A Relational Perspective on Collective Agency
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Irreducible Concepts of Collectives
2.1. Ontological Individualism
2.2. Ontological Individualism with Internalism
2.3. Ontological Individualism with Methodological Individualism
2.4. The Gordian Knot
3. Why Can’t We Speak of Collective Entities?
3.1. The Basic Argument of Physicalistic Individualism
- (P1)
- Internalism in principle: the justifications of our cognitive contents are independent of the outside world.
- (P2)
- Self-awareness: everyone is familiar with themselves and can be aware of their physical body and their cognitive contents, and understand the correlations and differences between them.
- (P3)
- Awareness of others: we can see and touch other people (in a physical sense), although we cannot see and touch cognitive contents of other people, we can be aware of such things. And we can also have the concept of similarity and difference with other humans.
- (C1)
- With (P2) and (P3) as basic intuitive facts, each individual “I” knows themselves well and is aware of others. This “I” would see others as familiar kinds of stuff and attribute similar cognitive contents to them. According to (P1), “I” do not need any external source to justify knowledge (internalism). Therefore, every individual has the concept of other people having intentionality, independent from any actual connection with such intentionality.
- (P4)
- Physicalistic function of brains: all intentionality requires a physical brain, and in the end is a physical existence.
- (C2)
- With (C1) as the basic conclusion, according to (P4), such intentionality depends only on physical brains, which can only own by individuals. In other words, intentionality only exists on the individual level (me and other persons, even intelligent animals), which is a typical individualistic claim.
3.2. Objection to Familiarity
- (P1)
- Internalism in principle: the justifications of our cognitive contents are independent of the outside world.
- (P2)
- Self-awareness: everyone is familiar with themselves and can be aware of their physical body and their cognitive contents, and understand the correlation and difference between them.
- (P3*)
- Awareness of collectives: although we cannot see collectives (physically), any person-in-society does perceive the existence of collectives, at least in the conceptual sense. Moreover, a person-in-society can be aware of a different kind of intentionality than that in a collective sense.11
- (C*)
- With (P2) and (P3*) as basic intuitive facts, each individual agent “I” knows myself well and is aware of collectives. Since the definition of an agent no longer requires physical grounds, “I” have no reason to reject the existence of collectives, at least in the conceptual sense. In this way, “I” will realize that such concepts arise from the manifestation of some counterpart of the physical world different from individuals, to which “I” would naturally attribute collective intentionality. According to (P1), justifications of my knowledge are independent of the outside. Therefore, collectives may exist and have their intentionality, and such intentionality depends on something different from individuals; in other words, intentionality can be realized at the level of a collective.
4. The Relational Account of Collective Agency
4.1. Functionalism and Interpretationism
4.2. Turn to a Unified Account
4.3. A Thorough Relational Account
- (1) A stable interrelationship between its members that constitutes a stable structure;
- (2) A stable relationship between its members’ choices and the collective action that constitutes a stable procedure.
5. Relations between Collective Agency and Individual Actions
6. Conclusions and Ideas for a Future Investigation
Author Contributions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Interpreting agency using the concept of intentionality is the mainstream tradition in philosophy of action since G. E. M. Anscombe and Donald Davidson. |
2 | The “rational” here indicates logical consistency of a collective’s decisions; that is, it is irrational for a collective agent to agree with A and B but to deny at the same time. More detail on interpretationism and functionalism can be found in Section 4. |
3 | Following Bach [8], we use the term ‘eventuality’ to refer neutrally to events and states. Note that the reference to events or states instead of facts emphasizes the importance of the temporal dimension as a constitutive element. As a set of relational eventualities, collective agents can originate, develop and vanish. In other words, collective agents are not constants but relatively stable states of relations. |
4 | |
5 | “This is a we-mode personal intention essentially of the kind ‘I, as a group member, intend to participate”’ ([18], p. 44). |
6 | For instance, the example of business school ([22], pp. 47–48). |
7 | For the purposes of this paper, we will simplify the Cartesian claim by focusing only on internalism and leave out solipsism, i.e., we will take the existence of other individuals for granted. |
8 | Broadly speaking, in contrast to physicalism and reductionism, emergentism recognizes the existence of collective agency and asserts that such an entity can not be reduced to its members and their interactions. In this sense, interpretationism and functionalism can be regarded as specific ways of explaining emergentism by relaxing several restrictions on agency from their particular perspectives. However, in detail, their concerns are different from those of emergentism; they pay more attention to the way we interpret conceptual objects rather than whether they are reducible to other entities. |
9 | Here, we merely point out that there is an intuitive difference between knowledge of oneself and knowledge of the external world and that this difference affects the application of familiarity. It is beyond the scope of this paper to discuss in what sense this distinction holds. For interested readers, see [27] for various accounts of the distinction between the two types of knowledge. |
10 | In order for internalism to not collapse into solipsism, it needs to satisfy two conditions: 1. the subject regards perceptual inputs as evidence; 2. the subject has the criteria to distinguish between knowledge of oneself and knowledge of others. Therefore, the distinction between the two types of knowledge is still meaningful in the context of internalism, which affects the application of familiarity. |
11 | Many experimental studies in cognitive science and anthropology confirm that infants about 12 to 15 months of age are capable of having collaborative engagements. They can exercise their individual intentionality and recognize the intentionality of others, and more importantly, they can realize the cooperative behavior and the role of others in collaborative engagements and can take in and complete the tasks of other roles. (See [28,29]; etc.) With the observations that gorillas cannot have collective intentionality and that autistic children cannot fully have collective intentionality, Tomasello [30] further suggests that the most important distinction between humans and other species is that we understand collective intentionality and can cooperate, rather than merely being rational and intentional. |
12 | A common example is pain. Functionalists may interpret pain as a physical injury, a belief in physical discomfort, a desire to express such discomfort, moaning, restlessness, etc. and assume that anything that satisfies these conditions is capable of being pain. However, in this account, it is not just humans or animals that have internal mental states that are capable of pain, but also those that meet these conditions, even silicon-based creatures, aliens, and other completely different types, can be capable of pain. This is the so-called multiple realization: “pain can be realized by different types of physical states in different kinds of creatures” [31]. |
13 | The “pattern” refers to the agential pattern in functionalism, which is the basic condition for behaviors of a system as an agent needs to satisfy. “There are purposes and representations that it is independently plausible to ascribe to the system... and the behavior of the system generally promotes those purposes according to those representations” [32]. |
14 | For example, there are three propositions (a), (b) and (c) with interrelations: the conjunction of (a) and (b) implies (c), namely “(a) Take preventive measures against COVID-19”, “(b) Fighting the epidemic should have the highest priority, whatever it takes”, and “(c) Accepting financial loss.” According to functionalism, a collective that manifests agency can not simultaneously adopt (a) and (b) but reject (c) because it will be logically inconsistent and indicates the collective cannot exercise its ratiocinative capacity. |
15 | Donald Davidson and Daniel Dennett are prominent in this tradition. |
16 | Although some authors advocate ontological reductionism about relations, most philosophers acknowledge relations as ontological commitments. For detail, see [34]. |
17 | One of the anonymous reviewers pointed out to us that a combination of organizational structures and functional capacity has already been made in the area of complex adaptive systems. In addition to convergence of opinions, in evolutionary economic theory emergence of generic rule structures plays an essential role. As a result, collective agents have internal processes that allow them to manifest rationality, independent of being observed as doing so. Interested readers can further check [36]. |
18 | Admittedly, our understanding of modal operators and principles depends on a previous understanding of the meta-language definitions in terms of explicit relations and relata. The point here is that even when all the relata have been abstracted, we can still directly talk about the relational properties without referring to any concrete relata. Similar things happen when we talk about the essence of a collective. |
19 | In some cases, these strategies are inconsistent, such as the prisoner’s dilemma. |
20 | Structures or functions of a collective guarantee minimum relational eventualities that constitute the relational identity of a collective. |
21 | The possibility of integrating our relationalist approach into the broader framework of critical realism, as suggested by one of the anonymous reviewers, is also a promising avenue to be explored. |
References
- Popper, K.R. The Open Society and Its Enemies, 2 Vols., Reprint; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1962. [Google Scholar]
- Rovane, C. The Bounds of Agency; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Tollefsen, D. Organizations as true believers. J. Soc. Philos. 2002, 33, 395–410. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- List, C.; Pettit, P. Group Agency: The Possibility, Design, and Status of Corporate Agents; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Baier, A.C. Doing things with others: The mental commons. In Commonality and Particularity in Ethics; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 1997; pp. 15–44. [Google Scholar]
- Meijers, A.M. Can collective intentionality be individualized? Am. J. Econ. Sociol. 2003, 62, 167–183. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schmid, H.B. Can brains in vats think as a team? Philos. Explor. 2003, 6, 201–217. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bach, E. The Algebra of Events. Linguist. Philos. 1986, 9, 5–16. [Google Scholar]
- Petersson, B. Collectivity and Circularity. J. Philos. 2007, 104, 138–156. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schweikard, D.P.; Schmid, H.B. Collective Intentionality. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Fall 2021 ed.; Zalta, E.N., Ed.; Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Sellars, W. Imperatives, Intentions, and the Logic of “Ought”; Wayne State University Press: Detroit, MI, USA, 1963. [Google Scholar]
- Tuomela, R.; Miller, K. We-intentions. Philos. Stud. 1988, 53, 367–389. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gilbert, M. A Theory of Political Obligation: Membership, Commitment, and the Bonds of Society; Oxford University Press on Demand: Detroit, MI, USA, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Gilbert, M. Sociality and Responsibility: New Essays in Plural Subject Theory; Rowman & Littlefield: Lanham, MD, USA, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Gilbert, M. Acting Together. In Social Facts and Collective Intentionality. Philosophische Forschung/Philosophical Research; Meggle, G., Ed.; Dr. Hänsel-Hohenhausen: Hesse, Germany, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Gilbert, M. On Social Facts; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Tuomela, R. The Philosophy of Sociality: The Shared Point of View; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Tuomela, R. Joint intention, we-mode and I-mode. Midwest Stud. Philos. 2006, 30, 35–58. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tuomela, R. We-intentions revisited. Philos. Stud. 2005, 125, 327–369. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tuomela, R. Social Ontology: Collective Intentionality and Group Agents; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Searle, J. Collective intentions and actions. Intentions Commun. 1990, 195, 220. [Google Scholar]
- Searle, J. Making the Social World: The Structure of Human Civilization; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Bratman, M.E. Dynamics of sociality. Midwest Stud. Philos. 2006, 30, 1–15. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bratman, M.E. Faces of Intention: Selected Essays on Intention and Agency; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Bratman, M.E. Shared Agency: A Planning Theory of Acting Together; Oup Usa: Oxford, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Humberstone, I.L. Two types of circularity. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. Q. J. 1997, 57, 249–280. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gertler, B. Self-Knowledge. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Winter 2021 ed.; Zalta, E.N., Ed.; Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Bakeman, R.; Adamson, L.B. Coordinating attention to people and objects in mother-infant and peer-infant interaction. In Child Development; Wiley: New York, NY, USA, 1984; pp. 1278–1289. [Google Scholar]
- Ross, H.S.; Lollis, S.P. Communication within infant social games. Dev. Psychol. 1987, 23, 241. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tomasello, M.; Carpenter, M.; Call, J.; Behne, T.; Moll, H. Understanding and sharing intentions: The origins of cultural cognition. Behav. Brain Sci. 2005, 28, 675–691. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Levin, J. Functionalism. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Winter 2021 ed.; Zalta, E.N., Ed.; Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Pettit, P. The reality of group agents. In Philosophy of the Social Sciences: Philosophical Theory and Scientific Practice; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2009; pp. 67–91. [Google Scholar]
- Pettit, P. Rationality, Reasoning and Group Agency. Dialectica 2007, 61, 495–519. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- MacBride, F. Relations. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Winter 2020 ed.; Zalta, E.N., Ed.; Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Schmid, H.B. Plural Action: Essays in Philosophy and Social Science; Springer Science & Business Media: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Page, S.; Miller, J.H. Complex Adaptive Systems: An Introduction to Computational Models of Social Life; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Rovane, C. Group agency and individualism. Erkenntnis 2014, 79, 1663–1684. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schmid, H.B. Plural self-awareness. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 2014, 13, 7–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wittgenstein, L. Philosophical Investigations; John Wiley & Sons: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Marx, K. Theses on Feuerbach (1845). In Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Selected Works; Wildside Press: Rockville, MD, USA, 1970. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Wang, Y.; Stokhof, M. A Relational Perspective on Collective Agency. Philosophies 2022, 7, 63. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7030063
Wang Y, Stokhof M. A Relational Perspective on Collective Agency. Philosophies. 2022; 7(3):63. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7030063
Chicago/Turabian StyleWang, Yiyan, and Martin Stokhof. 2022. "A Relational Perspective on Collective Agency" Philosophies 7, no. 3: 63. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7030063
APA StyleWang, Y., & Stokhof, M. (2022). A Relational Perspective on Collective Agency. Philosophies, 7(3), 63. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7030063