Natural Philosophy, Abstraction, and Mathematics among Materialists: Thomas Hobbes and Margaret Cavendish on Light
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Hobbes, Perception, and the Lux/Lumen Distinction
2.1. Hobbesian Sensation and Visual Perception
2.2. Hobbes on Lux and Lumen
3. Cavendish on Perception and Light and Her Criticisms of Hobbes
3.1. Cavendish on Visual Perception and Light
3.2. Criticisms of Hobbes on Light in Letters
But there is some difference between those figures that perceive light, and those that are light themselves; for when we sleep, there is made the figure of light, but not from a copy; but when the eye seeth light, that figure is made from a copy of the real figure of the sun; but those lights which are inherent, as in Glow-worms-tails, are original lights, in which there is as much difference as between a Man and his Picture [3] (p. 64).
Motion hath not Spare time as to Move or to Work so Curiously, as to Shape and Form every Particular Part of every Particular Creature so Exactly, as to Form them Mathematically or Geometrically, so as when any Creature is so Exact, as no Fault can be found, it seems rather a Work by Chance, than any Design in Motion to Work so Exactly [4] (p. 248).
4. Materialist Natural Philosophy: Mathematics and Abstraction
[…] since one cannot proceed in reasoning about natural things that are brought about by motion from the effects to the causes without a knowledge of those things that follow from that kind of motion; and since one cannot proceed to the consequences of motions without a knowledge of quantity, which is geometry; nothing can be demonstrated by physics without something also being demonstrated a priori. Therefore physics (I mean true physics) [vera physica], that depends on geometry, is usually numbered among the mixed mathematics [mathematicas mixtas]. […] Therefore those mathematics are pure which (like geometry and arithmetic) revolve around quantities in the abstract [in abstracto] so that work [in them] requires no knowledge of the subject; those mathematics are mixed, in truth, which in their reasoning some quality of the subject is also considered, as is the case with astronomy, music, physics, and the parts of physics that can vary on account of the variety of species and the parts of the universe [49] (p. 42) [1] (II.93).
5. Concluding Thoughts: Cavendish’s Criticisms and Materialist Explanations
Funding
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Sometimes Hobbes is inconsistent in his use of the Latin terminology related to light. For example, he describes the object of sense using lux in De corpore XXV.3. This is unsurprising since elsewhere he sometimes inconsistently uses Latin words that are fundamental to his philosophy. For example, he clearly distinguishes scientia from cognitio when needing to emphasize their differences [1] (I.58–59); however, other times he uses scientia for the more general form of ‘science’, for example, as the 1668 translation of ‘science’ from the 1651 edition of Leviathan [2] (pp. 72–73). |
2 | Hobbes’s early optics is represented in A Minute or First Draught of the Optiques (1983/1646) [5]. Shapiro [6] traces the influence of the Hobbesian account of refraction and theory of light. Malet [7] (pp. 315–317) discusses Hobbes’s criticisms of Claude Mydorge and Walter Warner. See also Prins [8] regarding accusations by Seth Ward that Hobbes plagiarized others’ work in optics. |
3 | This account relies upon the Leviathan rendition, but in De corpore XXIX and Elements of Law I.VII.1 Hobbes offers slightly different accounts of the roles played by heart and brain [10] (p. 8). |
4 | For discussion of Cavendish’s criticisms of the Hobbesian notion of ‘rest’ and her view that matter is always in motion, see Adams [11]. |
5 | See Jesseph [12] for discussion of these principles. |
6 | Stroud suggests that Hobbes’s view changed because of his later reticence to countenance vaccua in nature, see [5] (p. 30). |
7 | Hobbes mentions a final supposition at the end of De corpore XXVII.1: “…I suppose, that the parts of the pure aether, as if it were the first matter, have no motion at all but what they receive from bodies which float in them, and are not themselves fluid” [14] (I.448). However, this is not so much a supposition related specifically to these intersidereal bodies but is rather a consequence of one of the a priori principles that Hobbes holds regarding motion (cf. fn. 5 above). Insofar as they are bodies, the parts of the “pure aether” are not unique and, as such, Hobbes holds that they behave in accordance with those principles. Relevant to the issue at hand is the following principle from De corpore VIII.19: “whatever is at rest, is understood to always be at rest, unless there be some other body besides it, by which it is supposed, it may no longer remain at rest” [1] (I.102). The English translation, repeated in the Molesworth edition, adds that a body causes a resting body to move “by endeavouring to get into its place by motion” [14] (I.115), but this addition imports a conception of force not allowed by Hobbes’s definition of motion, see [12,16] (pp. 84–85). That translation does not add ‘endeavor’ to the recurrence of this principle later in De corpore XV.1 [14] (I.205). |
8 | |
9 | |
10 | Some scholarship on Cavendish’s works has argued that in her epistemology she aimed to offer ways for women to enter into natural philosophy. For example, Megan Poole [23] has recently argued that Cavendish’s epistemology aimed to expand women’s agency in this way. Lisa Sarasohn offers a similar view of Cavendish’s natural-philosophical project, arguing that “[b]y emphasizing the rationality that characterizes stones, beasts, and women, Cavendish’s universe became both animate and free, and the existence of a female natural philosopher possible” [24] (p. 54). In this same vein, Karen Detlefsen has argued that Cavendish’s “position on laws of nature and natural order presages [the] contemporary feminist account” in philosophy of science by Evelyn Fox Keller [25] (p. 73). Against such views, Boyle [26] has cogently argued that Cavendish’s natural philosophy does not show proto-feminist leanings. Although I find Boyle’s conclusion persuasive, further discussion of whether Cavendish’s epistemology, and, indeed, her overall natural-philosophical project, had feminist motivations is beyond the scope of this article, so I leave these issues to the side and assume that Cavendish did not operate with such aims in mind. As a result, when I advocate below for what I call an epistemic interpretation of Cavendish’s criticisms of Hobbes, I assume without further consideration that in the 1664 Letters Cavendish did not seek to advance a proto-feminist epistemology against Hobbes’s mechanical philosophy. I thank an anonymous referee for emphasizing these aspects of Cavendish’s view. |
11 | Lisa Walters has suggested that “Cavendish’s interest in removing force and pressure from optical theories may also have been prompted by the early modern trend for figuring the relation between nature and science as one of mastery and force,” and Walters connects this claim to Evelyn Fox Keller’s framework in which “the relationship between the powerful force of the male scientist’s mind and the resistant but ultimately submissive body of female nature” is a point of focus [28] (pp. 380–381). Discussing such aspects of Cavendish’s view are beyond the bounds of this paper, but it should suffice to say that whether or not the gendered representation of natural philosophy/nature is behind Cavendish’s critique of the perception-as-pressure account from Hobbes, Cavendish’s primary criticism is that the Hobbesian explanation simply fails to save the phenomena and that, were it correct, vision would be disorderly and the sense organs would be annoyed and damaged by the continuous application of pressure upon them. See Adams [29] for discussion of this latter point in the criticisms Cavendish makes in Letters of Hobbesian optics. |
12 | |
13 | I assume that Cavendish would agree with Hobbes that ideas, or conceptions, are images. For discussion of this aspect of her view, see Cunning [32] (pp. 21–27); also, see Cavendish’s description of ideas in Observations as “the picture of some object” [27] (p. 88), which Duncan [39] (p. 406) suggests offers a Hobbesian argument. |
14 | That she does not use this terminology is unsurprising since Cavendish was not skilled in Latin. She notes in the preface to Letters that she consulted works in her native language for the figures she criticizes, except for Descartes, whose work she had someone translate (sig. B1v) [3]. |
15 | A worry for Cavendish’s account is that in human perception it would seem that the perceiver would become the same kind of thing as the thing perceived. This worry arises since she holds that human perception is patterning and since she claims that what makes one bit of matter different from another is its unique motions. Thus, in patterning the motions of a Golden Retriever as I perceive it, it would seem that I become a Golden Retriever. Cavendish registers this worry later in Observations (phrased as “…you will say, If the eye did patter out the figure of light, it would become light itself…”) [27] (p. 186) and answers it by appeal to her view that perceiving occurs by making a copy of that which is perceived. The eye patterns light but it does so only by copying its “exterior figure”; the interior motions responsible for an object’s nature are not perceived and thus not patterned. The perceiver fails to become the perceived because it perceives only its exterior motions by making a copy of them. For discussion of this issue, see Lascano [41] (p. 417). |
16 | Chamberlain [42] (p. 327, fn. 67) discusses this claim about “one thing” and notes some of the difficulties in understanding what Cavendish could mean if her proposal is to be understood metaphysically. |
17 | This appears aimed at Hobbes’s claim that nature is the art God used: “Nature (the Art whereby God hath made and governes the World) is by the Art of man, as in many other things, so in this also imitated, that it can make an Artificial Animal” [2] (p. 16) [9] (p. 1). On Hobbes’s view Divine art produced the natural world and human art produces artificial entities, such as geometrical figures and commonwealths. |
18 | For discussion of this aspect Cavendish’s thought in her broader works, see Peterman [43] (pp. 3537–3543). |
19 | |
20 | Cavendish embraces a similar fallibilistic account of human knowledge. For discussion, see Cunning [32] (Chapter 1). |
21 | |
22 | Jesseph [12] (p. 139) makes a similar point regarding applying principles from first philosophy to natural philosophy. |
23 | |
24 | The text reads ‘obstruct’ here, but given the context it seems likely that Cavendish intends ‘abstract’ instead. |
25 | Boyle [26] (pp. 204–205) argues that Cavendish endorses moderate skepticism in the 1663 edition of Opinions, which she argues is somewhat mitigated in Letters. |
References
- Hobbes, T. Thomæ Hobbes Malmesburiensis Opera Philosophica; Molesworth, G., Ed.; John Bohn: London, UK, 1839–1845; volume 5 volumes. Citations in text are to volume and page number. [Google Scholar]
- Hobbes, T. Leviathan; Noel, M., Ed.; Claredon Press: Oxford, UK, 2012; 3 volumes. [Google Scholar]
- Cavendish, M. Philosophical Letters; London, UK, 1664. [Google Scholar]
- Cavendish, M. Philosophical and Physical Opinions, 2nd ed.; William Wilson: London, UK, 1663. [Google Scholar]
- Hobbes, T. Thomas Hobbes’s A Minute or First Draught of the Optiques: A Critical Edition. Ph.D. Thesis, University of Wisconsin-Madison, Madison, WI, USA, 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Shapiro, A.E. Kinematic optics: A study of the wave theory of light in the seventeenth century. Arch. Hist. Exact Sci. 1973, 11, 134–266. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Malet, A. The Power of Images: Mathematics and Metaphysics in Hobbes’s Optics. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 2001, 32, 303–333. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Prins, J. Ward’s polemic with Hobbes on the sources of his optical theories. Rev. D’histoire Des Sci. 1993, 46, 195–224. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hobbes, T. Leviathan; Andrew Crooke: London, UK, 1651. [Google Scholar]
- Adams, M.P. The Wax and the Mechanical Mind: Reexamining Hobbes’s Objections to Descartes’sMeditations. Br. J. Hist. Philos. 2014, 22, 403–424. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Adams, M.P. Motion as an Accident of Matter: Margaret Cavendish and Thomas Hobbes on Motion and Rest. South. J. Philos. 2021, 59, 495–522. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jesseph, D. Hobbesian Mechanics. In Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy III; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 2006; pp. 119–152. [Google Scholar]
- Heinrichs, T.A. Language and Mind in Hobbes. Yale Fr. Stud. 1973, 49, 56. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hobbes, T. The English Works of Thomas Hobbes; Molesworth, W., Ed.; John Bohn: London, UK, 1839–1845; 11 volumes. Citations in text are to volume and page number. [Google Scholar]
- Hobbes, T. The Elements of Law; Ferdinand, T., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1928. [Google Scholar]
- Jesseph, D. Hobbes on ‘Conatus’: A Study in the Foundations of Hobbesian Philosophy. Hobbes Stud. 2016, 29, 66–85. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lindberg, D.C. The Science of Optics. In Science in the Middle Ages; Lindberg, D.C., Ed.; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1978; pp. 338–368. [Google Scholar]
- Smith, A.M. Descartes’s Theory of Light and Refraction: A Discourse on Method. Trans. Am. Philos. Soc. 1987, 77, 1–92. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brandt, F. Thomas Hobbes’ Mechanical Conception of Nature; Levin & Munksgaard: Copenhagen, Denmark, 1927. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, J. Hobbes, Galileo, and the Physics of Simple Circular Motions. Hobbes Stud. 2016, 29, 9–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mintz, S.I. Galileo, Hobbes, and the Circle of Perfection. Isis 1952, 43, 98–100. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Baldin, G. Hobbes and Galileo: Method, Matter and the Science of Motion; Springer: Dordrech, The Netherlands, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Poole, M. A Woman’s Optics: Margaret Cavendish, Sensory Mimesis, and Early Modern Rhetorics of Science. J. Hist. Rhetor. 2021, 24, 195–222. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sarasohn, L. Leviathan and the Lady: Cavendish’s Critique of Hobbes in the Philosophical Letters. In Authorial Conquests: Essays on Genre in the Writings of Margaret Cavendish; Cottegnies, L., Weitz, N., Eds.; Associated University Presses: London, UK, 2003; pp. 40–58. [Google Scholar]
- Detlefsen, K. Margaret Cavendish on Laws and Order. In Early Modern Women on Metaphysics; Thomas, E., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2018; pp. 72–91. [Google Scholar]
- Boyle, D. Margaret Cavendish’s Nonfeminist Natural Philosophy. Configurations 2004, 12, 195–227. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cavendish, M. Observations upon Experimental Philosophy; Eileen, O’Neill, Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Walters, L. Optics and Authorship in Margaret Cavendish’s Observations and The Blazing World. Viator 2014, 45, 377–393. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Adams, M.P. Visual Perception as Patterning: Cavendish against Hobbes on Sensation. Hist. Philos. Q. 2016, 33, 193–214. [Google Scholar]
- Boyle, D. Margaret Cavendish on Perception, Self-Knowledge, and Probable Opinion. Philos. Compass 2015, 10, 438–450. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Boyle, D. The Well-Ordered Universe: The Philosophy of Margaret Cavendish; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Cunning, D. Cavendish; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Detlefsen, K. Reason and Freedom Margaret Cavendish on the Order and Disorder of Nature. Archiv für Geschichte der Philos. 2007, 89, 157–191. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- James, S. The philosophical innovations of Margaret Cavendish. Br. J. Hist. Philos. 1999, 7, 219–244. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Michaelian, K. Margaret Cavendish’s Epistemology. Br. J. Hist. Philos. 2009, 17, 31–53. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Richter, V. Exterior Inspection and Regular Reason: Robert Hooke’s and Margaret Cavendish’s Epistemologies of the Senses. In The Five Senses in Medieval and Early Modern England; Kern-Stähler, A., Busse, B., de Boer, W., Eds.; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 2016; pp. 96–116. [Google Scholar]
- Wilkins, E. Margaret Cavendish and the Royal Society. Notes Rec. R. Soc. J. Hist. Sci. 2014, 68, 245–260. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cavendish, M. Ground of Natural Philosophy Divided into Thirteen Parts; A. Maxwell: London, UK, 1668. [Google Scholar]
- Duncan, S. Debating Materialism: Cavendish, Hobbes, and More. Hist. Philos. Q. 2012, 29, 391–409. [Google Scholar]
- Cavendish, M. Philosophical and Physical Opinions, 1st ed.; Marchioness of Newcaste: London, UK, 1655; Printed for F. Martin and F. Allestrye at the Bell in St. Paul’s Church-Yard. [Google Scholar]
- Lascano, M. Cavendish and Hobbes on Causation. In A Companion to Hobbes; Adams, M.P., Ed.; Wiley-Blackwell: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 2021; pp. 413–430. [Google Scholar]
- Chamberlain, C. Color in a Material World: Margaret Cavendish against the Early Modern Mechanists. Philos. Rev. 2019, 128, 293–336. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Peterman, A. Empress vs. Spider-Man: Margaret Cavendish on pure and applied mathematics. Synthese 2019, 196, 3527–3549. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Boyle, D. Informed by ‘Sense and Reason’: Margaret Cavendish’s Theorizing about Perception. In the Senses and the History of Philosophy; Glenney, B., Silva, J.F., Eds.; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2019; pp. 231–248. [Google Scholar]
- Hobbes, T. Critique du De Mundo de Thomas White; Jacquot, J., Jones, H.W., Eds.; Vrin: Paris, France, 1973. [Google Scholar]
- Hobbes, T. Thomas White’s De Mundo Examined; Jones, H.W., Translator; Bradford University Press: London, UK, 1976. [Google Scholar]
- Hobbes, T. Computatio Sive Logica: Logic; Hungerland, I.C., Vick, G.R., Eds.; Martinich, A.P., Translator and, commentary; Abaris Books: New York, NY, USA, 1981. [Google Scholar]
- Deigh, J. Reason and Ethics in Hobbes’s Leviathan. J. Hist. Philos. 1996, 34, 33–60. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hobbes, T. Man and Citizen; Bernard, G., Ed.; Hackett Publishing: Indianapolis, IN, USA, 1994. [Google Scholar]
- Adams, M.P. Hobbes on Natural Philosophy as ‘True Physics’ and Mixed Mathematics. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 2016, 56, 43–51. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Adams, M.P. Natural Philosophy, Deduction, and Geometry in the Hobbes-Boyle Debate. Hobbes Stud. 2017, 30, 83–107. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cavendish, M. The Worlds Olio Written by the Right Honorable, the Lady Margaret Newcastle; London, UK, 1655. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Adams, M.P. Natural Philosophy, Abstraction, and Mathematics among Materialists: Thomas Hobbes and Margaret Cavendish on Light. Philosophies 2022, 7, 44. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7020044
Adams MP. Natural Philosophy, Abstraction, and Mathematics among Materialists: Thomas Hobbes and Margaret Cavendish on Light. Philosophies. 2022; 7(2):44. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7020044
Chicago/Turabian StyleAdams, Marcus P. 2022. "Natural Philosophy, Abstraction, and Mathematics among Materialists: Thomas Hobbes and Margaret Cavendish on Light" Philosophies 7, no. 2: 44. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7020044
APA StyleAdams, M. P. (2022). Natural Philosophy, Abstraction, and Mathematics among Materialists: Thomas Hobbes and Margaret Cavendish on Light. Philosophies, 7(2), 44. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7020044