The Geometry of Thought: Circling Through Concepts
Abstract
:1. Introduction
- (1)
- Mathematical work consists of deductions carried out within a specific, predefined formal system.
So we are confronted with a strange situation. We set out to find a formal system for mathematics and instead of that found an infinity of systems, and whichever system you choose out of this infinity, there is one more comprehensive, i.e., one whose axioms are stronger. ([5], p. 47)
- (2)
- Mathematical work consists of discovering the mathematical world and refining the view of the objects within it.
Remark Mathematics: Important activities of the mathematician:
- 1.
Generalizing (theorem) = consider what is essential in a proof.- 2.
Rendering precisely (an intuitive proof).- 3.
Continuizing = assign continuous values to originally discrete variables.- 3.1
Generalizing (concepts) = defining concepts in a broader area.- 4.
Approximate concepts (by simpler ones) and theorems by weaker ones.- 5.
Extensionalizing: transition from the intensional to the extensional, omitting certain peculiarities (examples: constructible set, axiom of replacement, Frege’s formalization of propositional calculus).- 6.
Calcularizing = seeking out operations that can be used to “calculate”; that is, that satisfy certain commutativities.- 4.1
Specializing (first give the proof of a general theorem for a special case). Very often, this special case is found through intuition; then prove abstractly and then render precisely. 1. For the general case; cf. below.- 7.
Elegantizing (of proofs and definitions) = simplify; cf. 1.- 8.
Finding out the “meaning” of a proposition (in order to find the proof).- 9.
Constructivizing (of non-constructive proofs), that is, descending to lower types. ([12], pp. 230–231)
2. Concept–Structure–Object
2.1. Concepts in Philosophy
2.1.1. Plato
2.1.2. Leibniz
Although, therefore, the idea of a circle is not similar to the circle, truths can be derived from it which would be confirmed beyond doubt by investigating a real circle. ([17], p. 208)
Here is a circle: if you know that all the lines from the center to the circumference are equal, in my opinion, you consider its essence sufficiently clearly. Still, you have not comprehended in virtue of that innumerable theorems. (as cited in [19], p. 432)
We do not have any idea of a circle, such as there is in God, who thinks all things at the same time … We think about a circle, we provide demonstrations about a circle, we recognize a circle: its essence is known to us—but only part by part. If we were to think of the whole essence of a circle at the same time, then we would have the idea of a circle. (as cited in [19], p. 432)
Remark Philosophy: How is it possible to have clear (although not distinct) concepts without knowing their definition, if the definition constitutes the essence of the concept? It seems to follow from this that the concept is an entity that exists independently of the definition, which merely describes it (through its relations to other concepts). ([20], pp. 4–5)1
2.1.3. Frege
The neglect of the conceptual content of sentences (i.e., the ’sense’ according to Frege) also is responsible for the wrong view that the conclusion in logical inference, objectively contains no information beyond that contained in the premises. ([22], p. 350)
2.2. Our Notion of Concept
The axioms correspond to the concepts, and the models which satisfy them correspond to the objects. The representations give the relation between concepts and objects. ([28], p. 141)
However, as to the justification of the axioms attempted here, Gödel feels that it is rather unsatisfactory and that something better could be achieved by a proper analysis of the notion of structural property of the concept of set, which would then lead to the reflection principles in the form ’any structural property of the concept of set is reflected by some set’. ([29], p. 189)
In order to arrive at a structured perception, it is necessary to relate the currently given “sense object” [which changes from one moment to the next] to some concepts [the totality of all possible concepts, ordered by affinity, forms the space of understanding (or space of concepts)]. The objects of the space do not change, only the attention directed at them changes. It is apparently not possible to direct attention on some object of the space3 without at the same time directing it at an object of the sensory space “on which” or “through which” the respective concept is perceived (in the case of abstract concepts this is the word?)
An example for the most primitive sensory concepts are colours (primary colours). Or better, it is any state of affairs that involves the respective concept. It is a perception in the case of sensuous concepts, which means that we understand what it means that they “apply” to something [i.e., when a state of affairs involving them is true], though we do not see the concepts themselves. In this sense, every concept is perceived via the concept of “truth”. ([30], p. 211)
Remark: This identification of the low by means of something higher (which is the essence of knowledge) takes place in many stages:
Individual objects are known by means of empirical concepts. The empirical concepts are known by means of formal concepts (in physics). The formal concepts are known by means of higher formal concepts. For example, if one had the right definition of the natural numbers in terms of higher concepts, one would probably overlook number-theoretical regularity, just as one overlooks the optical laws by means of the proper definition of color as wavelength (and undulatory theory).4 This correct definition of number may be analytical (via analytical functions). ([12], p. 248)
Remark Philosophy: Knowledge always consists in a connection between concepts, but the reason why this connection occurs (why the judgment is made or the knowledge is reached) does not always lie in the concepts alone, but often in something non-conceptual (in a having) [even in purely conceptual knowledge, such an externally forced evidence would be conceivable]. ([20], p. 47)5
Remark Gr: The fact that the understanding of concepts becomes significantly clearer by the construction of their sensory images [i.e., words] seems absurd at first [could the perception of some landscape become clearer by sketching a picture of it?]. But the reason might be that the material (i.e., the finite combinatorics) already contains, in some way, the image of the conceptual so that only this can really be depicted (or depicted simply). This would mean: the truth is what has the simplest and the most beautiful symbolic expression. (This means: the finite combinatorics already contains a ‘picture of God’). ([33], p. 18)6
3. Two Ways of Navigating the Web of Concepts
3.1. Example: Product
3.2. Example: Erlangen Program
3.3. Example: Circle
3.4. Example: Configuration
4. Conclusions
Author Contributions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
Abbreviations
CH | Continuum Hypothesis |
ZFC | Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the Axiom of Choice |
1 | Bem⟨erkung⟩ (Phil⟨osophie⟩) Wie ist es möglich, dass man klare (wenn auch nicht deutliche) Begriffe hat, ohne ihre Def(inition) zu kennen, wenn doch die Def(inition) das Wesen des Begriffes ausmacht? Daraus scheint zu folgen, dass der Begriff ein von der Def(inition) unabhängig existierendes Wesen ist, das in der Def(inition) bloss (vermöge seiner Beziehungen zu anderen Begriffen) beschrieben wird. |
2 | Bem⟨erkung⟩ (Philol⟨ogie⟩) Bei jedem Wort muss man unterscheiden zwischen dem, was es bezeichnet (z. B. der einzelne Mensch) und das, “vermöge dessen” es bezeichnet (der Begriff Mensch). |
3 | The space of concepts decomposes into the two separate regions of sensuous and abstract concepts. |
4 | Or do we not have this idea at all? |
5 | Bem⟨erkung⟩ (Phil⟨osophie⟩) … Die Erkenntnis besteht dann immer in einer Verknüpfung zwischen Begriffen, aber der Grund dafür, dass diese Verknüpfung eintritt (dass das Urteil gefällt oder die Erkenntnis gehabt wird), liegt nicht immer in den Begriffen allein, sondern oft in etwas Nicht-Begrifflichem (in einem Haben) [sogar bei reinen Begriffserkenntnissen wäre eine solche äussere erzwungene Evidenz denkbar]. |
6 | Bem(erkung) (Gr) Die Tatsache, dass man die Wahrnehmung der Begriffe dadurch bedeutend klarer macht, dass man sich sinnliche Bilder von ihnen macht [nämlich die Worte], scheint zunächst absurd zu sein [könnte man eine Landschaft dadurch deutlicher wahrnehmen, dass man ein Gemälde von ihr entwirft?]. Aber vielleicht liegt die Ursache darin, dass auch schon das Material (nämlich die endliche Kombinatorik) schon irgendwie ein Bild des Begrifflichen in sich hat, sodass man nur das tatsächlich abbilden (oder leicht abbilden) kann. Das heisst: Die Wahrheit ist das, was den einfachsten und schönsten symbolischen Ausdruck hat. (Das heisst: Schon die endliche Kombinatorik enthält ein “Bild Gottes"). |
References
- Carter, J. Introducing the Philosophy of Mathematical Practice; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2024. [Google Scholar]
- Mancosu, P. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Gödel, K. Russell’s Mathematical Logic. In The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell; Schilpp, P.A., Ed.; Northwestern University Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1944; pp. 123–154. [Google Scholar]
- Gödel, K. Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme I. Monatshefte für Mathematik 1931, 38, 173–198. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gödel, K. The Present Situation in the Foundations of Mathematics. In Collected Works. III: Unpublished Essays and Lectures; Feferman, S., Dawson, J.W., Jr., Goldfarb, W., Parsons, C., Solovay, R.M., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1995; pp. 36–53. [Google Scholar]
- Lakatos, I. Proofs and Refutations: The Logic of Mathematical Discovery; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1976. [Google Scholar]
- Curry, H. Outline of a Formalist Philosophy of Mathematics; North Holland: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 1951. [Google Scholar]
- Hilbert, D. Grundlagen der Geometrie, 2nd ed.; Teubner Verlag: Leipzig, Germany, 1903. [Google Scholar]
- Hilbert, D. Mathematical Problems. Bull. Am. Math. Soc. 1902, 8, 437–479. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Carter, J. Philosophy of Mathematical Practice—Motivations, Themes and Prospects. Philos. Math. 2019, 27, 1–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sriraman, B. (Ed.) Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Mathematical Practice; Springer-Verlag: New York, NY, USA, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Gödel, K. Philosophical Notebooks, Volume 3, Maxims III; Engelen, E.-M., Ed.; De Gruyter: Berlin, Germany, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Fodor, J. The Language of Thought, 1st ed.; Thomas Y. Crowell: New York, NY, USA, 1975. [Google Scholar]
- Brandom, R.B. Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Gödel, K. What is Cantor’s Continuum Problem? Am. Math. Mon. 1947, 54, 515–525. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Crocco, G. Gödel on Concepts. Hist. Philos. Log. 2006, 27, 171–191. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Leibniz, G.W. Philosophical Papers and Letters: A Selection; Kluwer Academic Publisher: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Leibniz, G.W. Meditations on Knowledge, Truth and Ideas. In Leibniz:Philosophical Essays; Ariew, R., Garber, D., Eds.; Hackett Publishing Company: Indianapolis, Indiana, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Mercer, C. Leibniz’s Metaphysics: It’s Origins and Development; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Gödel, K. Maxims and Philosophical Remarks: Volume XII. Crocco, G., van Atten, M., Cantu, P., Rollinger, R., Eds.; 2021; Available online: https://hal.science/hal-03142656v1 (accessed on 14 January 2025).
- Frege, G. On Concept and Object. Mind 1951, 60, 168–180. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gödel, K. Is Mathematics a Syntax of Language. In Collected Works. III: Unpublished Essays and Lectures; Feferman, S., Dawson, J.W., Jr., Goldfarb, W., Parsons, C., Solovay, R.M., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1995; pp. 334–356. [Google Scholar]
- Reck, E.H.; Price, P. Structures And Structuralism In Contemporary Philosophy Of Mathematics. Synthese 2000, 125, 341–383. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hallman, G.; Shapiro, S. Mathematical Structuralism; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Linnebo, Ø. Philosophy of Mathematics; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Feferman, S. Logic, Mathematics, and Conceptual Structuralism. In The Metaphysics of Logic; Rush, P., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2014; pp. 72–92. [Google Scholar]
- Awodey, S. Structure in Mathematics and Logic: A Categorical Perspective. Philos. Math. 1996, 4, 209–237. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wang, H. A Logical Journey: From Gödel to Philosophy; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Reinhardt, W. Remarks on reflection principles, large cardinals, and elementary embeddings. In Axiomatic Set Theory: Part II; Jech, T.J., Ed.; American Mathematical Society: Providence, RI, USA, 1974; pp. 189–205. [Google Scholar]
- Gödel, K. Philosophical Notebooks, Volume 1, Philosophy I Maxims 0; Engelen, E.-M., Ed.; De Gruyter: Berlin, Germany, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Došen, K. Models of Deduction. Synthese 2006, 148, 639–657. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- MacLane, S. Categories for the Working Mathematician, 2nd ed.; Springer-Verlag: New York, NY, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Gödel, K. Maxims and Philosophical Remarks: Volume X. Crocco, G., van Atten, M., Cantu, P., Engelen, E.-M., Eds.; 2017; Available online: https://hal.science/hal-01459188v1 (accessed on 14 January 2025).
- Došen, K. Algebras of Deduction in Category Theory. In Third Mathematical Conference of the Republic of Srpska, Proceedings; Pikula, M., Ed.; Univerzitet u Istočnom Sarajevu, Fakultet za proizvodnju i menadžment: Trebinje, Bosnia and Herzegovina, 2014; pp. 11–18. [Google Scholar]
- Klein, C.F. Vergleichende Betrachtungen über neuere geometrische Forschungen, Programm zum Eintritt in die philosophische Facultät und den Senat der Universität zu Erlangen. In Gesammelte Mathematische Abhandlungen I; (no. XXVII); Deichert: Erlangen, Germany, 1872; pp. 460–497. [Google Scholar]
- Kostić, J.; Vujošević, S. Kurt Gödel and the Logic of Concepts. Publ. L’Institut Math. 2024, 115, 1–19. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Adžić, M.; Jevtić, F.; Kostić, J. The Geometry of Thought: Circling Through Concepts. Philosophies 2025, 10, 49. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10030049
Adžić M, Jevtić F, Kostić J. The Geometry of Thought: Circling Through Concepts. Philosophies. 2025; 10(3):49. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10030049
Chicago/Turabian StyleAdžić, Miloš, Filip Jevtić, and Jovana Kostić. 2025. "The Geometry of Thought: Circling Through Concepts" Philosophies 10, no. 3: 49. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10030049
APA StyleAdžić, M., Jevtić, F., & Kostić, J. (2025). The Geometry of Thought: Circling Through Concepts. Philosophies, 10(3), 49. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10030049