Naturalising Mathematics? A Wittgensteinian Perspective
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Cognitive Neuroscience of Quantitative Competence
2.1. Pre-Verbal Cognition of Quantity
2.2. Limitations of Neuro-Cognitive Research
3. Wittgensteinian Naturalism and Mathematics
3.1. Wittgenstein and Naturalism
3.2. Wittgenstein and Practices
3.3. Mathematics as Practice
4. Training and Education
4.1. Learning Number Names and Counting
4.2. Learning Experiments ‘In Silico’
4.3. Learning to Calculate
5. Second Nature: The Socio-Cultural Acquisition of Symbolic Abilities
5.1. Connecting Culture to Brains
5.2. From Tool Use to Symbol Manipulation
6. Wittgenstein and Mathematics
7. Conclusions and Further Research
Author Contributions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Also called ‘number sense’ [2]. We regard this expression as shorthand for a perceptual system enabling organisms to behaviourally react to (‘recognize’) different discrete quantities of objects. |
2 | Leibovitch et al. emphasized the difficulty to separate in experiments the numerosity of discrete quantities (dots, sounds) from the magnitude of the stimulus (circumference, surface, duration), which could make the question of the selectivity of the ANS for numerosity unanswerable. Their paper attracted more than 30 pages of critical peer comments [8]. Most experts stick to the concept of a specific pre-verbal number sense. |
3 | Throughout we refer to Wittgenstein’s works by the usual acronyms: ‘PI’ for Philosophical Investigations [10]; ‘PPF’ for Philosophy of Psychology: A Fragment [10]; ‘Z’ for Zettel [11]; ‘OC’ for On Certainty [12]; ‘RFM’ for Remarks of the Foundations of Mathematics [13]; ‘LFM’ for Wittgenstein’s Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics [14]. |
4 | Whether subitizing is continuous with the ANS is controversial. Its speed and accuracy versus the slower and inaccurate ANS argue for separate systems [15]. In fMRI experiments, subitizing and ANS tasks activate different regions in the parietal cortex [3]. However, an information–theoretical model suggests a continuity between subitizing and the ANS and accurately predicted experimental results in humans [16]. |
5 | John O’Keefe, May-Britt Moser and Edward Moser discovered the place and grid cells (Nobel prize 2014). |
6 | According to Wittgenstein, ‘One of the most dangerous of ideas for a philosopher is, oddly enough, that we think, with our heads or in our heads.’ (Z, p. 605). |
7 | Bennet and Hacker ([20], p. 143) regard the concept of representation as ‘a weed in the neuroscientific garden, not a tool—and the sooner it is uprooted the better’. However, like most weeds, it proves to be quite resilient. |
8 | Dehaene et al. [17] for instance, reporting their experiments with Amazonian people who lack symbolic mathematical concepts, concluded that ‘core geometric knowledge, like basic arithmetic, is a universal constituent of the human mind’. |
9 | According to Macarthur ([30], p. 46), ‘a metaphysical quietist version of liberal naturalism, one that avoids supernatural theological commitments in philosophy as well as refusing to give science an unwarranted ontological significance’ This view not only rejects the metaphysics of ‘spooky stuff’ such as souls, eternal platonic forms, etc., but also denies scientism and physicalist reductionism. Nature in this view is not only what can be described by physics or biology but includes ‘human nature’, socialization, education, and our daily practices. |
10 | Cf. Stkohof and Lambalgen [35] for an argument to that effect in the context of an analysis of naturalism in linguistics. |
11 | A referee asked us why we have not engaged with the vast corpus of Piagetian studies on the development of logico-mathematical knowledge. The main empirical claim of these studies is that cognitive maturation consists in the acquisition of structures (for example mathematical structures such as groups, logical structures such as propositional logic). The main theoretical claim is that the acquisition of these structures is driven by biological processes aiming at homeostasis between an organism and its environment. This is a multi-factorial dynamic process: the organism acts on the environment, monitors the effects of its actions, and adjusts its behaviour accordingly, and all this against the background of biological maturation. The interaction of these factors is bound to generate discrepancies between the organism’s epistemic state and what it discovers in the environment, and Piaget’s theory claims that the resolution of these discrepancies takes the form of a determined progression of identifiable developmental stages. This claim has been a focal point of criticism. Piaget’s theory of cognitive development is thus an example of a domain-general theory, whereas naturalism in the Wittgensteinian mode tends to be domain-specific. More importantly, Piaget downplays the role of language, whereas this is obviously a core issue for Wittgenstein. Since our intention is to explore the Wittgensteinian perspective and to try and link it to cognitive scientific results, we have left the comparison with Piaget’s naturalism (or more broadly, Kantian forms of naturalism) for another occasion. |
12 | Wittgenstein uses the term ‘language game’, but ‘practice’ is a more neutral term adopted in work on practice theory that is inspired by Wittgenstein (cf., e.g., [45]). |
13 | Similar considerations, though not phrased in terms of certainties, can be found elsewhere, e.g., in LFM, RFM, PI, PPF. |
14 | |
15 | In PI 206, Wittgenstein refers to this as ‘shared human behaviour’. The interplay between these natural constraints and various socio-cultural parameters then accounts for the heterogeneity of certainties and different levels of entrenchment. The terms ‘constrains’ and ‘constraint’ should not be over-interpreted: we do not mean to suggest that what we call ‘constraints’ serve to carve out a specific subdomain from a larger whole that is of the same nature. ‘Natural constraints’ indicates those features of nature (including human nature) that are in a sense ‘inescapable’ and that in virtue of that specify a space of possible frameworks of certainties that humans may entertain. To put it differently, there is a multiplicity of world views that humans may have, but all of them are views of the same world and are entertained by humans that share basic features, and because of these two factors, these world views will share certain characteristics. |
16 | Recent years have seen an increased interest among philosophers and social scientists in the practice of mathematics, i.e., in the social structure of mathematical communities, practices of teaching and training, the pragmatics of proof, the situatedness of the development of mathematical theories, and so on. Cf., e.g., [48,49,50]. A recent book length treatment is Wagner, 2017 [51]. Some of the work in this area takes inspiration from Wittgenstein (for example [51,52,53,54]. The approach taken by these studies is largely complementary to the perspective of cognitive science that is our focus here, which is why an explicit comparison is beyond the scope of this paper and must be left for another occasion. |
17 | The example of the wallpaper decorators (LFM, 36), who produce wallpaper that is adorned with complex proofs of deep mathematical theorems but who lack any knowledge of mathematics, provides an illustration: what are proofs to us are decorations to them; they don’t engage in mathematics: their practice has a completely different point. |
18 | Counting and measuring is relevant in a wide variety of practices. That makes them more akin to what Schatzki ([45], chapter 4) calls ‘dispersed practices’, as opposed to ‘integrative practices’. One important distinction is that the latter have an intrinsic telos. Interestingly, Schatzki argues that dispersed practices adapt to the integrative practices in which they occur. This might be part of an explanation of the pluralism that Wittgenstein endorses. |
19 | See also [55] for the position of non-applied mathematics in Wittgenstein’s descriptions. |
20 | There is ‘obsessive’ counting, but that serves a different purpose; cf., also the case reported by Oliver Sacks of the savant twins that communicate prime numbers [56]: has that anything to do with primes? |
21 | Cf., e.g., Wittgenstein’s reference to ‘the common behaviour of mankind’ in PI 206. His investigations being conceptual rather than empirical, Wittgenstein makes no attempt to come up with an empirically justified further specification. Various remarks throughout his later work do provide some clues, but for reasons of space we cannot go into that here. The interested reader may consult the literature referred to in Section 3.1. |
22 | To be able count sets beyond the size of 4, children are supposed to have grasped that the last numeral in the counting sequence is the number of items in the set. Mastering this ‘cardinality principle’ is assumed to require ‘knowing’ the following procedural principles: (a) the number sequence is stable; (b) number words must be matched one-to-one with objects in a set and (c) irrespective of the kind of objects (abstraction); (d) the order of counting is irrelevant ([58], p. 31). This ‘knowing’ of procedural principles may well be a rational reconstruction which has nothing to do with what is going on in the mind or brain. |
23 | ‘The question (...) is why young children, who have had some understanding of quantity since they were neonates, wait until they are five to six years old to fully understand number’ ([60], p. 186). |
24 | A point that is also argued by Wittgenstein, cf., PI 26 ff. |
25 | A kind of learning by trial and error is also described by Wittgenstein: When someone learns a new language in a strange country, he ‘will sometimes learn the language from ostensive definitions they give him; and he will often have to guess the meaning of these definitions; and will guess sometimes right, sometimes wrong’ (PI, 32). |
26 | For example: Young children without numerical language can make simple ordinal (less, more) numerical judgements for smal numbers, but their achievements improve after they have mastered verbal counting [61]. |
27 | The German term ‘Abrichtung’ is normally used for the training of animals ([29], p. 161). Wittgenstein also uses it for teaching a mathematical rule, and an expression like ‘365 × 428′ is even called an ‘order’ (RFM VI, 19–20). |
28 | The idea to first learn the principles or ‘foundations’ motivated the ‘new math’ educational reform in the 1960s, which was a failure. |
29 | Wittgenstein describes the teaching of abstract concepts like ‘regular’ or ‘same’ to someone who only speaks French: ‘...if a person has not yet got the concepts, I shall teach him to use the words by means of examples and by means of practice.—And when I do this I do not communicate less to him than I know myself’ (PI, 208). |
30 | Cf., e.g., OC 113, where Wittgenstein makes the point that commutativity of addition is typically something that in teaching basic arithmetic is treated as a rule, not as a (mathematical) fact. Facts are things you can claim to know, in which case you need to be prepared to back them up by giving grounds. In this case, e.g., by providing a proof in some axiomatisation of arithmetic. But that comes long after (if at all) learning to count, to add, and so on. Thus, the status of a + b = b + a depends on how it functions in a particular setting. And if the setting is that of teaching, it simply functions as a rule that guides behaviour. |
31 | Calculating prodigies, ‘who get the right answer but cannot say how. Are we to say that they do not calculate?’ (PI, 236). The association of knowledge and understanding with an ability extends beyond practical know-how and understanding and includes propositional knowledge. Quite generally, Wittgenstein claims, the grammar of the word ‘know’ is related to that of ‘can’ and ‘be able to’: the mastery of a technique (PI, 150). |
32 | ‘And hence also ‘obeying a rule’ is a practice. And to think one is obeying a rule is not to obey the rule. Hence it is not possible to obey a rule ‘privately’ (PI, 202). Following a rule is part of a practice, and as such it is taught and subject to social norms. This summarizes Wittgenstein’s anti-mentalism and his enactive and socially embedded view. Important to note here is that the rule-following considerations occur not only in PI, but also in RFM. |
33 | A disclaimer: we will not even try to summarize the huge literature in this field, which ranges from philosophy to psycholinguistics, social and evolutionary psychology, game theory, sociology, economics, etc. We select a couple of in our view promising approaches to naturalize conceptual levels of human mathematical cognition. |
34 | Already suggested by Charles Darwin, who proposed that the swim bladder of fishes developed into an organ of respiration in land animals. |
35 | Inspired by the work by Overmann and Malafouris. We use Zahidi’s summary. |
36 | Inspired by Haeckel’s ‘recapitulation theory’ in biology: the phylogenetic development of a species is reproduced in the embryological development of the individual. Such analogous pictures are seductive but often incorrect. Biological phylogenesis and ontogenesis differ radically in their causal mechanism: Phylogenesis is driven by the mechanism of natural selection; ontogenesis (at least prenatally) by the genetically programmed growth and differentiation of the embryo. |
37 | TLP 6.21: ‘A proposition of mathematics does not express a thought’. ‘Thought’ is used here in the Fregean sense, it does not refer to a mental entity. |
38 | In LFM he also rejects other positions which were mainstream in the 20th century philosophy of mathematics, such as Frege-Russellian logistic foundationalism (LFM 260-66), formalism (112, 142-3), intuitionism (237) and finitism (141). His views of the latter three ‘isms’ are more nuanced and complicated than we can summarise here [72]. |
39 | The superficial similarity of mathematics to games might lead to formalist conclusions, but this would be misleading and even ‘very dangerous’ (LFM, p. 142–143). |
40 | As he declares for instance in PI 144. |
41 | Wittgenstein’s picture of early language acquisition during joint activities is supported by psycho-linguistic observations: the ‘social-pragmatic account of word learning’ ([64], p. 114). |
42 | See Bartley III [74] for Wittgenstein’s short-lived career as an elementary school teacher. |
43 | In the case of functions which take real numbers as values, ‘computable’ means that the number can be approximated in a computable manner to any desired degree of accuracy. |
44 | Cantor, who took the existence of a bijection as definitional for equicardinality and then applied his diagonal argument to construct a hierarchy of infinities, wrote scathing criticisms of DuBois Reymond’s work which took part–whole relationships as the starting point of his theory of orders of infinity. |
References
- Menary, R. Introduction to the Special Issue on 4E Cognition. Phenom. Cogn. Sci. 2010, 9, 459–463. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nieder, A. The Neuronal Code for Number. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 2016, 17, 366–382. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Piazza, M. Neurocognitive Start-up Tools for Symbolic Number Representations. Trends Cogn. Sci. 2010, 14, 542–551. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Pica, P.; Lemer, C.; Izard, V.; Dehaene, S. Exact and Approximate Arithmetic in an Amazonian Indigene Group. Science 2004, 306, 499–503. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Benson-Amram, S.; Gilfillan, G.; McComb, K. Numerical Assessment in the Wild: Insights from Social Carnivores. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 2018, 373, 20160508. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Bortot, M.; Regolin, L.; Vallortigara, G. A Sense of Number in Invertebrates. Biochem. Biophys. Res. Commun. 2021, 564, 37–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Walsh, V. A Theory of Magnitude: Common Cortical Metrics of Time, Space and Quantity. Trends Cogn. Sci. 2003, 7, 483–488. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Leibovich, T.; Katzin, N.; Harel, M.; Henik, A. From “Sense of Number” to “Sense of Magnitude”: The Role of Continuous Magnitudes in Numerical Cognition. Behav. Brain Sci. 2017, 40, e164. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Clarke, S.; Beck, J. The Number Sense Represents (Rational) Numbers. Behav. Brain Sci. 2021, 44, e178. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wittgenstein, L. Philosophical Investigations; Wiley-Blackwell: Oxford, UK, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, L. Zettel; Blackwell: Oxford, UK, 1967. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, L. Über Gewißheit. On Certainty; Blackwell: Oxford, UK, 1969. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, L. Remarks on the Foundation of Mathematics, 3rd ed.; Blackwell: Oxford, UK, 1978. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, L. Wittgenstein’s Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics, Cambridge, 1939; Blackwell: Oxford, UK, 1976. [Google Scholar]
- Revkin, S.K.; Piazza, M.; Izard, V.; Cohen, L.; Dehaene, S. Does Subitizing Reflect Numerical Estimation? Psychol. Sci. 2008, 19, 607–614. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cheyette, S.J.; Piantadosi, S.T. A Unified Account of Numerosity Perception. Nat. Hum. Behav. 2020, 4, 1265–1272. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Dehaene, S.; Izard, V.; Pica, P.; Spelke, E. Core Knowledge of Geometry in an Amazonian Indigene Group. Science 2006, 311, 381–384. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Spelke, E.S.; Lee, S.A. Core Systems of Geometry in Animal Minds. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 2012, 367, 2784–2793. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Barrett, L. Back to the Rough Ground and into the Hurly-Burly: Why Cognitive Ethology Needs ‘Wittgenstein’s Razor’. In Mind, Language and Action; Moyal-Sharrock, D., Munz, V., Coliva, A., Eds.; De Gruyter: Berlin, Grermany, 2015; pp. 299–316. ISBN 978-3-11-037861-0. [Google Scholar]
- Bennett, M.R.; Hacker, P.M.S. Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience; Blackwell Pub: Malden, MA, USA, 2003; ISBN 978-1-4051-0855-3. [Google Scholar]
- Ferreirós, J.; García-Pérez, M.J. Beyond Natural Geometry: On the Nature of Proto-Geometry. Philos. Psychol. 2020, 33, 181–205. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Harnad, S. The Symbol Grounding Problem. Phys. D Nonlinear Phenom. 1990, 42, 335–346. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Dromm, K. Imaginary Naturalism: The Natural and Primitive in Wittgenstein’s Later Thought. Br. J. Hist. Philos. 2003, 11, 673–690. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Baker, L.R. Does Naturalism Rest on a Mistake? Am. Philos. Q. 2011, 48, 161–173. [Google Scholar]
- McGinn, M. Wittgenstein and Naturalism. In Naturalism and Normativity; De Caro, M., MacArthur, D., Eds.; Columbia University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2010; pp. 322–351. [Google Scholar]
- Tang, H. A Meeting of the Conceptual and the Natural: Wittgenstein on Learning a Sensation-Language. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2015, 91, 105–135. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Crary, A. Wittgenstein and Ethical Naturalism. In Wittgenstein and His Interpreters: Essays in Memory of Gordon Baker; Kahane, G., Kanterian, E., Kuusela, O., Eds.; Blackwell: Oxford, UK, 2007; pp. 295–319. [Google Scholar]
- Christensen, A.-M.S. Boundless Nature: Virtue Ethics, Wittgenstein and Unrestricted Naturalism. In Ethics in the Wake of Wittgenstein; de Mesel, B., Kuusela, O., Eds.; Routledge Studies in Ethics and Moral Theory; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2019; pp. 63–83. ISBN 978-1-138-74429-5. [Google Scholar]
- Bangu, S. Later Wittgenstein and the Genealogy of Mathematical Necessity. In Wittgenstein and Naturalism; Cahill, K., Raleigh, T., Eds.; Routledge: London, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Macarthur, D. Wittgenstein’s Liberal Naturalism of Human Nature. In Wittgenstein and Naturalism; Cahill, K., Raleigh, T., Eds.; Routledge: London, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Hutto, D.D.; Satne, G. Wittgenstein’s Inspiring View of Nature: On Connecting Philosophy and Science Aright. Philos. Investig. 2018, 41, 141–160. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Medina, J. Anthropologism, Naturalism, and the Pragmatic Study of Language. J. Pragmat. 2004, 36, 549–573. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jacquette, D. Wittgenstein’s Anthropologism in Logic, Philosophy and the Social Sciences. Soc. Epistemol. 1999, 13, 303–323. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Beale, J.; Kidd, I.J. (Eds.) Wittgenstein and Scientism; Routledge: London, UK, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Stokhof, M.; van Lambalgen, M. What Cost Naturalism? In Bridging Formal and Conceptual Semantics. Selected Papers of \sc Bridge-14; Balogh, K., Petersen, W., Eds.; University of Düsseldorf Press: Düsseldorf, Germany, 2016; pp. 89–117. [Google Scholar]
- Moyal-Sharrock, D. Wittgenstein’s Razor: The Cutting Edge of Enactivism. Am. Philos. Q. 2013, 50, 263–279. [Google Scholar]
- Moyal-Sharrock, D. From Deed to Word: Gapless and Kink-Free Enactivism. Synthese 2021, 198, 405–425. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hutto, D.D.; Satne, G. Naturalism in Goldilock’s Zone: Wittgenstein’s Delicate Balancing Act. In Wittgenstein and Naturalism; Cahill, K.M., Raleigh, T., Eds.; Routledge: London, UK, 2018; pp. 56–76. [Google Scholar]
- Medina, J. Wittgenstein’s Social Naturalism: The Idea of ‘Second Nature’ After the Philosophical Investigations. In The Third Wittgenstein: The Post-Investigations Works; Moyal-Sharrock, D., Ed.; Ashgate: Aldershot, UK, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Williams, M. Normative Naturalism. Int. J. Philos. Stud. 2010, 18, 355–375. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Menary, R. Mathematical Cognition: A Case of Enculturation; Open MIND: Frankfurt, Germany, 2015. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Moyal-Sharrock, D. (Ed.) The Third Wittgenstein: The Post-Investigations Works; Ashgate: Aldershot, UK, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Van Gennip, K. Wittgenstein’s on Certainty in the Making: Studies into Its Historical and Philosophical Background; Selbstverl: Groningen, The Netherlands, 2008; ISBN 978-90-367-3637-4. [Google Scholar]
- Van Gennip, K. Wittgenstein on Intuition, Rule-Following and Certainty: Exchanges with Brouwer and Russell. In The Oxford Handbook of Wittgenstein; Kuusela, O., McGinn, M., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2012; pp. 426–443. [Google Scholar]
- Schatzki, T.R. Social Practices. A Wittgensteinian Approach to Human Activity and the Social; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Coliva, A. Extended Rationality. A Hinge Epistemology; Palgrave/MacMillan: London, UK, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Coliva, A.; Moyal-Sharrock, D. (Eds.) Hinge Epistemology; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Mancosu, P. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2008; ISBN 978-0-19-929645-3. [Google Scholar]
- Van Kerkhove, B.; van Bendegem, J.-P. (Eds.) Perspectives on Mathematical Practices. Bringing Together Philosophy of Mathematics, Sociology of Mathematics, and Mathematics Education; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Van Kerkhove, B. (Ed.) New Perspectives on Mathematical Practices. Essays in the Philosophy and History of Mathematics; World Scientific Publishers: Singapore, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Wagner, R. Making and Breaking Mathematical Sense. Histories and Philosophies of Mathematical Practices; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NY, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Sørensen, H.K. Representations as Means and Ends: Representability and Habituation in Mathematical Analysis During the First Part of the Nineteenth Century. In New Perspectives on Mathematical Practices. Essays in Philosophy and History of Mathematics; Van Kerkhove, B., Ed.; World Scientific Publishers: Singapore, 2009; pp. 114–137. [Google Scholar]
- Avigad, J. Understanding Proofs. In The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice; Mancuso, P., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2008; pp. 317–353. [Google Scholar]
- Parker, M. Philosophical Method and Galileo’s Paradox of Infinity. In New Perspectives on Mathematical Practices. Essays in Philosophy and History of Mathematics; Van Kerkhove, B., Ed.; World Scientific Publishers: Signapore, 2009; pp. 76–113. [Google Scholar]
- Dawson, R. Wittgenstein on Pure and Applied Mathematics. Synthese 2014, 191, 4131–4148. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sacks, O. The Man Who Mistook His Wife for a Hat; Duckworth: London, UK, 1985. [Google Scholar]
- Mion, G. Wittgensteinian Wood-Sellers: A Resolute Relativistic Reading. Int. J. Philos. Stud. 2021. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gilmore, C.; Göbel, S.M.; Inglis, M. An Introduction to Mathematical Cognition; International Texts in Developmental Psychology; Routledge, Taylor and Francis Group: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2018; ISBN 978-1-317-41010-2. [Google Scholar]
- Ramscar, M.; Dye, M.; Popick, H.M.; O’Donnell-McCarthy, F. The Enigma of Number: Why Children Find the Meanings of Even Small Number Words Hard to Learn and How We Can Help Them Do Better. PLoS ONE 2011, 6, e22501. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Tomasello, M. The Cultural Origins of Human Cognition; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1999; ISBN 978-0-674-00070-4. [Google Scholar]
- Brannon, E.M.; Van de Walle, G.A. The Development of Ordinal Numerical Competence in Young Children. Cogn. Psychol. 2001, 43, 53–81. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Zorzi, M.; Testolin, A. An Emergentist Perspective on the Origin of Number Sense. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 2018, 373, 20170043. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Badcock, P.B.; Friston, K.J.; Ramstead, M.J.D.; Ploeger, A.; Hohwy, J. The Hierarchically Mechanistic Mind: An Evolutionary Systems Theory of the Human Brain, Cognition, and Behavior. Cogn. Affect. Behav. Neurosci. 2019, 19, 1319–1351. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Tomasello, M. Becoming Human: A Theory of Ontogeny; The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2021; ISBN 978-0-674-98085-3. [Google Scholar]
- Sarnecka, B.W. Learning to Represent Exact Numbers. Synthese 2021, 198, 1001–1018. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Noteboom, A.; van Os, S.; Spek, W. Concretisering Referentieniveaus Rekenen 1F/1S; SLO (Nationaal Expertisecentrum Leerplanontwikkeling): Enschede, The Netherlands, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Dehaene, S.; Cohen, L. Cultural Recycling of Cortical Maps. Neuron 2007, 56, 384–398. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Price, C.J.; Devlin, J.T. The Myth of the Visual Word Form Area. NeuroImage 2003, 19, 473–481. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zahidi, K. Radicalizing Numerical Cognition. Synthese 2021, 198, 529–545. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Moeller, K.; Martignon, L.; Wessolowski, S.; Engel, J.; Nuerk, H.-C. Effects of Finger Counting on Numerical Development? The Opposing Views of Neurocognition and Mathematics Education. Front. Psychol. 2011, 2. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Monk, R. Ludwig Wittgenstein. The Duty of Genius; Jonathan Cape: London, UK, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Marion, M. Wittgenstein, Finitism, and the Foundations of Mathematics; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Frascolla, P. Realism, Anti-Realism, Quietism: Wittgenstein’s Stance. Grazer Philos Stud. 2014, 89, 11–21. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bartley, W.W., III. Wittgenstein, Open Court Paperbacks, 2nd ed.; Open Court: La Salle, IL, USA, 1985; ISBN 978-0-87548-441-9. [Google Scholar]
Arithmetic Names of numerals; digits; decimal position system and notation; concept of zero; number sequence and number line; ordinal relations; insight in orders of magnitude up to ca. one billion; estimating; fractions, decimals, and conversion (¾ = 0.75, etc.); rounding; calculating (+ − × ÷) with small numbers; multiplication tables to 10 × 10 by heart; using an electronic calculator; order of arithmetic operations, grouping, brackets. |
Geometry Length, surface, volume (estimating, measuring, calculating); metric system; temperature; weight; time (units and intervals, clock, calendar); instrument readings; maps, scale, distance, route planning; simple 3D objects; 2D <> 3D projections; simple formulas (velocity, etc.); basic graphs and tables; symmetry; tiling. |
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Stam, J.; Stokhof, M.; Van Lambalgen, M. Naturalising Mathematics? A Wittgensteinian Perspective. Philosophies 2022, 7, 85. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7040085
Stam J, Stokhof M, Van Lambalgen M. Naturalising Mathematics? A Wittgensteinian Perspective. Philosophies. 2022; 7(4):85. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7040085
Chicago/Turabian StyleStam, Jan, Martin Stokhof, and Michiel Van Lambalgen. 2022. "Naturalising Mathematics? A Wittgensteinian Perspective" Philosophies 7, no. 4: 85. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7040085
APA StyleStam, J., Stokhof, M., & Van Lambalgen, M. (2022). Naturalising Mathematics? A Wittgensteinian Perspective. Philosophies, 7(4), 85. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7040085