
- Adúriz-Bravo, A.; Sans Pinillos, A. Abduction as a Mode of Inference in Science Education. Sci. Educ. 2022. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Apel, K.-O. Der Denkweg Von Charles S. Peirce. Eine Einführung in Den Amerikanischen Pragmatismus; Suhrkamp Verlag: Berlin, Germany, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- West, C. The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of Pragmatism; The University of Wisconsin Press: Madison, WI, USA, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Sans Pinillos, A. Neglected Pragmatism: Discussing Abduction to Dissolute Classical Dichotomies. Found. Sci. 2021, 27, 1107–1125. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Magnani, L. The Abductive Structure of Scientific Creativity: An Essay on the Ecology of Cognition; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Brandom, R. Articulating Reason: An Introduction to Inferentialism; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Christensen, B.T.; Ball, L.J. Dimensions of creative evaluation: Distinct design and reasoning strategies for aesthetic, functional and originality judgments. Des. Stud. 2016, 45, 116–136. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gabbay, M.; Wood, J. A Practical Logic of Cognitive Systems: The Reach of Abduction—Insight and Trial; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Aliseda, A. Abductive Reasoning: Logical Investigations into Discovery and Explanation; Springer Science + Business Media B.V: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Estany, A.; Herrera, R.M. Innovación en el Saber Teórico y Práctico; College Publications: London, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Magnani, L. Abduction, Reason, and Science: Processes of Discovery and Explanation; Kluwer/Plenum: New York, NY, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Sans Pinillos, A. El lado epistemológico de las abducciones: La creatividad en las verdades-proyectadas. Rev. Iberoam. Argum. 2017, 15, 77–91. [Google Scholar]
- Adúriz-Bravo, A.; González Galli, L. Darwin’s Ideas as Epitomes of Abductive Reasoning in the Teaching of School Scientific Explanation and Argumentation. In Handbook of Abductive Cognition; Magnani, L., Ed.; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2022. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Thagard, P. Computational Philosophy of Science; The MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- Aliseda, A. Seeking Explanations: Abduction in Logic, Philosophy of Science and Artificial Intelligence. Ph.D. Thesis, Institute for Logic, Language and Computation, Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Kowalski, R.A. Logic for Problem Solving; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 1979. [Google Scholar]
- Kakas, A.; Kowalski, R.A.; Toni, F. Abductive logic programming. J. Log. Comput. 1993, 2, 719–770. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kuipers, T.A.F. Abduction aiming at empirical progress of even truth approximation leading to challenge for computational modelling. Found. Sci. 1999, 4, 307–323. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Meheus, J.; Verhoeven, L.; Van Dyck, M.; Provijn, D. Ampliative adaptive logics and the foundation of logic-based approaches to abduction. In Logical and Computational Aspects of Model-Based Reasoning; Magnani, L., Nersessian, N.J., Pizzi, C., Eds.; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2002; pp. 39–71. [Google Scholar]
- Vallverdú, J.; Sans Pinillos, A. The Foundations of Creativity: Human Inquiry Explained through the Neuro-Multimodality of Abduction. In Handbook of Abductive Cognition; Magnani, L., Ed.; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2022. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hempel, C.G. Philosophy of Natural Science; Prentice Hall: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 1966. [Google Scholar]
- Woods, J. Errors of Reasoning: Naturalizing the Logic of Inference; College Publications: London, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Magnani, L. The eco-cognitive model of abduction. Aπαγωγή now: Naturalizing the logic of abduction. J. Appl. Log. 2015, 13, 285–315. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Magnani, L.; Sans Pinillos, A.; Arfini, S. Language: The “Ultimate Artifact” to Build, Develop, and Update Worldviews. Topoi 2021, 41, 461–470. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Shanahan, M. Perception as abduction: Turning sensor data into meaningful representation. Cogn. Sci. 2005, 29, 103–134. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Park, W. Abduction in Context: The Conjectural Dynamics of Scientific Reasoning; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Putnam, H. The Collapse of the Fact/Value Dichotomy; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Putnam, H. El Pragmatismo. Un Debate Abierto; Editorial Gedisa: Sevilla, Spain, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Cross, N. Designerly Ways of Knowing; Springer: London, UK, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Simon, H. The Science of the Artificial, 3rd ed.; The MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Niiniluoto, I. The aim and structure of applied research. Erkenntnis 1993, 38, 1–21. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bengoa, G. Distintos acercamientos epistemológicos: Cinco enfoques sobre los objetos. In Seminario en la Facultad de Arquitectura, Diseño y Urbanismo; UBA Universidad de Buenos Aires: Buenos Aires, Argentina, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Karabeg, D. Design Epistemology. Information 2012, 3, 621–634. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Östman, L.E. Design theory is a philosophical discipline-Reframing the epistemological issues in design theory. In Proceedings of the 6th Academy of Design Conference, Bremen, Germany, 29–31 March 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Östman, L.E. A Pragmatist Theory of Design. The Impact of the Pragmatist Philosophy of John Dewey on Architecture and Design. Ph.D. Thesis, School of Architecture Royal Institute of Technology, Stockholm, Sweden, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Estany, A. Design epistemology for public health research. In Philosophical and Methodological Debates in Public Health; Estany, A., Vallverdú, J., Puyol, A., Eds.; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2019; pp. 85–106. [Google Scholar]
- Dalsgaard, P. Pragmatism and Design Thinking. Int. J. Des. 2014, 8, 143–155. [Google Scholar]
- Magnani, L. Computational domestication of ignorant entities. Synthese 2021, 198, 7503–7532. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Festenstein, M. John Dewey: Inquiry, Ethics and Democracy. In Oxford Handbook Of American Philosophy; Misak, C., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2008; pp. 87–109. [Google Scholar]
- Putnam, H. Ethics without Ontology; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Dorst, K. The core of ‘design thinking’ and its application. Des. Stud. 2011, 32, 521–532. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brooks, F.P. The Design of Design: Essays from a Computer Scientist; Addison-Wesley Professional: Boston, MA, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Martin, R. The Design of Business; Harvard Business Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Kolko, J. Abductive Thinking and Sensemaking: The Drivers of Design Synthesis. Des. Issues 2010, 26, 15–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Magnani, L. Abductive Cognition: The Epistemological and Eco-Cognitive Dimensions of Hypothetical Reasoning; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Park, W. On classifying abduction. J. Appl. Log. 2015, 13, 215–238. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cannizzaro, S.; Anderson, M. Culture as Habit, Habit as Culture: Instinct, Habituescence, Addiction. In Consensus on Peirce’s Concept of Habit; West, D., Anderson, M., Eds.; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2016. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brewer, J.D. Imagining The Sociological Imagination: The biographical context of a sociological classic. Br. J. Sociol. 2004, 55, 317–333. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Adams, V.; Murphy, M.; Clarke, A. Anticipation: Technoscience, life, affect, temporality. Subjectivity 2009, 28, 246–265. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sans Pinillos, A. Abductive Irradiation of Cultural Values in Shared Spaces: The Case of Social Education through Public Libraries. In Handbook of Abductive Cognition; Magnani, L., Ed.; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2022. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Haack, S. Evidence and Inquiry. Towards Reconstruction in Epistemology; Blackwell: Cambridge, UK, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Burckhardt, L. L’archittettura: Arte o scienza? In Arte e Scienza; Feyerabend, P., Thomas, C., Eds.; Armando Editore: Roma, Italy, 1989; pp. 45–46. [Google Scholar]
- Magnani, L.; Bardone, E. Chances, affordances, and cognitive niche construction: The plasticity of environmental situatedness. Int. J. Adv. Intell. Paradig. (IJAIP) 2010, 2, 235–253. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gibson, J. The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems; Allen and Unwin: London, UK, 1966. [Google Scholar]
- Dewey, J. Human Nature and Conduct. An Introduction to Social Psychology; The Modern Library: New York, NY, USA, 1930. [Google Scholar]
- Sans Pinillos, A.; Magnani, L. How Do We Think about the Unknown? The Self-Awareness of Ignorance as a Tool for Managing the Anguish of Not Knowing. In Embodied, Extended, Ignorant Minds: New Studies on the Nature of Not-Knowing; Arfini, S., Magnani, L., Eds.; Synthese Library, Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2022. [Google Scholar]
- Sans Pinillos, A. Distribución abductiva de los valores culturales: El proyecto de Alejandría. In Diseño Institucional e Innovaciones Democráticas; Estany, A., Gensollen, M., Eds.; Universidad Autónoma de Barcelona-Universidad Autónoma de Aguascalientes: Aguascalientes, Mexico, 2022; pp. 333–352. [Google Scholar]
- Adds, P.; Hall, M.; Higgins, R.; Higgins, T.R. Ask the posts of our house: Using cultural spaces to encourage quality learning in higher education. Teach. High. Educ. 2011, 16, 541–551. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lai, L.Y.; Said, I.; Kubota, A. The Roles of Cultural Spaces in Malaysia’s Historic Towns: The Case of Kuala Dungun and Taiping. Procedia-Soc. Behav. Sci. 2013, 85, 602–625. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Deduction | Induction | Abduction |
---|---|---|
Rule: All the beans from this bag are white. Case: These beans are from this bag. therefore Result: These beans are white. | Case: These beans are from this bag. Result: These beans are white. therefore Rule: All the beans from this bag are white. | Rule: All the beans from this bag are white. Result: These beans are white. therefore Case: These beans are from this bag. |
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Sans Pinillos, A.; Estany, A. Concerning the Epistemology of Design: The Role of the Eco-Cognitive Model of Abduction in Pragmatism. Philosophies 2023, 8, 33. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8020033
Sans Pinillos A, Estany A. Concerning the Epistemology of Design: The Role of the Eco-Cognitive Model of Abduction in Pragmatism. Philosophies. 2023; 8(2):33. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8020033
Chicago/Turabian StyleSans Pinillos, Alger, and Anna Estany. 2023. "Concerning the Epistemology of Design: The Role of the Eco-Cognitive Model of Abduction in Pragmatism" Philosophies 8, no. 2: 33. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8020033
APA StyleSans Pinillos, A., & Estany, A. (2023). Concerning the Epistemology of Design: The Role of the Eco-Cognitive Model of Abduction in Pragmatism. Philosophies, 8(2), 33. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8020033