Civility and Civil Religion before and after the French Revolution: Religious and Secular Rituals in Hume and Tocqueville
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Hume on the Role of Religious and Secular Rituals in Modern Civility
2.1. The Critique of Religious Rituals in Hume
2.2. Simple Religious Rituals: A Remedy to Superstition?
All the forms of ceremony, invented by pride and ostentation, Fox and his disciples, from a superior pride and ostentation, carefully rejected: Even the ordinary rites of civility were shunned, as the nourishment of carnal vanity and self-conceit. They would bestow no titles of distinction: The name of friend was the only salutation, with which they indiscriminately accosted every one. To no person would they make a bow, or move their hat, or give any signs of reverence. Instead of that affected adulation, introduced into modern tongues, of speaking to individuals as if they were a multitude, they returned to the simplicity of ancient languages; and thou and thee were the only expressions, which, on any consideration, they could be brought to employ.
3. Secular Rituals: The Importance of the Symbolic Order in the History of Civility
3.1. Profane Rituals: Secularization or Irreducible Religiosity?
3.2. The Letter of 1734 on Politeness and the Essay on Chivalry: Early Thoughts on the Importance of Secular Rituals in the Civilizing Process
4. Civil Religion in America: Religious and Secular Rituals in Tocqueville
4.1. Protestantism, Catholicism, and Rituals in America
I firmly believe in the necessity of forms. I know that they fix the human mind in the contemplation of abstract truths, and forms, by helping the mind to grasp those truths firmly, make it embrace them with fervor. I do not imagine that it is possible to maintain a religion without external practices, but on the other hand I think that, during the centuries we are entering, it would be particularly dangerous to multiply them inordinately…”.
4.2. Patriotism and Christian Civil Religion in America
4.3. Hume and Tocqueville: A Comparative Assessment
5. Concluding Remarks: Civil Religion or Rituals of Civility?
Funding
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Beiner, Ronald. 2012. Civil Religion: A Dialogue in the History of Political Philosophy. Cambridge: CUP. [Google Scholar]
- Berry, Christopher. 2018. Essays on Hume, Smith and the Scottish Enlightenment. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Chriss, James J. 1993. Durkheim’s Cult of the Individual as Civil Religion: its Appropriation by Erving Goffman. Sociology and Criminology Faculty Publication 97: 251–75. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Costelloe, Timothy. 2004. ‘In Every Civilized Community’: Hume on Belief and the Demise of Religion. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 55: 171–85. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Craiutu, Aurelian, and Matthew N. Holbreich. 2015. On individualism, Authority, and Democracy as a New Form of Religion: A few Tocquevillian Reflections. In Combining the Spirit of Religion and the Spirit of Liberty: Tocqueville’s Thesis Revisited. Edited by Catherine Zuckert. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- De Dijn, Herman. 2003. Promise and ritual: Profane and sacred symbols in Hume’s philosophy of religion. The Journal of Scottish Philosophy 1: 64. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- De Dijn, Herman. 2011. The Natural History of Religion in Hume and Baron d’Holbach. Paper presented at Hume Society Conference, Old College, Edinburgh, UK, July 19. [Google Scholar]
- De Dijn, Herman. 2012. Spinoza and Hume on Religion as a Natural Phenomenon. Hume Studies 38: 1. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Durkheim, Emile. 1933. The Division of Labor in Society. Glencoe: The Free Press of Glencoe. First published 1893. [Google Scholar]
- Elias, Norbert. 1978. The Civilizing Process. In The History of Manners. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. First published 1939. [Google Scholar]
- Hanley, Ryan. 2013. Hume’s Critique and Defense of Religion. In Enlightenment and Secularism: Essays on the Mobilization of Reason. Edited by Christian Nadon. Lanham: Lexington Books. [Google Scholar]
- Hume, David. 1998. An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals. Edited by Tom L. Beauchamp. Oxford: OUP. First published 1751. [Google Scholar]
- Hume, David. 2007. The Natural History of Religion. Edited by Tom L. Beauchamp. Oxford: Clarendon Press. First published 1757. [Google Scholar]
- Hume, David. 1932. The Letters of David Hume. Edited by J. Y. T. Creig. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2 vols. [Google Scholar]
- Hume, David. 1983. The History of England. Edited by William B. Todd: Liberty Classics. First published 1754–1761. [Google Scholar]
- Hume, David. 1985. Enquiries concerning Human Understanding and concerning the Principles of Morals, 3rd ed. Edited by Peter H. Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon Press. First published 1748 and 1751. [Google Scholar]
- Hume, David. 1987. Essays Moral, Political and Literary. Edited by Eugene F. Miller. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund. First published 1742–1751. [Google Scholar]
- Jordan, W. R. 2002. Religion in the Public Square: A Reconsideration of Hume and Religious Establishment. The Review of Politics 64: 687–713. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kahan, Alan. 2015. Tocqueville, Democracy, and Religion: Checks and Balances for Democratic Souls. Oxford: OUP. [Google Scholar]
- Kries, Douglas. 2010. Alexis de Tocqueville on ‘Civil Religion" and the Catholic Faith. In Civil Religion in Political Thought/ Its Perennial Questions and Enduring Relevance in North America. Edited by Ronald Weed and John Von Heyking. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, pp. 167–205. [Google Scholar]
- Langford, Paul. 2002. The Uses of Eighteenth-Century Politeness. Transactions of the RHS 12: 311–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lemmens, Wim. 2011. Beyond the Calm Sunshine of the Mind. Hume on Religion and Morality. Aufklarung und Kritik 1: 423–60. [Google Scholar]
- McClay, Wilfred M. 2010. Foreword. In Civil Religion in Political Thought/ Its Perennial Questions and Enduring Relevance in North America. Edited by Ronald Weed and John Von Heyking. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, pp. i–ix. [Google Scholar]
- Mossner, Cambell Ernst. 1947. David Hume’s “An Historical Essay on Chivalry and Modern Honour”. Modern Philology 45: 1. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mossner, Cambell Ernst. 1980. The Life of David Hume. Oxford: OUP. [Google Scholar]
- Muir, Edward. 2005. Ritual in early Modern Europe. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Pocock, John Greville Agard. 1999. Enlightenment and Counter-Enlightenment, Revolution and Counter-Revolution: a Eurosceptical Enquiry. History of Political Thought 20: 125–39. [Google Scholar]
- Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 2012. On the Social Contract. In The Major Political Writings of J.-J. Rousseau. Edited by John T. Scott. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. First published 1762. [Google Scholar]
- Siebert, Thomas. 1995. Hume on Idolatry and Incarnation. In David Hume: Critical Assessments. Edited by Stanley Tweyman. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Stasch, Rupert. 2011. Ritual and Oratory Revisited: The Semiotics of Effective Action. Annual Review of Anthropology 40: 159–74. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Streminger, G. 1989. Religion, a threat to morality: an attempt to throw some new light on Hume’s philosophy of religion. Hume Studies 2: 277–93. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tocqueville, Alexis. 1861. Memoirs, Letters and Remains. Translated by Napoleon’s Correspondence with King Joseph. Cambridge: Macmillan and Co. [Google Scholar]
- Tocqueville, Alexis. 2010. Democracy in America. Historical-Critical Edition of De la Démocratie en Amérique. Edited by Eduardo Nolla. Translated by James T. Scheifer. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 4 vols. First published 1835–1840. [Google Scholar]
- Weed, Ronald, and John Von Heyking. 2010. Introduction. In Civil Religion in Political Thought/ Its Perennial Questions and Enduring Relevance in North America. Edited by Ronald Weed and John Von Heyking. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, pp. 1–15. [Google Scholar]
- Zuckert, Catherine. 2016. The saving minimum? Tocqueville on the Role of Religion in America—Then and Now. American Political Thought: A Journal of Ideas, Institutions, and Culture 5. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
1 | Essays 74: “As these enemies are entirely invisible and unknown, the methods that taken to appease them are equally unaccountable, and consists in ceremonies, observances, mortifications, sacrifices, presents, or in any practice, however absurd or frivolous, which either folly or knavery recommends to a blind and terrified credulity.” |
2 | (Streminger 1989): “Because they feel that their moral acts are plainly natural, they have to find something that is done for God’s sake: rites, ceremonies, and, sometimes, oppression and annihilation of other people.” |
3 | (Hume [1754–1761] 1983, V, p. 460): ‘Whatever ridicule, to a philosophical mind, may be thrown on pious ceremonies, it must be confessed, that, during a very religious age, no institution can be more advantageous to the rude multitude, and tend more to mollify that fierce and gloomy spirit of devotion, to which they are subject. Even the English church, though it had retained a share of popish ceremonies, may justly be thought too naked and anadorned, and still to approach too near the abstract and spiritual religion of the Puritans. Laud and his associates, by reviving a few primitive institutions...corrected the error of the first reformers and presented to the affrightened and astonished mind, some sensible, exterior observances, which might occupy it during its religious exercises, and abate the violence of its disappointed efforts. The thought, no longer bent on that divine and mysterious essence, so superior to the narrow capacities of mankind, was able...to relax itself in the contemplation of pictures, postures, vestments, buildings.’ |
4 | (Hume [1754–1761] 1983, vol. V, p. 46): ‘The mind, straining for these extraordinary raptures, reaching them by short glances, sinking again under its own weakness, rejecting all exterior aid of pomp and ceremony, was so occupied in this inward life, that it fled from every intercourse of society, and from every chearful amusement, which could soften or humanize the character. It was obvious to all discerning eyes, and had not escaped the king’s, that, by the prevalence of fanaticism, a gloomy and sullen disposition established itself among the people; a spirit, obstinate and dangerous; independent and disorderly; animated equally with a contempt of authority, and a hatred to every other mode of religion, particularly to the Catholic. In order to mellow these humours, James endeavoured to infuse a small tincture of ceremony into the national worship, and to introduce such rites as might, in some degree, occupy the mind, and please the senses, without departing too far from that simplicity…’ |
5 | Regarding religion’s benign role in ‘every civilized society’ see (Costelloe 2004). |
6 | (De Dijn 2003, 2012). |
7 | (De Dijn, ibid. pp. 63–64); (Hume [1748 and 1751] 1985, p. 200). |
8 | Ibid., pp. 37, 94. |
9 | (De Dijn 2012, p. 17). In another paper, [Response to Richard Hodgson, “The Natural History of Religion in Hume and Baron d’Holbach” (19 July 2011—Old College, Lecture Theatre)] De Dijn perspicuously remarks: “He seems to be the first, or among the first, together with Gianbattista Vico and Montesquieu, to pay attention to characteristics of human life which will be theorized about only much later by cultural anthropologists, more particularly the immersion of morality in culture. From our present perspective, one can regret two things. First, that Hume does not seem to apply his insights as to the importance of symbol and ritual or ceremony to the link between morality and culture. He does not sufficiently attend to the degree in which morality as a whole is pervaded by symbol and ritual; and this independently of the fact whether it is the morality of a religious or a secularized society. The morality even of secularized individuals, living today or in the 18th century, is strongly characterized by all sorts of moral taboos.’ |
10 | |
11 | David Hume to Michael Ramsay, 12 September 1734 (Hume 1932, pp. 19–21). |
12 | (Mossner 1947, p. 60): “…Your Devotees feel their devotion increase by the Observance of trivial Superstitions, as Sprinkling, Kneeling, Crossing &c, so men insensibly soften towards each other in the practice of these Ceremonies.” |
13 | There is a striking parallel to be drawn between the treatment of foreigners and strangers through the rites of politeness in Hume and the critique of politeness sketched by Rousseau in Emile. Following the drift of Humean argument, we might suggest that the treatment of foreigners is the most prominent locus of politeness as it regards the outsider par excellence, the one who by his mere presence breaks any habit and custom that informs human intercourse within the frame of a given community. In another essay, Hume evokes that the progress of civility and commerce over ancient times becomes palpable in the modern distinction between the notions of stranger and enemy that ancient ferocious manners used to conflate in the term hostis (‘Of commerce’, (Hume [1742–1751] 1987, p. 259, n.8)). |
14 | (Hume [1742–1751] 1987, p. 132): “Whenever nature has given the mind a propensity to any vice, or to any passion disagreeable to others, refined breeding has taught men to throw the bias on the opposite side, and to preserve, in all their behaviour, the appearance of sentiments different from those to which they naturally incline…In like manner, whenever a person’s situation may naturally beget any disagreeable suspicion in him, it is the part of good manners to prevent it, by a studied display of sentiments, directly contrary to those of which he is apt to be jealous. Thus, old men know their infirmities, and naturally dread contempt from the youth: Hence, well-educated youth redouble the instances of respect and deference to their elders. Strangers and foreigners are without protection: Hence, in all polite countries, they receive the highest civilities, and are entitled to the first place in every company. A man is lord in his own family, and his guests are, in a manner, subject to his authority; Hence, he is always the lowest person in the company; attentive to the wants of everyone; and giving himself all the trouble, in order to please, which may not betray too visible an affectation, or to impose too much constrain on his guests. Gallantry is but an instance of the same generous attention.” |
15 | (Tocqueville [1835–1840] 2010, vol. III, p. 30): “You see today more than in earlier periods, Catholics who become unbelievers and Protestant who turn into Catholics.” |
16 | For a comparison with Rousseau that takes into account this dialectic between moderate forms of Protestantism and Catholicism see (Beiner 2012, pp. 251–52). |
17 | (Tocqueville [1835–1840] 2010, vol. II, p. 133): “…and what is more important for society is not so much that all citizens profess the true religion but that they profess a religion. All the sects in the United States are, moreover, within the great Christian unity, and the morality of Christianity is the same everywhere. [In America there are Catholics and Protestants, but Americans profess the Christian religion.] |
18 | On the other side of the channel, Rousseau, equally concerned with superstition within religious institutions, inaugurates a different tradition of thought: he famously expresses a wholesale rejection of modern manners while setting forth an idiosyncratic civil religion, see (Rousseau [1762] 2012, pp. 263–72). Rousseau rejects manners precisely as empty ceremonial while he sacralises the social contract’s basic tenets. Both philosophers, suspicious about progress in religious matters, seek to evacuate superstitious elements from social life without dismissing the affective dispositions of human nature. |
© 2020 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Tegos, S. Civility and Civil Religion before and after the French Revolution: Religious and Secular Rituals in Hume and Tocqueville. Genealogy 2020, 4, 48. https://doi.org/10.3390/genealogy4020048
Tegos S. Civility and Civil Religion before and after the French Revolution: Religious and Secular Rituals in Hume and Tocqueville. Genealogy. 2020; 4(2):48. https://doi.org/10.3390/genealogy4020048
Chicago/Turabian StyleTegos, Spyridon. 2020. "Civility and Civil Religion before and after the French Revolution: Religious and Secular Rituals in Hume and Tocqueville" Genealogy 4, no. 2: 48. https://doi.org/10.3390/genealogy4020048
APA StyleTegos, S. (2020). Civility and Civil Religion before and after the French Revolution: Religious and Secular Rituals in Hume and Tocqueville. Genealogy, 4(2), 48. https://doi.org/10.3390/genealogy4020048