A Genetic Interpretation of the Preface of The Genealogy of Morals
Abstract
:1. Introduction: Overview of Scholarship
“For all the value that may be attributed to the true, the truthful, the selfless, it would be possible that a higher and more fundamental value for all life would have to be ascribed to appearance, the will to deceive[…].”(Nietzsche 1966, BGE 2)
2. Overview of Scholarship
It is notable that the scholars here listed say little or nothing about Nietzsche’s discussions of truth in GM III, especially GM III 25–28. The very first line of GM reads, “We are unknown to ourselves, we men of knowledge—and with good reason” (GM pref. 1). This should indicate to diligent scholars that this text has something to do with epistemology and a genealogy of knowledge itself.In Essay III, [Nietzsche] reveals morality to be dependent on the ascetic ideal, which honors the life of self-deprivation as the highest standard of human flourishing. Finally, at the close of GM, he exposes the will to nothingness that morality both presupposes and expresses.
This approach, which suggests that morality is the central, but not the only topic, can also be found in the work of Lawrence Hatab, who writes,The nominal subject of Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morals is the investigation of the origins of our moral values. While the book tenaciously pursues the topic of its title without disintegrating into a loosely related collection of aphorisms (as some of Nietzsche’s other books tend to do), it nevertheless deals with more than morality, and more than genealogy.
All of these approaches take one thing unquestioningly, that the central topic or goal of GM is to address morality. However, as I will argue later, this is a distortion of Nietzsche’s central purpose. As I argue, the aim of the text is to understand all fundamental problems, including those of knowledge and truth, as a kind of moral prejudice informed by the ascetic ideal.[The Genealogy] aims to diagnose esteemed moral traditions as forms of life-denial, in that what is valued as ‘good’ in these systems stands opposed to the actual conditions of natural life. […] Of course, questions of ethics and politics are at the core of the Genealogy, but it should be recognized that its critique of ‘morality’ is also a gateway to larger questions of knowledge, truth, and meaning.
For Foucault, GM demonstrates that truths are historical and forged as weapons functioning to particular ends of power. Many of Foucault’s works during his genealogical period can be seen as applied case studies using Nietzsche’s method.The historical analysis of this rancorous will to knowledge reveals that all knowledge rests upon injustice (that there is no right, not even in the act of knowing, to truth or a foundation to truth) and that the instinct for knowledge is malicious (something murderous, opposed to the happiness of all mankind).
Derrida’s point is that after Nietzsche has questioned and demolished metaphysics, he seeks to found an anti-metaphysics; however, the attempt to overcome, transgress, or step beyond metaphysics always requires borrowing from metaphysics itself. As the saying goes, the gravediggers of metaphysics always end up burying themselves too.Nietzsche has written what he has written. He has written that writing-and first of all his own-is not originarily subordinate to the logos and to truth. And that this subordination has come into being during an epoch whose meaning we must deconstruct. Now in this direction (but only in this direction, for read otherwise, the Nietzschean demolition remains dogmatic and, like all reversals, a captive of that metaphysical edifice which it professes to overthrow. On that point and in that order of reading, the conclusions of Heidegger and Fink are irrefutable) […]
This different will, he suggests, must be a kind of thinking that “ceases to be a ratio.” (Deleuze 1983, p. 101). Deleuze’s solution is to replace the ascetic ideal and the will to truth with the artist and an aesthetics of creation. His evidence comes from Nietzsche’s claim that, “Art […] is much more fundamentally opposed to the ascetic ideal than is science” (GM III 25). Deleuze writes,But we do not replace the ascetic ideal, we let nothing of the place itself remain, we want to destroy the place, we want another ideal in another place, another way of knowing, another concept of truth, that is to say a truth which is not presupposed in a will to truth but which presupposes a completely different will.
For Deleuze, it is art and a will to deception that replaces the ascetic ideal. This creates a fundamentally new context where what is true is no longer God or the thing-in-itself, but the artistic celebration of appearance and life.Art is the highest power of falsehood, it magnifies the ‘world as error’, it sanctifies the lie; the will to deception is turned into a superior ideal. […] for the artists, appearance no longer means the negation of the real in this world but this kind of selection, correction, redoubling and affirmation. Then truth perhaps takes on a new sense. Truth is appearance.
3. Genetic Analysis of the Preface
- Preliminary stages/Drafts [Vorstufe]
- Handwritten fair copy [Reinschrift]
- Print manuscript [Druckmanuskript]
- Correction pages [Korrekturbogen & Korrekturbogenexemplar]
- Author’s examination copy [Handexemplar]
- First edition [Erstdruck]
- Later developments (if any)
3.1. A Genetic Analysis
3.2. Handwritten Fair Copy
3.3. Print Manuscript
3.4. Correction Pages
3.5. The Letter
8.
Translated this reads:Zuletzt, daß ich wenigstens mit Einem Worte auf einen ungeheuren und noch gänzlich unentdeckten Thatbestand hinweise, der sich mir langsam, langsam festgestellt hat: es gab bisher keine grundsätzlicheren Probleme als die moralischen, ihre treibende Kraft war es, aus der alle großen Conceptionen im Reiche der bisherigen Werthe ihren Ursprung genommen haben (—Alles somit, was gemeinhin „Philosophie“ genannt wird; und dies bis hinab in deren letzte erkenntnißtheoretische Voraussetzungen) Aber es giebt noch grundsätzlichere Probleme als die moralischen: diese kommen Einem erst in Sicht, wenn man das moralische Vorurtheil hinter sich hat, wenn man als Immoralist in die Welt, in das Leben, in sich zu blicken weiß…
Finally, I would like to point out, at least in one word, a tremendous and still completely undiscovered fact, which has gradually become apparent to me: up till now there have been no more fundamental problems than the moral [ones], it was their driving force from which all the great conceptions in the realm of the previous values have originated (—Consequently everything, that is commonly called “philosophy”; and this down to the last epistemological presuppositions) But there are even more fundamental problems than the moral [ones]: these come into view only when you have moral prejudice behind you, when you know how to look into the world, into life, into yourself as an Immoralist…18
8.
Translated this reads:Zuletzt, daß ich wenigstens mit Einem Worte auf einen ungeheuren und noch gänzlich unentdeckten Thatbestand hinweise, der sich nur langsam, langsam festgestellt hat: es gab bisher keine grundsätzlicheren Probleme als die moralischen, ihre treibende Kraft ist es, aus der alle großen Conceptionen im Reiche der bisherigen Werthe ihren Ursprung genommen haben (—zum Beispiel alles was gemeinhin “Philosophie” genannt wird; und dies bis hinab in deren letzte erkenntnißtheoretische Voraussetzungen). Aber es giebt noch grundsätzlichere Probleme als die moralischen: diese kommen Einem erst in Sicht, wenn man das moral<ische> Vorurtheil hinter20 sich hat…21
Finally, I want to point out, at least with one word, an immense and still completely undiscovered fact, which has only been slowly, slowly established: there have been no more fundamental problems than the moral ones, it is their driving force from which all great conceptions in the realm of the previous values have originated (—for example, everything that is commonly called “philosophy”; and this right down to its final epistemological presuppositions). But there are even more fundamental problems than the moral ones: these only come into sight when one has moral prejudice behind them…
4. Conclusions: An Immoral Counter-Ideal
In the penultimate section of Z, “The Convalescent”, where Zarathustra confronts the thought of eternal recurrence, he must recover and be redeemed from his great nausea [Ekel]. This reference to being redeemed from the great nausea points to Zarathustra’s encounter with the thought of eternal recurrence.He may bring home the redemption of this reality: its redemption from the curse that the hitherto reigning ideal has laid upon it. This man of the future, who will redeem us not only from the hitherto reigning ideal but also from that which was bound to grow out of it, the great nausea [vom grossen Ekel], the will to nothingness, nihilism. (GM II 24)
However, the most straightforward account of Amor Fati begins in book four of The Gay Science in which eternal recurrence is first introduced. Nietzsche writes,My formula for greatness in a human being is Amor Fati: that one wants nothing to be different, not forward, not backwards, not in all eternity. Not merely bear what is necessary, still less conceal it […] but love it.(Nietzsche 1967a, EH Clever 10)
It is notable that not wanting to accuse is one of the important results of Zarathustra’s recovery after confrontation with eternal recurrence in “The Convalescent.” While GS provides the most straightforward account of Amor Fati, we also obtain a glimpse of it being performed in Beyond Good and Evil 56.I want to learn more and more to see as beautiful what is necessary in things; then I shall be one of those who makes things beautiful. Amor Fati: let that be my love henceforth! I do not want to wage war against what is ugly. I do not want to accuse; I do not even want to accuse those who accuse. Looking away shall be my only negation.27
Someone who has opened his eyes to the opposite ideal, in the face of the idea of eternal recurrence, can affirm life through Amor Fati. Thinking through the thought of eternal recurrence might very well crush you as Nietzsche mentions in GS 341, but it might also change you into the kind of person that wants nothing more fervently than eternal necessity. If one could achieve this, one would have willed beyond good and evil and beyond morality. If everything is necessary, there is no praise or blame to be distributed. There is no linear eschatological ending or heavenly after-world to which we can flee our lives. To think through eternal recurrence and be able to will Amor Fati is to have found the counter-ideal beyond morality. This is indicated by the ending of the removed section, which gives away the ending of GM, stating, “But there are even more fundamental problems than the moral [ones]: these come into view only when you have moral prejudice behind you, when you know how to look into the world, into life, into yourself as an Immoralist…” The hope, then, is to encounter these problems through the thought of eternal recurrence and be able to will Amor Fati, the counter-ideal. The attitude of Amor Fati offers a solution to the problem of meaning without falling back into either morality or the ascetic ideal.[…] the opposite ideal: the ideal of the most high-spirited, alive, and world-affirming human being who has not only come to terms and learned to get along with whatever was and is, but who wants to have what was and is repeated into all eternity, shouting insatiably da capo [from the beginning, play it again]—not only to himself but to the whole play and spectacle, and not only to a spectacle but at bottom to him who needs precisely this spectacle—and who makes it necessary because again and again he needs himself—and makes himself necessary.(Nietzsche 1966, BGE 56)
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | In this essay I will be using standard scholarly abbreviations: The Gay Science (GS), Thus Spoke Zarathustra (Z), Beyond Good and Evil (BGE), The Genealogy of Morals (GM), Ecce Homo (EH), and Nietzsche Contra Wagner (NCW). The KGW represents the most comprehensive of Nietzsche’s complete works (Kritische Gesamtausgabe Werke) and the KSA is a smaller version of complete works (Samtliche Werke: Kritische Studienausgabe). Similarly, Nietzsche’s letters are found in KSB (Sämtliche Briefe: Kritische Studienausgabe) or KGB (Briefe: Kritische Gesamtausgabe). |
2 | (Nietzsche 1887), image 4 (title page) [Princeton University Library. Call number: 6179.67.39. PT2440.N72 A6 2002 vol.15. https://dpul.princeton.edu/pudl0106/catalog/7s75dd671]. Accessed 4 April 2022. |
3 | While the distinction between “Traditional” and “Postmodern” is itself very crude, this has guided the debate and is therefore a historically useful, if overgeneralized, demarcation. As this distinction was created by the “Traditional” school, it is likely those categorized as “Postmodern” would reject being lumped together. |
4 | One might say that only soundness, not validity, assumes truth. This, however, is not Habermas’ target. |
5 | (Derrida 1998, p. 140). Derrida here does not capitalize or italicize “the genealogy of morals” and therefore may be refering to the process rather than the texts itself. |
6 | Nietzsche often relies on selecting his audience based on multiple readings. If you read his text once through, you will get one impression. If you read it several more times, you will have different impressions. For example, once one finishes the third essay discussing the “Will to Truth”, the preface appears in a different light. The very first line is actually about our epistemic access to ourselves, not morality per se. He writes, “We are unknown to ourselves, we knowers: and this for a good reason” (GM Pref. 1). On a first reading, however, one simply rushes by this indication of the text’s topic. Nietzsche also foreshadows the end of the book, writing, “But against these instincts an even more fundamental mistrust, and ever more deeply delving skepticism expressed itself in me! Precisely here I saw the great danger of humankind, its most sublime excitement and seduction—where to? to nothingness?—right here I saw the beginning of the end, the stopping, the backward-looking weariness, the will turned against life […] nihilism” (GM Pref. 5). Here Nietzsche has given away, in part, the ending. However, because this section is framed within the debate of compassion, it does not give away the whole story just yet. It is still plausible to understand this text as one about morality. |
7 | Georg Brandes sent a letter to Nietzsche on 26 November 1887 stating that he had received a copy of GM (KGB iii 6:120. Nr. 500. Georg Brandes to Nietzsche in Nice) |
8 | KSB 8, 111. Number 877—An Constantin Georg Naumann in Leipzig. |
9 | KSB 8, 114–115. Number 879—An Constantin Georg Naumann in Leipzig. |
10 | KSB 8, 115. Number 880—An Constantin Georg Naumann in Leipzig. |
11 | GSA 71/27.1 (https://ores.klassik-stiftung.de/ords/f?p=401:2:::::P2_ID:75094). Accessed 4 April 2022. |
12 | GSA 71/27.2 (https://ores.klassik-stiftung.de/ords/f?p=401:2:::::P2_ID:75097). Accessed 4 April 2022. |
13 | The KGW contains what are called Nachbericht volumes that detail the development of the text and cross reference it. Thus far, only one Nachbericht has been published in division VI and that is for volume 1. What this means is that there is no Nachbericht volume for The Genealogy of Morals. There is, however, some limited information in the Kommentar of the KSA (KSA 14, pp. 377–78). |
14 | This should not be confused with another manuscript that also bears the reference number E40 (Shelfmark: HAAB C 4620). I believe this older reference system was intended to help identify manuscripts that culminated in a final work. It is no longer used. |
15 | HAAB C 4616. “Zur Genealogie der Moral [Korrekturbogenexemplar],” p. 9. (https://haab-digital.klassik-stiftung.de/viewer/!metadata/1649471971/9/-/). Accessed 4 April 2022. |
16 | KSB 8, 163. Number 922. |
17 | https://ores.klassik-stiftung.de/ords/f?p=406:2:::::P2_ID:981. Accessed 4 April 2022. |
18 | As one review pointed out, this could be alternately rendered as: “Finally, that I indicate at least with one word on an uncanny and still entirely (wholly) undiscovered fact, which has become fixed in me slowly, slowly: up to now, there were no more fundamental problems than the moral; it was its driving force from out of which all great conceptions in the realm of values up to here have taken their origin (—All thereby which is commonly named philosophy: and this up to the last epistemological presuppositions). But there are still more fundamental problems than the moral: these come first into sight for one when one has moral prejudice behind oneself, when one knows to see oneself as an immoralist in the world, in life.” While this translation does capture some aspects much better than mine, it does not clearly demonstrate the structural parity with BGE 56 which is important later in the paper. I have decided to keep my own translation. I am thankful to Andrew Jampol-Petzinger for his help in choosing a translation. |
19 | KSB 8, 163. Nr. 923 (https://ores.klassik-stiftung.de/ords/f?p=406:2:::::P2_ID:981). Accessed 4 April 2022. |
20 | The KSA and KGW does not italicize this but it is clearly underlined in the draft in the notebook. |
21 | KGW VIII 1, 5[80, pg. 224; eKGWB/NF-1886,5[80]—Nachgelassene Fragmente Sommer 1886—Herbst 1887. (http://www.nietzschesource.org/#eKGWB/NF-1886,5[80]). Accessed 4 April 2022. |
22 | The KSA, and often the KGW also, do not make it clear when Nietzsche has crossed something out. Often, the crossed out word is simply not included. This is the case here. |
23 | KGW IX, 3, pg 60 of N VII 3. |
24 | It is clear in the document and the KGW IX that “last” (letzte) is crossed out and replaced with “lowest” (unterste) which is also crossed out. It is not clear why the editors of the KSA and KGW included this word. Perhaps it is because he reaffirms “letzte” in the letter. |
25 | (Deleuze 1983, p. 102; Buchsbaum 1993, p. 23). For more on Deleuze’s interpretation of eternal recurrence see (Jampol-Petzinger 2022, pp. 49–55). |
26 | NCW Epilogue, 1. |
27 | GS 276. |
References
- Adorno, Theodor, and Max Horkheimer. 2002. Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments. Edited by Gunzelin Schmmid Noerr. Translated by Edmund Jephcott. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Allison, David. 2001. Reading the New Nietzsche: The Birth of Tragedy, the Gay Science, Thus Spoke Zarathustra, and on the Genealogy of Morals. New York: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. [Google Scholar]
- Babich, Babette. 2006. The Genealogy of Morals and Right Reading: On the Nietzschean Aphorism and the Art of the Polemic. In Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morals: Critical Essays. Edited by Crista Acampora. Lanham and New York: Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 177–90. [Google Scholar]
- Buchsbaum, Julie Anne. 1993. Ascetism and the Value of Truth in The Genealogy of Morals. Episteme 4: 17–27. [Google Scholar]
- Clark, Maudematie. 1990. Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Conway, Daniel. 2008. Nietzsche’s ‘on the Genealogy of Morals’: A Reader’s Guide. New York: Continuum. [Google Scholar]
- Deleuze, Gilles. 1983. Nietzsche and Philosophy. Translated by Hugh Tomlinson. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, Jacques. 1998. Of Gramatology. Translated by Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Foucault, Michel. 1977. Nietzsche, Genealogy, History. In Language, Counter-Memory, Practice: Selected Essays and Interviews. Edited by Donald F. Bouchard. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, pp. 139–64. [Google Scholar]
- Franco, Paul. 2011. Nietzsche’s Enlightenment; the Free-Spirit Trilogy of the Middle Period. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Gemes, Ken. 2006. ‘We Remain of Necessity Strangers to Ourselves’ The Key Message of Nietzsche’s Genealogy. In Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morals: Critical Essays. Edited by Christa Davis Acampora. New York: Rowman and Littlefield, pp. 191–208. [Google Scholar]
- Gillespie, Michael Allen, and Keegan F. Callanan. 2012. On the Genealogy of Morals. In A Companion to Friedrich Nietzsche: Life an Works. Edited by Paul Bishop. New York: Camden House, pp. 255–78. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2006. The Entwinement of Myth and Enlightenment. In Nietzsche’s on the Genealogy of Morals: Critical Essays. Edited by Christa Davis Acampora. New York: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, pp. 223–32. [Google Scholar]
- Hatab, Lawrence. 1987. Nietzsche, Nihilism and Meaning. The Personalist Forum 3: 91–111. [Google Scholar]
- Hatab, Lawrence. 2008. Nietzsche’s on The Genealogy of Morality: An Introduction. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Jampol-Petzinger, Andrew M. 2022. Deleuze, Kierkegaard and the Ethics of Selfhood. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Jenkins, Scott. 2003. Morality, Agency, and Freedom in Nietzsche’s ‘Genealogy of Morals’. History of Philosophy Quarterly 20: 61–80. [Google Scholar]
- Leiter, Brian. 2002. Nietzsche on Morality. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Loeb, Paul S. 2005. Finding the Übermensch in Nietzsche’s Genealogy of Morality. Journal of Nietzsche Studies 30: 70–101. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- May, Simon. 1999. Nietzsche Ethics and His War on ‘Morality’. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- McNiel, Bevis. 2021. Nietzsche and Eternal Recurrence. Cham: Palgrave Mcmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Migotti, Mark. 1998. Slave Morality, Socrates, and the Bushmen: A Reading of the First Essay of On the Genealogy of Morals. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58: 745–79. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Morrisson, Iain. 2014. Ascetic Slaves: Rereading Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morals. Journal of Nietzsche Studies 45: 230–57. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1887. Zur Genealogie der Moral: Eine Streitschrift/von Friedrich Nietzsche. Leipzig: Verlag von C. G. Naumann. [Google Scholar]
- Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1966. [BGE] Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future. Translated by Walter Kaufmann. New York: Vintage Books. [Google Scholar]
- Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1967a. [EH] Ecce Homo: How One Becomes What One Is. Translated by Walter Kaufmann. New York: Vintage Books. [Google Scholar]
- Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1967b. [GM] Genealogy of Morals: A Polemic. Translated by Walter Kaufmann. New York: Vintage Books. [Google Scholar]
- Paphitis, Sharli Anne. 2009. The Doctrine of Eternal Recurrence and its Significance with Respect to On the Genealogy of Morals. South African Journal of Philosophy 28: 189–98. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Parkhurst, William A. B. forthcoming. Ecce Homo—Notes on Duplicates: The Great Politics of the Self. In Nietzsche and the Politics of Difference. Edited by Andrea Rehberg and Ashley Dean Woodward. Germany: De Gruyter, pp. 75–93, forthcoming.
- Poellner, Peter. 2009. Phenomenology and Science in Nietzsche. In A Companion to Nietzsche. Edited by Keith Ansell-Pearson. Malden: Blackwell Publishing, pp. 297–313. [Google Scholar]
- Richardson, John. 2020. Nietzsche’s Values. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Schacht, Richard. 2016. Nietzsche’s Genealogy. In The Oxford Handbook to Nietzsche. Edited by Ken Gemes and John Richardson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 323–43. [Google Scholar]
- Shapiro, Gary. 1990. Translating, Repeating, Naming: Foucault, Derrida and The Genealogy of Morals. In Nietzsche as Postmodernist: Essays Pro and Contra. Edited by Clayton Koelb. Albany: State University of New York Press, pp. 39–55. [Google Scholar]
- Soll, Ivan. 1994. Nietzsche on Cruelty, Asceticism and the Failure of Hedonism. In Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality: Essays on Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morals. Edited by Richard Schact. Berkley: University of California Press, pp. 168–92. [Google Scholar]
- Solms-Lubach, Franz zu. 2007. Nietzsche and Eraly German and Austrian Sociology. Germany: De Gruyter. [Google Scholar]
- Solomon, Robert. 1994. One Hundred Years of Ressentiment: Nietzsche’s Genealogy of Morals. In Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality: Essays on Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morals. Edited by Richard Schacht. Berkley: University of California Press, pp. 95–126. [Google Scholar]
- von Tevenar, Gudrun. 2016. Zarathustra: ‘That Malicious Dionysian. In The Oxford Handbook to Nietzsche. Edited by Ken Gemes and John Richardson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 272–97. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Parkhurst, W.A.B. A Genetic Interpretation of the Preface of The Genealogy of Morals. Genealogy 2022, 6, 81. https://doi.org/10.3390/genealogy6040081
Parkhurst WAB. A Genetic Interpretation of the Preface of The Genealogy of Morals. Genealogy. 2022; 6(4):81. https://doi.org/10.3390/genealogy6040081
Chicago/Turabian StyleParkhurst, William A. B. 2022. "A Genetic Interpretation of the Preface of The Genealogy of Morals" Genealogy 6, no. 4: 81. https://doi.org/10.3390/genealogy6040081
APA StyleParkhurst, W. A. B. (2022). A Genetic Interpretation of the Preface of The Genealogy of Morals. Genealogy, 6(4), 81. https://doi.org/10.3390/genealogy6040081