Next Article in Journal
Technique for Enhancing the Chaotic Characteristics of Chaotic Maps Using Delayed Coupling and Its Application in Image Encryption
Previous Article in Journal
Identification and Classification of Multi-Attribute Decision-Making Based on Complex Intuitionistic Fuzzy Frank Aggregation Operators
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

A Model in Which Well-Orderings of the Reals First Appear at a Given Projective Level, Part III—The Case of Second-Order PA

by
Vladimir Kanovei
*,† and
Vassily Lyubetsky
*,†
Kharkevich Institute for Information Transmission Problems, 127051 Moscow, Russia
*
Authors to whom correspondence should be addressed.
These authors contributed equally to this work.
Mathematics 2023, 11(15), 3294; https://doi.org/10.3390/math11153294
Submission received: 20 June 2023 / Revised: 22 July 2023 / Accepted: 24 July 2023 / Published: 26 July 2023
(This article belongs to the Section Mathematics and Computer Science)

Abstract

:
A model of set theory ZFC is defined in our recent research, in which, for a given n 3 , ( A n ) there exists a good lightface Δ n 1 well-ordering of the reals, but ( B n ) no well-orderings of the reals (not necessarily good) exist in the previous class Δ n 1 1 . Therefore, the conjunction ( A n ) ( B n ) is consistent, modulo the consistency of ZFC itself. In this paper, we significantly clarify and strengthen this result. We prove the consistency of the conjunction ( A n ) ( B n ) for any given n 3 on the basis of the consistency of PA 2 , second-order Peano arithmetic, which is a much weaker assumption than the consistency of ZFC used in the earlier result. This is a new result that may lead to further progress in studies of the projective hierarchy.

1. Introduction

The following theorem, devoted to the problem of “effective” well-orderability of the real line R , was established in our recent paper [1].
Theorem 1
(= Theorem 1 in [1]). Let n 3 . There is a generic extension of L , in which:
( A n )
t h e r e   i s   a   Δ n 1 - good well-ordering of the set R   o f   a l l   r e a l s ,   o f   l e n g t h ω1;
( B n )
t h e r e   a r e   n o   Δ n 1 1 well- o r d e r i n g s   o f   R ,   o f   a n y   k i n d , i . e . , n o t   n e c e s s a r i l y   g o o d .
Here Δ n 1 are lightface projective classes. We refer to [1] for introductory material and references to earlier research on this topic. Generally we refer to Moschovakis’ monograph [2] in matters of modern notation in descriptive set theory. We recall that a Δ n 1 -good well-ordering is any Δ n 1 well-ordering ≼ such that the class Δ n 1 is closed under ≼-bounded quantification, so that if P ( y , x ) is a binary Δ n 1 relation on the reals, then the relations
Q ( z , x ) : = y x P ( z , y ) and R ( z , x ) : = y x P ( z , y )
belong to Δ n 1 as well. Gödel [3] proved that the axiom of constructibility V = L implies the existence of a Δ 2 1 -good well-ordering of R , and such well-orderings are behind some crucial applications of constructibility in set theory, see Section 5A in [2].
The goal of this paper is to reprove Theorem 1 in the context of second-order Peano arithmetic PA 2 . This theory governs the interrelations between the natural numbers and sets of natural numbers, and is widely assumed to lay down working foundations for essential parts of modern mathematics, see, e.g., Simpson [4]. The specific version PA 2 of second-order Peano arithmetic considered here contains Peano’s axioms for numbers, the axioms of Induction and Extensionality, and the Comprehension and Countable Choice schemata resp. CA and AC ω , see Section 8 for details.
Note that claims ( A n ) and ( B n ) of Theorem 1 can be adequately presented by certain formulas of the language of PA 2 , based on suitable universal formulas for classes Σ n 1 and Σ n 1 1 . Therefore, for any given n 3 , the conjunction ( A n )  ∧  ( B n ) is essentially a formula, say Φ n , of the language of PA 2 , and the theorem implies that Φ n is consistent with ZFC , and, hence, with PA 2 as well. Thus, it becomes a natural problem to establish the consistency result of Theorem 1 on the base of the PA 2 tools rather than (much stronger) ZFC tools. This problem is solved by the next theorem, which is the main result of this paper.
Theorem 2.
Let n 3 . Assuming that PA 2 is consistent, the conjunction of ( A n ) and ( B n ) of Theorem 1 is consistent with PA 2 .

2. Outline of the Proof

Given n 3 as in Theorem 1, a generic extension of L was defined in [1], in which ( A n ) and ( B n ) of Theorem 1 hold. This model involves a product forcing notion P L , defined in L , the constructible universe, as the finite support product of 1 -many forcing notions similar to Jensen’s “minimal Π 2 1 singleton” forcing as in [5]. This forcing notion P depends on the index n in Theorems 1 and 2, of course, but we suppress this dependence, assuming that n 3 is fixed once and for all.
The method of finite-support products of Jensen’s forcing, which we owe to Enayat [6], has brought several results similar to Theorem 1 in our recent papers. Some of them are mentioned in [1]. Some other results are as follows.
  • A model of ZFC in [7] with a Groszek–Laver pair (see [8]), which consists of two OD-undistinguishable E 0 classes X Y , whose union X Y is a Π 2 1 set.
  • A model of ZFC in [9] in which, for a given n 3 , Δ n 1 reals = constructible reals.
  • Models in [10] with counterexamples to the separation theorem for both Σ 3 1 and Π 3 1 .
  • A model of ZFC in [11] in which the full basis theorem holds for the effective projective hierarchy but there is no Σ 1 well-ordering of the reals.
We may also mention a very recent paper [12] related to this research line.
The factors of the product forcing P L in [1] are forcing notions that consist of perfect trees in 2 < ω . Therefore, P L ω 1 , and, in fact, P is a definable class in L ω 1 , and a CCC forcing. (We recall that a partially ordered set or class P satisfies CCC, or the countable chain condition, if every antichain A P is at most countable.) Thus, we may think about treating P as a class-forcing over L ω 1 . Yet, there is a serious obstacle noted in Section 31 in [1]: the construction of P involves a ω 1 -sequence, which goes on in L ω 2 rather than L ω 1 . We overcome this difficulty in this paper. We make use of a recent construction of definable-⋄ sequences by Enayat and Hamkins [13], to obtain a definable- ω 1 sequence inside L ω 1 (Theorem 4), or rather by means of
ZFC lc : = ZFC + all sets are constructible and countable ,
a theory known to be equiconsistent with PA 2 and to have L ω 1 (more exactly, L ω 1 L ) as a natural model. The upper minus stands for the absence of the Power Sets axiom, whereas l and c in the lower index stand for the constructibility ( L ) and countability.
Adapting the whole structure of the proof of Theorem 1 in [1], we introduce P here as a definable class forcing in ZFC lc satisfying the definable CCC. Then we use the class forcing theory of S. D. Friedman [14,15], developed by Antos and Gitman [16] to be applicable over ZFC , and check that P -generic extensions of a ZFC lc universe satisfy ( A n )  ∧  ( B n ) above.
The final reduction to PA 2 will be based on the equiconsistency of PA 2 , ZFC , and ZFC lc , see Section 8. This is how the proof of Theorem 2 is organized in this paper. We will freely use the notation and results of the previous article [1] in the course of the proof.

3. On Power-Less Set Theory

Recall that HC is the set of all hereditarily countable sets. Thus, X HC if the transitive closure TC ( X ) is at most countable. Note that HC = L ω 1 under V = L .
We recall that ZFC is a subtheory of ZFC , obtained as follows:
(a)
We exclude the Power Set axiom PS;
(b)
The well-orderability axiom WA, which claims that every set can be well-ordered, is substituted for the usual set-theoretic Axiom of Choice AC of ZFC;
(c)
The Separation schema is preserved, but the Replacement schema (which happens to be not sufficiently strong in the absence of PS) is substituted with the Collection schema: X Y x X y Φ ( x , y ) y Y Φ ( x , y ) .
A comprehensive account of main features of ZFC is given in, e.g., [16,17].
We may note that if HC L holds, then the set L ω 1 = HC is a natural model of the theory ZFC lc defined by (1) above. This motivates the following definition.
Definition 1.
The ground set universe of ZFC lc (not including classes) is denoted by L ω 1 . Accordingly, ω 1 will be the collection (a proper class) of all ordinals in L ω 1 .
Remark 1.
Arguing in ZFC lc , we will often consider (definable) proper classes because they will play a more essential role than is common in ZFC. We will also consider such things as class-size collections of proper classes, e.g., class-long sequences X α α < ω 1 of proper classes X α , with the understanding that the real thing considered in this case is some (definable) class Y ω 1 × L ω 1 whose slices Y α = { x : α , x Y } are equal to the given classes X α .

4. Some Preliminary Constructions in Power-Less Set Theory

The construction of the forcing notion P P for the proof of Theorem 1 in [1] goes on in the universe L ω 1 of ZFC lc and involves the following principal elements.
(1)
The collection PT of all perfect trees T 2 < ω .
Arboreal forcings, i.e., those P PT satisfying s T P T s P , in § 3 of [1].
In the context of ZFC lc , such a P can be either a set or a (definable) proper class. Let AF be the class of all arboreal forcings P which are sets.
(2)
By § 3 of [1], an arboreal forcing P is:
-
regular, if, for any S , T P , the intersection [ S ] [ T ] of corresponding perfect sets [ S ] , [ T ] is clopen in [ S ] or in [ T ] ;
-
special, if there is a finite or countable antichain A P such that P = { T s : s T A } — the antichain A is unique and P is countable in this case.
(3)
The class MT of all multitrees, i.e., maps p : | p | PT , such that | p | ω 1 is finite.
(4)
Multiforcings, i.e., maps π : | π | { arboreal forcings } , such that | π | ω 1 , in § 6 of [1]. A multiforcing π is:
-
small, in case both | π | and each forcing π ( ξ ) , ξ | π | , are (countable) sets rather than proper classes, or equivalently (in ZFC lc ), π itself is a set;
-
special, in case | π | is countable and each π ( ξ ) is special, as in (2);
-
regular, in case all π ( ξ ) are regular, as in (2).
All special multiforcings are small and regular—hence, sets in ZFC lc . Non-small multiforcings are proper classes, of course. See Remark 1.
(5)
If π is a multiforcing then MT ( π ) is a collection of all π -multitrees p , i.e., those satisfying | p | | π | and p ( ξ ) π ( ξ ) for all ξ | p | . Clearly, both MT ( π ) and π itself are just different representations of the finite-support product ξ | π | π ( ξ ) , see § 6 of [1]. If π is a set (equivalently, a small multiforcing), then MT ( π ) is a set as well.
(6)
The collection MFsp of all special (therefore small) multiforcings π , i.e., such that | π | ω 1 is at most countable and if α | π | , then π ( α ) is special in § 16 of [1].
(7)
The operation cw of component-wise union of multiforcings, § 6 of [1].
(8)
The relation of refinement of multiforcings, § 7 of [1]. The relation π D ϙ (sealing refinement, § 8 of [1]) means that π ϙ and D MT ( π ) is pre-dense in MT ( ( π cw ϙ ) ) . Some related notions such as p (types of sealing refinements) are introduced in § § 9–13 of [1], and summarized in the common sealing refinement relation π M ϙ in § 14 of [1], meaning that π D ϙ holds for all D dense in MT ( π ) , which either belong to M or are coded in some way by elements of M.
(9)
For any ordinal, α ω 1 — the collection MF α of all -increasing sequences π of special multiforcings, of length lh ( π ) = α , in § 16 of [1]. If π MF α , then the componentwise union cw π = γ < α π ( γ ) is a multiforcing, and cw π a set in case α < ω 1 and a proper class in case α = ω 1 .
(10)
The collection MF = α < ω 1 MF α of all -increasing sequences of special multiforcings, of countable transfinite length. The relation π ϙ on MF means that a sequence ϙ is a proper extension of π . If M is any set, then π M ϙ means that π ϙ , and in addition π M ϙ ( λ ) , where λ = lh ( π ) and π = cw π . See § 16 of [1].
Of those, perfect trees, special arboreal forcings, multitrees, special multiforcings, sequences in MF are pretty legitimate objects (sets) in ZFC lc . If π is a special multiforcing then MT ( π ) (all π -multitrees as in (5)) is a set in ZFC lc . On the other hand, collections PT, AF, MFsp, MF , as well as any sequence in MF ω 1 , and similar uncountable objects are definable classes in ZFC lc , and accordingly so that all associated results in Sections 3–14 and 16 in [1] remain true in ZFC lc , with the understanding that some objects are proper classes, of course. In particular, the following results are true.
Theorem 3
(Theorem 4 in [1]). In ZFC lc , if π is a small regular multiforcing and M a countable set, then there is a special multiforcing ϙ satisfying | π | = | ϙ | and π M ϙ .
Lemma 1
(Lemma 21 in [1]). In ZFC lc , assume that M is any (countable) set. Then:
 (i) 
If κ < λ < ω 1 and π MF κ , then there exists a sequence ϙ MF λ such that π M ϙ ;
 (ii) 
If κ < λ ω 1 , π MF κ , ϙ MF λ , π M ϙ , and a set D M is open dense in MT ( π ) , then cw π D ϙ κ = κ α < λ cw ϙ ( α ) , so that D is pre-dense in MT ( ϙ ) .
Lemma 2
(Lemma 22 in [1]). In ZFC lc , the following ternary relation belongs to the class Δ 1 = Δ 1 L ω 1 : “ π , ϙ MF M L ω 1 π M ϙ ”.
Now we approach the construction of the forcing notion P P in § § 18–20 of [1]. The main issue with this construction is that it involves a ω 1 -sequence in [1]. The ZFC construction of such a sequence (as, e.g., in [18]) formally can be maintained as a proper class in ZFC lc . However, unfortunately, the proof of the ω 1 -property does not go through in ZFC lc because its ZFC proof involves ordinals beyond ω 1 , and hence, does not directly translate to the ZFC lc setup. The next section provides an appropriate substitution.

5. Definable ω 1 Sequence by Means of Power-Less Set Theory

It is established in a recent paper (Theorem 4.1 in [13]) that, under V = L , there is an Ord-long class-sequence satisfying a ⋄-property for all definable classes. Inspired by this result, we prove the following theorem using nearly the same method:
Theorem 4
( ZFC lc ). There is a Δ 1 sequence S α α < ω 1 of sets S α α such that: for any definable (with parameters) classes S , C ω 1 , if C is club in ω 1 , then S α = S α for some α C .
Any sequence of sets S α as in the theorem can be seen as guessing sufficiently often initial segments S α of any definable S ω 1 within any definable club (i.e., closed unbounded) C ω 1 . This is the best possible result in ZFC lc of such kind. But ZFC with the axiom of constructibility, a stronger result is possible, in which the guessing property holds for arbitrary (not necessarily definable) sets S , C ω 1 . This is basically the fundamental “diamond” theorem ω 1 of Jensen, see, e.g., Theorem 13.21 in [18].
We use the standard notation Σ n X , Π n X , Δ n X (slanted lightface Σ , Π , Δ ) for classes of lightface definability over a given transitive set X, e.g., X = L ω 1 (no parameters allowed), and Σ n X , Π n X , Δ n X for boldface definability in X (parameters from X allowed). Simply Σ n means Σ n definability in the whole universe, i.e., L ω 1 when arguing under ZFC lc , and Π n , Δ n is understood similarly. We call Σ n , Π n , Δ n and the like types rather than classes in this paper since the word ‘class’ has a special technical meaning in the context of ZFC lc , that is, a definable collection of sets.
Proof. 
We argue under ZFC lc . As the axiom of constructibility is assumed by ZFC lc , let L be the Gödel well-ordering of the universe, of definability type Δ 1 . Define the sets S α by transfinite recursion. Suppose that S α has been defined for all α < ϑ . We put S ϑ = unless
(*)
ϑ is a limit ordinal, and there is a set S ϑ and a club (closed unbounded set) C ϑ , with both S and C definable (allowing parameters) in the structure L ϑ = L ϑ ; .
If (*) holds, then pick the least such pair S , C , minimizing first on the Gödel codes of the defining formulas of S and C , and then, using the well-order L L ϑ , on the parameters used in the definitions. For this minimal pair, let S ϑ = S . This completes the inductive definition. The definition makes use of the truth predicate for the structure L ϑ ; .
We claim that the sequence S α α < ω 1 is as required. First of all, the truth predicate is known to be Δ 1 , and so is the restricted order L L ϑ , with ϑ as the only parameter. It routinely follows that the class sequence S α α < ω 1 is Δ 1 in the universe of ZFC lc .
Further, suppose towards the contrary that S , C ω 1 are counterexamples, so that C is a club in ω 1 , both S , C are classes definable by specific formulas resp. σ ( · ) , κ ( · ) (with some parameters not explicitly indicated), so that
C = { γ < ω 1 : κ ( γ ) } , S = { γ < ω 1 : σ ( γ ) } ,
and S α S α for all α < ω 1 .
We may assume, without loss of generality, that these formulas are chosen so as to be minimal in the sense of the construction, so that, successively, their Gödel codes are as small as possible, and the the parameters involved form a L -minimal tuple, respectively.
Let m be a sufficiently large natural number, larger than the Gödel codes of the formulas σ ( · ) , κ ( · ) and their subformulas, and large enough so that the minimality condition we just formulated is expressible by a Σ m formula. Let ϑ be any limit ordinal such that all the parameters used in the definitions belong to L ϑ , and such that L ϑ is an elementary submodel of the whole universe L ω 1 of the theory ZFC lc considered, w.r.t. all Σ m formulas. It follows that the restrictions L L ϑ , and also S L ϑ and C L ϑ are definable in L ϑ by the same definitions and parameters as their counterparts in L ω 1 .
Therefore, C ϑ is club in L ϑ , and S ϑ , C ϑ form a minimal pair using those definitions S α S α for any α C ϑ . Thus, by the definition of S ϑ , it follows that S ϑ = S ϑ . Since C ϑ is unbounded in ϑ and C is closed, it follows that ϑ C , and so S ϑ = S ϑ contradicts our assumption about S and C. So there are no such counterexample classes, and we have finished. □
Following § 18 in [1], we proceed to the next definition.
Definition 2.
( ZFC lc ). We fix a sequence S α α < ω 1 given by Lemma 4.
As usual, let L be the Gödel Δ 1 well-ordering of the set universe L ω 1 under ZFC lc .
We let c α = α th element of L ω 1 in the sense of L ; thus, L ω 1 = { c α : α < ω 1 } .
If Z L ω 1 and α < ω 1 , then let ( Z ) < α = { c ξ Z : ξ < α } .
If α < ω 1 then let A α = { c ξ : ξ S α } . Then, A α α < ω 1 is still a Δ 1 sequence.
Let A α n = { a : n , a A α } .
Let M ( α ) = { A α n : n < ω } . Then, M ( α ) α < ω 1 is still a Δ 1 sequence.

6. The Key Sequence and Key Forcing Notion

The next theorem (Theorem 5) is a crucial step towards the construction of the forcing notion that will prove Theorem 2. The theorem is a close version of Theorem 7 in [1]. The construction employs some ideas related to definable generic transfinite constructions, and it will go on by a transfinite inductive definition of a sequence MF ω 1 in L ω 1 from countable subsequences. The result can be viewed as a maximal branch in MF , generic with respect to all sets of a given complexity.
Definition 3.
(in ZFC lc ). From now on, a number n 3 as in Theorem 2, is fixed.
A sequence π MF blocks a set or class W MF , if either π belongs to W (a positive block) or no sequence ϙ W MF extends π (a negative block).
Any sequence = α α < ω 1 MF ω 1 (that is, a definable proper class), satisfying the following four conditions (A)–(D) for this n, will be called a key sequence:
 (A) 
The set | | = α < κ | ( α ) | is equal to ω 1 .
 (B) 
Every γ < ω 1 is a crucial ordinal for , so that the relation ( α < γ cw α ) M ( γ ) γ holds, where M ( γ ) is introduced by Definition 2 and M by (8) of Section 4.
 (C) 
If in fact n 4 and W MF is a boldface Σ n 3 class (a definition with parameters), then there exists an ordinal γ < ω 1 such that the subsequence γ  blocks W—so that either γ W , or there is no sequence ϙ W extending γ .
 (D) 
The sequence belongs to the definability type Δ n 2 in L ω 1 .
Theorem 5
( ZFC lc ). There exists a key sequence = α α < ω 1 MF ω 1 .
Proof 
(sketch). Argue under ZFC lc , with n 3 fixed, and strictly follow the proof of Theorem 7 in [1], with Theorem 3 and Lemmas 1 and 2 as the principal references. □
Definition 4
( ZFC lc ). From now on, we fix a key sequence  = α α < ω 1 MF ω 1 , given by Theorem 5 for the number n 3 fixed by Definition 3. It satisfies (A)–(D) of Definition 3. We call this fixed L the key sequence.
Based on Definition 4, we introduce some derived notions.
Definition 5
( ZFC lc ). Using the key sequence = α α < ω 1 , we define the regular multiforcing = α < ω 1 cw α , and the forcing notion P P = MT ( ) = MT ( ) .
We will call the key multiforcing below. Technically, is a class-long sequence of proper classes; see Remark 1. Accordingly, P P = MT ( ) will be our key forcing notion; technically, a definable proper subclass of the class MT of all multitrees. The following theorem presents the principal CCC property of P P in the ground universe L ω 1 of ZFC lc .
Theorem 6
( ZFC lc , Theorem 7 in [1]). The forcing notion P P satisfies countable chain condition CCC. Therefore, P P -generic extensions of L preserve cardinals.

7. Forcing Method over Power-Less Set Theory and the Key Model

The forcing engine does not necessarily work in ZFC lc for an arbitrary class-size forcing notion. But there is a type of forcing notions that admits adequate treatment of forcing, similar to the standard ZFC case.
Definition 6
(S. D. Friedman, see [14,16]). A forcing notion (a partially ordered definable class) P = P ; is pre-tame if for every class sequence D x x a of dense classes D x P , parametrized by elements of a set a (so that D = { x , z : x a z D x } is a definable class), and every condition p P , there is a condition q p and a sequence d x x a of subsets of P such that each d x D x is pre-dense below q in P.
Theorem 7
(S. D. Friedman, see [14,16]). In ZFC , let P = P ; be a pre-tame class-forcing notion. Then P preserves ZFC and satisfies the main forcing principles including the truth—forcing and forcing definability theorems.
We recall that our key forcing P P , introduced by Definition 5, is a class forcing, satisfying CCC by Theorem 6. Therefore, P P is pre-tame under ZFC lc , as so obviously is any CCC forcing. We conclude that Theorem 7 is applicable, and, hence, usual forcing theorems are valid for P P -generic extensions of L ω 1 , the ZFC lc set universe. This justifies all forcing results in Chapters III and IV of [1], including Theorems 9 and 13 there, on the basis of ZFC lc . This argument validates the following theorem:
Theorem 8
( ZFC lc , Theorems 9 and 13 in [1]). Let n 3  (see Definition 3 on n ). Any P P -generic extension of L ω 1 , the ZFC lc universe of discourse, is still a model of ZFC , in which statements ( A n ) and ( B n ) of Theorem 1 hold for the index n .
In other words, any P P -generic extension of L ω 1 , the ZFC lc universe of discourse, is still a model of ZFC and a model of statements ( A n ) and ( B n ) of Theorem 1. The following is a usual metamathematical corollary.
Corollary 1.
If ZFC lc is consistent, then so is the theory ZFC + ( A n ) ( B n ) of Theorem 1”.

8. Reduction to Second-Order Peano Arithmetic

Following [4,19,20] the second order Peano arithmetic PA 2 is a theory in the language L ( PA 2 ) with two sorts of variables—for natural numbers and for sets of them. We use j , k , m , n for variables over ω and x , y , z for variables over P ( ω ) , reserving capital letters for subsets of P ( ω ) and other sets. The axioms are as follows in (1)–(5):
(1)
Peano’s axioms for numbers.
(2)
Induction as one sentence: x 0 x n ( n x n + 1 x ) n ( n x ) .
(3)
Extensionality for sets of natural numbers.
(4)
The Comprehension schema CA: x k ( k x Φ ( k ) ) , for every formula Φ in which x does not occur, and in Φ, we allow parameters—free variables other than k.
(5)
The schema AC ω of Countable Choice: k x Φ ( k , x ) x k Φ ( k , ( x ) k ) ) , for every formula Φ with parameters allowed, where ( x ) k = { j : 2 k ( 2 j + 1 ) 1 x } .
The theory PA 2 is also known as A 2 (see, e.g., an early survey [19]), az Z 2 (in [21] or elsewhere). See also [22]. We recall that the consistency of PA 2 is the blanket assumption in Theorem 2. Yet, we can use the following equiconsistency result:
Theorem 9.
Theories PA 2 and ZFC lc are equiconsistent.
Proof. 
The theorem has been a well-known fact for some time, see, e.g., Theorem 5.25 in [19]. A rather natural way of proof is as follows.
 Step 1. 
Theory ZFC + all sets are countable is interpreted in PA 2 by the tree interpretation described in [19], §5, especially Theorem 5.11, or in [4], Definition VII.3.10 ff. Kreisel [20], VI(a)(ii), attributed this interpretation to the type of “crude” results.
 Step 2. 
Arguing in ZFC + all sets are countable , we define the transitive class L of all constructible sets, which models ZFC + all sets are constructible .
 Step 3. 
We argue in ZFC + all sets are constructible . If every ordinal is countable, then immediately all sets are countable, that is, we have ZFC lc . If there exist uncountable ordinals, then let ω 1 be the least of them. Then, L ω 1 is a transitive set which models ZFC lc .
We conclude from Steps 1–3 that PA 2 and ZFC Lc are equiconsistent. □
Combining Theorems 9 and 8, we accomplish the proof of Theorem 2.

9. Conclusions and Problems

In this study, the method of definable ω 1 sequences was employed to the construction of a model in which, for a given n 3 , there is a Δ n 1 -good well-ordering of the reals, but no well-orderings of the reals exist in the class Δ n 1 1 at the preceding level of the hierarchy, on the basis essentially of the second-order Peano arithmetic PA 2 . This considerably strengthens and extends our earlier results, in which such a model was defined on the basis of a much stronger theory ZFC typically assumed in for independence results by the forcing method. This is a new result and a valuable improvement upon our earlier results in [1]. The technique developed in this paper may lead to further progress in studies of different aspects of the projective hierarchy. We hope that this study will contribute to the following fundamental problem by S. D. Friedman: find a model for a given n, in which all Σ n 1 sets of reals are Lebesgue measurable and have the Baire and perfect set properties, and, at the same time, there exists a Δ n + 1 1 well-ordering of the reals, [14] (p. 209) and [15] (p. 602).
From our study, it is concluded that the technique of definable -sequences will lead to similar consistency and independence results on the basis of the consistency of PA 2 .
Some problems that arise from our study are mentioned in § 32 in [1]. We adjoin the following problem specific to the research line of this article.
Problem 1.
Reprove the consistency result in [9], related to the equality “ Δ n 1 reals = constructible reals” for any given n 3 , on the basis of the consistency of theory PA 2 .

Author Contributions

Conceptualization, V.K. and V.L.; methodology, V.K. and V.L.; validation, V.K.; formal analysis, V.K. and V.L.; investigation, V.K. and V.L.; writing original draft preparation, V.K.; writing review and editing, V.K. and V.L.; project administration, V.L.; funding acquisition, V.L. All authors have read and agreed to the published version of the manuscript.

Funding

This research was partially supported by Russian Foundation for Basic Research RFBR grant number 20-01-00670.

Institutional Review Board Statement

Not applicable.

Informed Consent Statement

Not applicable.

Data Availability Statement

The study did not report any data.

Acknowledgments

We are thankful to Victoria Gitman for pointing out the paper [13], critically important for replacing the usual principle ω 1 with the definable- ω 1 as in Theorem 4 above. We thank the anonymous reviewers for their thorough review and highly appreciate the comments and suggestions, which significantly contributed to improving the quality of the publication.

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

References

  1. Kanovei, V.; Lyubetsky, V. A model in which wellorderings of the reals first appear at a given projective level, part II. Mathematics 2023, 11, 2517. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  2. Moschovakis, Y.N. Descriptive Set Theory; Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics; North-Holland: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 1980; Volume 100, pp. XII + 637. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  3. Gödel, K. The Consistency of the Continuum Hypothesis; Annals of Mathematics Studies; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1940; Volume 3. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  4. Simpson, S.G. Subsystems of Second Order Arithmetic, 2nd ed.; Perspectives in Logic; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK; ASL: Urbana, IL, USA, 2009; pp. xvi + 444. [Google Scholar]
  5. Jensen, R. Definable sets of minimal degree. In Proceedings of the International Colloquium on Mathematical Logic and Foundations of Set Theory, Jerusalem, Israel, 11–14 November 1968; Bar-Hillel, Y., Ed.; Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics. North-Holland: Amsterdam, The Netherlands; London, UK, 1970; Volume 59, pp. 122–128. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  6. Enayat, A. On the Leibniz—Mycielski axiom in set theory. Fundam. Math. 2004, 181, 215–231. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  7. Golshani, M.; Kanovei, V.; Lyubetsky, V. A Groszek—Laver pair of undistinguishable E0 classes. Math. Log. Q. 2017, 63, 19–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  8. Groszek, M.; Laver, R. Finite groups of OD-conjugates. Period. Math. Hung. 1987, 18, 87–97. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  9. Kanovei, V.; Lyubetsky, V. On the Δ n 1 problem of Harvey Friedman. Mathematics 2020, 8, 1477. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  10. Kanovei, V.; Lyubetsky, V. Counterexamples to countable-section Π 2 1 uniformization and Π 3 1 separation. Ann. Pure Appl. Log. 2016, 167, 262–283. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  11. Kanovei, V.; Lyubetsky, V. The full basis theorem does not imply analytic wellordering. Ann. Pure Appl. Log. 2021, 172, 102929. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  12. Wansner, L.; Wontner, N.J.H. Descriptive choice principles and how to separate them. arXiv 2023, arXiv:2307.09837. [Google Scholar]
  13. Enayat, A.; Hamkins, J.D. ZFC proves that the class of ordinals is not weakly compact for definable classes. J. Symb. Log. 2018, 83, 146–164. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  14. Friedman, S.D. Fine Structure and Class Forcing; De Gruyter Series in Logic and Its Applications; de Gruyter: Berlin, Germany, 2000; Volume 3, pp. x + 221. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  15. Friedman, S.D. Constructibility and class forcing. In Handbook of Set Theory; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2010; pp. 557–604. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  16. Antos, C.; Gitman, V. Modern Class Forcing. In Research Trends in Contemporary Logic; Daghighi, A., Rezus, A., Pourmahdian, M., Gabbay, D., Fitting, M., Eds.; College Publications: Suwanee, GA, USA, 2023; Available online: https://philpapers.org/go.pl?aid=ANTMCF (accessed on 1 July 2023).
  17. Gitman, V.; Hamkins, J.D.; Johnstone, T.A. What is the theory ZFC without power set? Math. Log. Q. 2016, 62, 391–406. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  18. Jech, T. Set Theory; The Third Millennium Revised and Expanded ed.; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany; New York, NY, USA, 2003; pp. xiii + 769. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  19. Apt, K.R.; Marek, W. Second order arithmetic and related topics. Ann. Math. Log. 1974, 6, 177–229. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  20. Kreisel, G. A survey of proof theory. J. Symb. Log. 1968, 33, 321–388. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  21. Schindler, T. A disquotational theory of truth as strong as Z 2 . J. Philos. Log. 2015, 44, 395–410. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  22. Friedman, H. On the necessary use of abstract set theory. Adv. Math. 1981, 41, 209–280. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Kanovei, V.; Lyubetsky, V. A Model in Which Well-Orderings of the Reals First Appear at a Given Projective Level, Part III—The Case of Second-Order PA. Mathematics 2023, 11, 3294. https://doi.org/10.3390/math11153294

AMA Style

Kanovei V, Lyubetsky V. A Model in Which Well-Orderings of the Reals First Appear at a Given Projective Level, Part III—The Case of Second-Order PA. Mathematics. 2023; 11(15):3294. https://doi.org/10.3390/math11153294

Chicago/Turabian Style

Kanovei, Vladimir, and Vassily Lyubetsky. 2023. "A Model in Which Well-Orderings of the Reals First Appear at a Given Projective Level, Part III—The Case of Second-Order PA" Mathematics 11, no. 15: 3294. https://doi.org/10.3390/math11153294

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop