2. Midpoint Representation for Fuzzy Numbers
The family
of all bounded closed intervals in
is defined as the following set:
within which the
midpoint-radius representation for a given interval
provides for the midpoint
and radius
defined as:
where
and
. An interval is denoted by
or, in midpoint notation, by
and consequently
is also equal to
It follows that when an interval belongs to then its elements are denoted as , with , and the interval by in extreme-point representation or, equivalently, by , in midpoint notation.
Given two intervals and , the following classical (Minkowski-type) addition, scalar multiplication and difference are defined:
,
,
,
.
On the other hand, using midpoint notation, the above operations, for and become:
,
,
,
.
In what follows, the subscript , indicating the Minkowski-type operations, is used just when misunderstandings may arise.
The generalized Hukuhara difference (
-difference for short, as extensively detailed in [
3,
9]) of two intervals
A and
B always exists and it is denoted by
or, using midpoint notation, by
Similarly, we have that the
-addition for intervals is also defined by
Furthermore, if , the length of interval A will be denoted by .
In addition, given two intervals
, the Pompeiu–Hausdorff distance
is:
where
; it is established (see [
3]) that
and for
it holds that
and
is a complete metric space.
The concept of fuzzy set, of which [
10] is a key element, is also part of the preliminary notions useful for evaluating the contribution of the article.
Definition 1 ([
11])
. A fuzzy set on is a mapping and its α-level set are defined as for any . The support is defined as: ; the 0-level set of u is defined by where means the closure of the subset . A fuzzy set on is called a fuzzy number when:
u is normal, i.e., there exists such that
u is a convex fuzzy set (i.e., ),
u is upper semi-continuous on ,
is compact.
If denotes the family of fuzzy numbers, then for any it holds for all , and thus, the -levels of a fuzzy number are given by , for all . In midpoint notation, we write where so that and Triangular fuzzy numbers are well determined by three real numbers , denoted by , with -levels for all .
It is well known that in terms of
-levels, and taking into account the midpoint notation, for every
the following definitions hold:
and
The Level-wise gH (LgH)-difference can be read as a generalization of the fuzzy gH-difference.
Definition 2. For given two fuzzy numbers , the LgH-difference of is defined as the family of interval-valued gH-differences defined as:that is, for each , either or . In relation with the defined difference, we detail the concept of LgH-differentiability.
Definition 3 ([
9])
. Let and h be such that , then the LgH-derivative of a function at is defined as the set of interval-valued gH-derivatives, if they exist,If is a compact interval for all we say that F is LgH-differentiable at and the family of intervals is the LgH-derivative of F at , denoted by Also, one-side derivatives can be considered. The right gH-derivative of
F at
is
while to the left it is defined as
The LgH-derivative exists at if and only if the left and right derivatives at exist and produce the same interval.
In terms of midpoint representation
, for all
, we can write
and taking the limit for
, we obtain the LgH-derivative of
, if and only if the two limits
and
exist in
; we remark that the midpoint function
is required to admit the ordinary derivative at
x. With respect to the existence of the second limit, the existence of the left and right derivatives
and
is required with
(in particular
if
exists) so that we have
or, in the standard interval notation,
3. Orders for Fuzzy Numbers
Regarding the partial order for intervals, the LU-fuzzy partial order is well known in the literature and we can find a complete investigation in [
12]; Ref. [
1] also introduces a more general
-order based on the gH-difference that includes the generally used order relations and allows the definition of risk measures to quantify a worst-case loss in interval maximization or minimization problems.
To facilitate understanding of the text, we present some of the key definitions related to these interval orders.
Specifically, consider two intervals
and
. We then define the
Lower and Upper order (abbreviated as the
-order), denoted by
, as follows:
However, we can further refine the definition by incorporating the cases of strict order and strong order, exactly as reported in [
5,
6].
The subsequent definition extends the statement made in (
20).
Definition 4 ([
5])
. Given , , we say that- (i)
if and only if and ,
- (ii)
if and only if and ( or ),
- (iii)
if and only if and .
Using midpoint notation
,
, the partial orders
and
above can be expressed as
while the partial order
can be expressed in terms of
with the additional requirement that at least one of the inequalities is strict.
The three order relations , and can be generalized on the basis of the -difference as follows.
Definition 5 ([
6])
. Given two intervals and and , (eventually and/or ) we define the following order relation, denoted ,similarly, we define the following (strict) order relation, denoted ,and the following (strong) order relation, denoted , At this point, extending what is reported in [
13] to its corresponding fuzzy version, it is interesting to further expand the cases relating to the
-order, analyzing the entire spectrum of possibilities that the two real values
and
can assume.
Therefore, let
with
, if we consider
and the corresponding level-wise expressed in midpoint notation
, for each
, we are able to define three relations between
u and a generic fuzzy number
, with
; in [
14] the following equivalences are established:
while in [
1] we write the equivalence in the following form (where the conditions
, is added when
or
):
The third case can be analyzed in a more detailed way; given the conditions in case (3):
the order relation denoted as
can be defined as follows:
i.e.,
Moreover, as it will be better defined below (see Definition 8), for a given fuzzy number , it is possible to introduce the following sets of fuzzy numbers :
-dominated by :
-dominating :
-incomparable with when , but it does not belong to any of the two previous sets.
Note also that by changing and , we obtain an infinite number of partial orders and by increasing and/or decreasing , the incomparability region(s) will be reduced.
Now we will consider only case 3 (
) because of its significance in estimating the risk of possible worst-case loss (see [
11,
15,
16]); indeed, it is possible to face two types of risk, due to the possibility of a worst-case loss if we make a choice exclusively on the basis of the midpoint values
and
.
In many real-life situations, we need to select an appropriate action. In economics, a reasonable idea is to select an action that leads to the largest values of the expected gain because if we repeatedly make such a selection, then, because of the law of large numbers, we will obtain the largest possible gain.
Moreover, according to [
14], it appears evident that for all
, where
and
according to endpoint and midpoint notations, respectively, the following properties are satisfied:
reflexivity: , for all ;
antisymmetry: and iff , for all ;
transitivity: and , then , for all ;
consistency with common sense: if then , for all ;
scale-invariance: if then , for all (that is, if we multiply all the gains by the same positive constant , then whichever gain was larger remains larger, and whichever gain was smaller remains smaller);
additivity: iff for all (that is, if we add the same amount to the two gains, this will not change which gain is larger);
closeness: when the values of and are close, the corresponding alternatives are practically indistinguishable. Similarly, if we have two sequences and so that and endpoints of both tends to some limits, then, since the limit intervals are indistinguishable from these ones for sufficiently large n, we should expect the same relation ⩽ for the limit intervals. This means that if for all n, and , , , , then .
From now on the symbol ⪷ will be used to indicate , with and, in addition to the ⪷-order, we will also consider the relations of strict order, indicated by ≾, and of strong order, indicated by ≺, which, respectively, stand for and .
We point out that, given and , we write their -levels in endpoint notation as and , respectively.
Definition 6. Given u, and given we say that
- 1.
if and only if that is, and ,
- 2.
if and only if
- 3.
if and only if
Correspondingly, the analogous -fuzzy orders can be obtained by
- 4.
if and only if for all
- 5.
if and only if for all
- 6.
if and only if for all
The corresponding reverse orders are, respectively, , and .
Switching to the
-levels midpoint notation
,
for all
, the partial orders
and
above can be written for all
as
then, adding the requirement that at least one of the two inequalities be strict, we can express the partial order (2.) in terms of
.
The results listed below are obtained from those in [
5,
6] for each
, where proof can be found, too. Indeed, the level-wise generalized Hukuhara difference (LgH-difference), which was used in the fuzzy case, turns out to be more general than the gH-difference of the interval case, but if we consider the
-levels of the fuzzy version, then we have that the properties as in the interval case are confirmed; therefore, all the relations and properties established in the above-mentioned papers are maintained.
Proposition 1. Let with for all . We have
- 1.
if and only if ;
- 2.
if and only if and ;
- 3.
if and only if ;
- 4.
if and only if ;
- 5.
if and only if and ;
- 6.
if and only if .
When case 3 is verified (if > 0 then we consider ), we have that the following holds.
Proposition 2. Let with , for all . We have
- 1.
if and only if ;
- 2.
if and only if ;
- 3.
if and only if ;
- 4.
if and only if ;
- 5.
if and only if ;
- 6.
if and only if .
Definition 7. Given , we clearly have thatWe say that u and v are incomparable if neither nor and u and v are α-incomparable if neither nor Proposition 3. Let with , for all . The following are equivalent:
- 1.
u and v are α-incomparable;
- 2.
is not a singleton and ;
- 3.
for ;
- 4.
or ,
where is the set of all interior points in an interval E.
It is trivial to note that Proposition 3 is not valid for -incomparable.
Proposition 4. If , then
- 1.
if and only if ;
- 2.
If then ;
- 3.
If then ;
- 4.
if and only if .
Definition 8. Given with , for all . We define the following sets of fuzzy numbers y:
- 1.
- 2.
- 3.
-incomparable with u:
Proposition 5. For any fuzzy numbers , we have
- 1.
if and only if ;
- 2.
if and only if ;
- 3.
;
- 4.
;
- 5.
.
4. General Properties of Fuzzy-Valued Functions
In general, a function
F is said to be a fuzzy-valued when it is defined as the family of interval-valued functions
given by
for all
. Using midpoint notation, it is denoted as
where
stands for the midpoint value of interval
and
is the half-length of
:
so that
Once more, the outcomes presented below are derived from those in [
5,
6] for each
; given that the procedures are similar, they are reiterated here without additional demonstration.
Proposition 6. Let be a fuzzy-valued function and be an accumulation point of T. If with . Then for all α (uniformly in ).
Considering the midpoint notation, let
and
for all
; it follows that we can express the limits and continuity, respectively, as
and
A connection between limits and the order of fuzzy numbers can be easily obtained as expressed by the following proposition. Considering the reverse partial order ⪸, it is possible to infer similar results.
Proposition 7. Let be fuzzy-valued functions and an accumulation point for T.
- 1.
If for all in a neighborhood of and , , then ;
- 2.
If for all in a neighborhood of and , then .
For the left limit with , ( for short) and for the right limit , ( for short) similar results to those of Propositions 6 and 7 hold; the condition that if and only if is implied.
It is therefore possible to graphically represent a fuzzy-valued function in both standard ways, by plotting the level curves
and
in the plane
(as in
Figure 1), or by drawing the parametric curves
and
in the half-plane
(as in
Figure 2); in both figures the fuzzy function
is such that
-cuts are defined by functions:
which does not depend on
and
for
; only
-cuts are represented for uniform
.
In
Figure 3, based on the midpoint representation, we obtain that the red lines on the right pictures reconstruct the eleven
-cuts and it is established that
y and
share the same domain, and the linear vertical segment in the midpoint representation corresponds to a symmetric membership function having the same value of
for all
.
Definition 9. Let be a fuzzy function, where for all . We say that F is
(a-i) -nondecreasing on if implies for all ;
(a-ii) -nonincreasing on if implies for all ;
(b-i) (strictly) -increasing on if implies for all ;
(b-ii) (strictly) -decreasing on if implies for all ;
(c-i) (strongly) -increasing on if implies for all ;
(c-ii) (strongly) -decreasing on if implies for all .
If one of the six conditions is satisfied, we say that F is monotonic on ; the monotonicity is strict if (b-i,b-ii) or strong if (c-i,c-ii) are satisfied.
We can also analyze the monotonicity of locally, in a neighborhood of an interior point , by considering condition (or condition ) for and with a positive small .
Definition 10. Let be a fuzzy function, where for all and . Let (for positive δ) denote a neighborhood of . We say that F is (locally)
(a-i) -nondecreasing at if implies for all and some ;
(a-ii) -nonincreasing at if implies for all and some ;
(b-i) (strictly)-increasing at if implies for all and some ;
(b-ii) (strictly)-decreasing at if implies for all and some ;
(c-i) (strongly) -increasing at if implies for all and some ;
(c-ii) (strongly) -decreasing at if implies for all and some .
Proposition 8. Let be a fuzzy function, where for and . Then
- 1.
is -nondecreasing at if and only if is nondecreasing, is nonincreasing and is nondecreasing at for all ;
- 2.
is -nonincreasing at if and only if is nonincreasing, is nondecreasing and is nonincreasing at for all .
Analogous conditions are valid for strict and strong monotonicity.
Proposition 9. Let be a fuzzy function, where for all and let F be LgH-differentiable at the internal points . Then
- 1.
If F is -nondecreasing on , then for all x, ;
- 2.
If F is -nonincreasing on , then for all x, .
A similar result is obtained immediately by relating the strong (local) monotonicity of F to the “sign” of its left and right derivatives and ; note that at the extreme points of , only the right monotonicity (in a) or left monotonicity (in b) and the right or left derivatives are considered.
Proposition 10. Let be a fuzzy function, where for all with left and/or right gH-derivatives at a point . Then
(i.a) if , then F is strongly -increasing on for some (here );
(i.b) if , then F is strongly -increasing on for some (here );
(ii.a) if , then F is strongly -decreasing on for some (here );
(ii.b) if , then F is strongly -decreasing on for some (here ).
As already performed for the monotonicity property, it is possible to manage the concavity and convexity of fuzzy-valued functions; in particular, there are three types of convexity.
Definition 11. Let be a function and let ⪷ be a partial order on . We say that
(a-i) is (⪷)-convex on if and only if and all ;
(a-ii) is ()-concave on if and only if and all .
(b-i) is strictly (≾)-convex on if and only if and all ;
(b-ii) is strictly (≾)-concave on if and only if and all .
(c-i) is strongly (≺)-convex on if and only if and all ;
(c-ii) is strongly (≺)-concave on if and only if and all .
Concavity and convexity of a function satisfy the property that F is (⪷)-concave if and only if is (⪷)-convex.
Proposition 11. Let with for all and ⪷ be a given partial order; then
- 1.
F is (⪷)-convex if and only if is convex, is concave and is convex;
- 2.
F is (⪷)-concave if and only if is concave, is convex and is concave.
According to Proposition 11, it is easy to prove that F is (⪷)-convex (or concave) if and only if and are convex (or concave) for all . Additionally, several ways to analyze (⪷)-convexity (or concavity) in terms of the first or second derivatives of functions , and can be easily derived.
Proposition 12. Let with for all . Real-valued functions and are differentiable, then:
1. If the first order derivatives and exist, then:
(1-a) F is (⪷)-convex on if and only if , and are increasing (nondecreasing) for all on ;
(1-b) F is (⪷)-concave on if and only if , and are decreasing (nonincreasing) for all on ;
2. If the second order derivatives and exist and are continuous, then:
(2-a) F is (⪷)-convex on if and only if , and for all on ;
(2-b) F is (⪷)-concave on if and only if , and for all on .
Remark 1. Similarly to the relationship between the convexity for ordinary functions and the sign of the second derivative, we can establish conditions for convexity of fuzzy functions and the sign of the second-order LgH-derivative ; for example, a sufficient condition for strong ≺-convexity is the following (compare with Proposition 12):
- 1.
If then is strongly concave at .
- 2.
If then is strongly convex at .
The periodicity property for fuzzy-valued functions can also be defined.
Definition 12. A function is said to be periodic if, for some nonzero constant , it occurs that for all with (i.e., for all ). A nonzero constant T for which this is verified is called a period of the function and if there exists a least positive constant T with this property, it is called the fundamental period.
Clearly, in case F has a period T, this also implies that for all has a period T, i.e., for all , and are periodic with period T. On the other side, the periodicity of F is not necessarily implied by the periodicity of the functions for all .
Proposition 13. Let be a continuous function such that for all with periodic of period and of period . Then it holds that:
- (1)
if the periods and are commensurable, i.e., (, such that p and q are coprime) then the function F is periodic of period , i.e, T is the least common multiple between and (i.e., );
- (2)
if the periods and are not commensurable, i.e., , then function F is not periodic.
The function depicted in all the preceding figures, defined by (
39) and (
40), provides a clear example of a periodic function with period
p = 2π.
5. Extrema of Fuzzy Valued Functions
The concepts of simple, strict and strong monotonicity defined above, based on the orders ⪷, ≾ and ≺, give rise to different concepts of extrema.
Regarding the demonstrations of the results presented below, reference is made to those discussed in [
6], as the procedures and steps are similar for each
; therefore, the results are provided here without further demonstrations. Additionally, the following terminology will be adopted.
Definition 13. If , we say that dominates with respect to the partial order ⪷ (for short, -dominated ), or equivalently that is -dominated by . We say that and are incomparable with respect to ⪷ if both and are not valid. Analogous domination rules are defined in terms of the strict and strong order relations ≾ and ≺, respectively.
Now the basic concepts of order-based minimum and maximum points can be introduced for fuzzy-valued functions.
Definition 14. Let be a fuzzy-valued function and . We say that, with respect to ⪷,
- (a)
is a local lattice-minimum point of F (-point for short) if there exists such that for all , i.e., if all around are -dominated by ;
- (b)
is a local lattice-maximum point of F (-point for short) if there exists such that for all , i.e., if all around -dominate .
It will be helpful to explicitly establish the conditions for
-dominance of a general fuzzy function
, with respect to fuzzy functions
and
, that characterize the minimality and the maximality of a point
(for min) or a point
(for max). Avoiding making an explicit distinction between strict or strong dominance, we have, for all
:
and
With the following proposition it is possible to show that lattice-type minimality and maximality, with respect to the partial order ⪷, can be identified exactly in terms of functions
and
, for all
, as follows.
Proposition 14. Let be a fuzzy-valued function, where for all . Then
- (a)
is a min-point of F if and only if it is a minimum of functions and for all ;
- (b)
is a max-point of F if and only if it is a maximum of functions and for all .
What has been seen above shows the restricting notion of a lattice-extreme point, since it is rare for simultaneous extrema to occur for the two functions and . Taking into account the possibility that the fuzzy functions for different x are locally incomparable with respect to the actual order relation, the following definition is more general.
Definition 15. Let be a fuzzy-valued function and . We say that, with respect to the order ⪷ and the corresponding strict order ≾,
(c) is a local best-minimum point of F (best-min for short) if:
(c.1) it is a local minimum for the midpoint function for all , and
(c.2) there exists and no point with such that ;
(d) is a local best-maximum point of F (best-max for short) if:
(d.1) it is a local maximum for the midpoint function for all , and
(d.2) there exists and no point with such that .
We can give the definitions of strict and strong (local) extremal points considering the strict ≾ or the strong ≺ orders associated to the lattice order ⪷.
Definition 16. Let be a fuzzy-valued function. With respect to an order ⪷ and the associated strict order ≾ or strong order ≺, we say that
- -
a best-min point is a strict (respectively, strong) best-minimum point if there exists and no point with (or , respectively);
- -
a best-max point is a strict (respectively, strong) best-maximum point if there exists and no point with (or , respectively).
Considering the case in which
is a lattice-minimum point, that is, there exists a neighborhood of
such that all
satisfy (
41), we have that no such
is incomparable with
; similarly, if
is a lattice-maximum point, i.e., there exists a neighborhood of
such that all
satisfy (
42), then no such
is incomparable with
. This fact can be expressed by saying that the (local) min-efficient frontier for the
-point
is concentrated into the fuzzy function
; analogously, the (local) max-efficient frontier for the max-point
is concentrated into the fuzzy function
.
On the other hand, in the case where and are best-type and not lattice-type extrema, then it is fundamental to identify the fuzzy function , in particular with x in a neighborhood of or , that are not min-dominated by (or do not max-dominate ); clearly, these are necessarily (⪷)-incomparable with (or with , respectively).
Therefore, corresponding to a minimum and to a maximum point of F, we are interested in identifying the locally (min/max)-efficient fuzzy function and what we will call the local min or max efficient frontier for and around points and , respectively.
In order to find the efficient frontier for a strict minimum and a strict maximum, the first thing to do is the following:
Proposition 15. Let be a fuzzy-valued function. Let be local strict best-min and local strict best-max points of F. Then, there exist , , and (all belonging to ) such that, respectively,
- 1.
is incomparable with , for all , ;
- 2.
is incomparable with , for all , .
A significant consequence of Proposition 15 is a sufficient condition for a lattice type external point.
Proposition 16. Let ; if (respectively, ) is a minimum point (a maximum point) of function for all and (or ) then is a lattice min-point (respectively is a lattice max-point) of and vice versa.
Another crucial consequence of the last proposition is that the efficient function , relative to the best minimum point or to the best maximum point , considering the case where they are not extremal points of the lattice, must be sought between the points and , respectively.
The last step is to feature the points of and that contain, respectively, , and are such that all corresponding define the local efficient frontier of F around and .
We begin by providing a formal definition of the min/max efficient frontier:
Definition 17. Let be a fuzzy-valued function and let be local strict best-min and local strict best-max points of F with respect to the partial order ⪷.
(a) The (local) min-efficient frontier of function F associated to the best-min point (or to the best-min fuzzy-value ) is the set of fuzzy-values such that:
(a.1) ,
(a.2) if and then and are (⪷)-incomparable,
(a.3) no other set containing has property (a.2). The set of points such that are the local min-efficient points corresponding to and is denoted by .
(b) The (local) max-efficient frontier of function F associated to the best-max point (or to the best-max fuzzy-value ) is the set of fuzzy-values such that:
(b.1) ,
(b.2) if and then and are (⪷)-incomparable,
(b.3) no other set containing has property (b.2). The set of points such that are the local max-efficient points corresponding to and is denoted by .
The efficient frontiers or are obviously subsets of the interval in Proposition 15; but, in cases where the function has possible inflection or angular points, tangencies of high order, multiple nodes, fractal-like or complex pathological patterns, their characterization is not at all simple.
Let us consider the curve , in the half-plane with parametric equations , and parameter and assume that the curve is simple (without multiple points) and differentiable (i.e., both and have derivatives at internal points); we say that has the convexity property if, for each of its points, the curve lies on one side of the tangent line to it. In our case, the convexity of is only needed locally, considering the restriction of to points around (or ). In particular, we fix the notion of local convexity of by distinguishing the case of a minimum to the case of a maximum point.
Taking into account specific assumptions about the function’s shape, the following results can be proven:
Proposition 17. Let ⪷ be a partial order on and let be a fuzzy-valued function with for all such that is a local min point of for all and Assumption 1 is satisfied. Then there exist two points with and such that, for ,
- (1)
either maximizes and minimizes for all ,
- (2)
or minimizes and maximizes for all ,
and equivalently,
- (i)
either minimizes and minimizes for all ,
- (ii)
or maximizes and minimizes for all .
Furthermore, interval is the local efficient frontier of Definition 17. In particular, if and are internal to the local convexity region and , are differentiable at x for all , then Proposition 18. Let ⪷ be a partial order on and let be fuzzy-valued function with for all such that is a local max point of for all and Assumption 2 is satisfied. Then there exist two points with and such that, for ,
- (1)
either minimizes and maximizes for all ,
- (2)
or maximizes and minimizes for all .
Equivalently,
- (i)
either maximizes and maximizes , for all ,
- (ii)
or maximizes and maximizes for all . Furthermore, interval is the local efficient frontier of Definition 17. In particular, if and are internal to the local convexity region and , are differentiable at x for all , then
Developing the same examples (
39) and (
40),
Figure 4 and
Figure 5 show the Efficient Regions at two specific minimum and maximum points (both level-wise and fuzzy cases are indicated).
More generally,
Figure 6 and
Figure 7 summarize the efficient regions for all maximum and minimum points.
The last part of the section is devoted to an attempt to see how the property of local extreme for a point (minimum) or (maximum) is connected to the left and/or right LgH-derivatives or to the LgH-derivative when they assume the same value. To reach the goal, we introduce the following Fermat-like property:
Proposition 19. Let be LgH-differentiable at and ⪷ be a partial order on . If is a lattice extremum for F (a lattice-min or a lattice-max point), then .
Proposition 20. Let , and ⪷ be a partial order on . Suppose that F has left and right LgH-derivatives at (if or , we consider only the right or the left LgH-derivatives, respectively):
- (1.a)
If is a lattice minimum point for F, then and ;
- (1.b)
If is a lattice maximum point for F, then and .
Proposition 21. Let be LgH-differentiable at and be a partial order on .
- (i)
If is a best-minimum point for F, then .
- (ii)
If is a best-maximum point for F, then .
Notation: It is trivial to note that Proposition 21 is not valid for ⪷ of partial order on .
Analogously to the well-known situation for single-valued functions, the following are sufficient conditions based on the “sign” of the left and right LgH-derivatives.
Proposition 22. Let , and ⪷ be a partial order on and . Suppose that F has left and right LgH-derivatives at (if or we consider only the right or the left LgH-derivatives, respectively):
- (a)
If and , then is a best minimum point for F;
- (b)
If and , then is a best maximum point for F.
Finally, it is possible to argue that the sign of the left and right LgH-derivatives established conditions for local extremes.