Next Article in Journal
AdS/CFT in Fractional Dimension and Higher-Spins at One Loop
Previous Article in Journal / Special Issue
The First Detection of Gravitational Waves
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

Do We Live in the Best of All Possible Worlds? The Fine-Tuning of the Constants of Nature

Deutsches Elektronen-Synchrotron DESY, Platanenallee 6, 15738 Zeuthen, Germany
Universe 2017, 3(3), 60; https://doi.org/10.3390/universe3030060
Submission received: 14 June 2017 / Revised: 20 July 2017 / Accepted: 26 July 2017 / Published: 1 August 2017
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Varying Constants and Fundamental Cosmology)

Abstract

:
Our existence depends on a variety of constants which appear to be extremely fine-tuned to allow for the existence of life as we know it. These include the number of spatial dimensions, the strengths of the forces, the masses of the particles, the composition of the Universe, and others. On the occasion of the 300th anniversary of the death of G.W. Leibniz, we discuss the question of whether we live in the “Best of all possible Worlds”. The hypothesis of a multiverse could explain the mysterious fine tuning of so many fundamental quantities. Anthropic arguments are critically reviewed.

1. The Best of all Worlds—From Leibniz to Einstein

The Electress of Brandenburg and later Queen of Prussia Sophie Charlotte was a lifelong friend to Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, who died 300 years ago. They inspired the king to create the Kurfürstlich Brandenburgische Societät der Wissenschaften zu Berlin in 1700. Leibniz became the first lifetime President of this academy renamed in 1701 to Royal Prussian Society of Sciences and known today as Berlin-Brandenburgische Akademie der Wissenschaften.
Since Leibniz tended to never finish his many activities and to spread his ideas over thousands of loose notes, the Queen asked him to summarize his world view in a popular pamphlet. As he was very much indebted to her he completed in 1710 the only coherent text published during his lifetime, his “Essays on the Goodness of God, the Freedom of Man and the Origin of Evil” [1,2].
In this treatise, he tried what one might call the impossible: to unify and harmonise science, metaphysics, and theology. In § 8 of its first part he writes: “this supreme wisdom, united to a goodness that is no less infinite, cannot but have chosen the best … if there were not the best among all possible worlds, God would not have produced any ... there is an infinitude of possible worlds among which God must have chosen the best, since he does nothing without acting in accordance with supreme reason ...” [2]. The important point for modern science is that Leibniz assumes the existence of a multitude of possible worlds, although by this he meant imaginary moral but not real physical worlds which are the subject of this text.
In modern physics, Weinberg [3] quoted Einstein [4], who in a paper on his attempts to create a unified theory of interactions wrote: “Roughly but truthfully, one might say: we not only want to understand how nature works..., but we are also after the perhaps utopian and presumptuous goal of understanding why nature is the way it is and not otherwise”. In the late thirties in a discussion with his assistant, Banesh Hoffmann asked a similar question: “When I am judging a theory, I ask myself whether, if I were God, I would have arranged the world in such a way” [5]. To Ernst Gabor Straus, his assistant from 1940 to 1948, Einstein made the famous remark: “What really interests me is whether God could have created the world any differently” [6]. This reiterates Leibniz’s question whether we live in the best of all worlds in the context of modern physics.

2. Had God a Choice?

An early observation of the fine-tuning of the fundamental cosmological parameters (Hubble and gravitational constants H0 and GN and mean density Ω of the Universe) was made by Dicke in 1961 [7]. If any of several fundamental physical constants were only slightly different, the Universe would be unlikely to lead to the formation of nuclear, atomic, or cosmic structures which allow for chemical elements, stellar burning, and finally, life.
We do not restrict our concept of life to carbon-based forms—an attitude called carbon chauvinism first by Sagan [8] in 1973 and also criticised by, e.g., Stenger [9]. In order to allow for the complexity of life, stellar evolution should however have had enough time to produce elements beyond primordial hydrogen and helium. Additionally, the subsequent formation of stable structures leading to life is governed by temperatures and time scales that do not allow life to form much before the first billion years of cosmic evolution1.
The Universe indeed appears to be extremely fine-tuned for life. We will illustrate this phenomenon by asking the question: “What if we change some of the constants of Nature?”, proceeding from the most general to more specific constants:
-
the dimensionality of the Universe
-
symmetries: the matter–antimatter asymmetry
-
the cosmic inventory: mean density, Hubble and cosmological constant, curvature
-
coupling constants
-
What if no Higgs? The masses of weak bosons, quarks, and the electron
Changing the dimensionality of the Universe or dropping the electroweak symmetry breaking in a world without the Higgs boson are not acts of fine-tuning but of a more fundamental tuning of the laws of Nature. We should also keep in mind that beyond fundamental constants like the strengths of the interactions, constants like those defining the cosmic inventory (such as the Hubble and the cosmological constant) are of environmental nature.
The amazing fine-tuning of nuclear processes visible in the deuterium bottleneck, the triple-alpha process of stellar burning, and nucleon–nucleon binding must be left for a separate discussion.

2.1. The Dimensionality of the Universe

A world with less than three dimensions was discussed by Barrow and Tipler [10,11] and Hawking [12]. In such a world, the digestive tract of any higher animal would separate it into disjoint upper and lower parts. Additionally, nerves and blood vessels would cross in two dimensions, and food absorption would have to proceed by breaking a one-dimensional boundary. This illustrates how dramatically processes can depend on the number of dimensions and topological issues.
The case of a world with more than three spatial dimensions was discussed by Ehrenfest in 1917 [13,14]. He considered the scattering of a small on a large mass. The probe particle is either trapped by the large mass—or it escapes to infinity. In more than three dimensions, no stable orbits of planets are possible! The same is true for electrons in classical atoms. In 1963, Tangherlini [15] showed that also in quantum mechanics in more than three spatial dimensions there are no stable atoms.

2.2. The Matter–Antimatter Asymmetry

In order to avoid additional fine-tuned constants of Nature, it is reasonable to assume that the Big Bang started from a totally neutral state where the sum of all additive charge-like quantum numbers was zero, hence from equal amounts of matter and antimatter. A matter–antimatter symmetric universe would, however, have rapidly annihilated to an empty light bubble, while we live today in a matter-dominated Universe. Related to the density of relic photons, the number of matter particles amounts only to about one in several billions. The matter content of our Universe hence originates from a tiny but decisive disbalance characterized by a small number. In a closed universe, a significantly larger matter density (more than one matter particle per one million relic photons) would have caused a rapid recollapse of the Universe without any chance for structure formation and life [16].

2.3. The Cosmic Inventory

As already observed by Dicke in 1961 [5], the evolution of the Universe is characterized by a delicate balance of its inventory, a balance between repulsion and attraction, between expansion and contraction. Since gravity is purely attractive, its action sums up throughout the whole Universe. The strength of this attraction is defined by the gravitational constant GN and by an environmental parameter, the density ΩM of (dark and baryonic) matter. The strength of the repulsion is defined by two parameters: the initial impetus of the Big Bang parameterized by the Hubble constant H0 and the cosmological constant Λ.
As determined from data of the PLANCK satellite combined with other cosmological observations, the total density of the Universe is Ωtot = ρ/ρcrit = 1.0002 ± 0.0026 and thus extremely close to its critical density ρcrit = 3H02/8πGN with a contribution from a curvature of the Universe of Ωk = 0.000 ± 0.005 [17]. However, the balance between the ingredients of the Universe is time-dependent. Any deviation from zero curvature after inflation is amplified by many orders of magnitude. Hence, a cosmic density fine-tuned to flatness today to less than a per mille must have been initially fine-tuned to tens of orders of magnitude.
Another mystery is the smallness of the cosmological constant. First of all, the Planck scale is the only natural energy scale of gravitation: mPl = (ħc/GN)1/2 = 1.2 × 1019 GeV/c2. Compared to this natural scale, the cosmological constant or dark energy density Λ is tiny:
Λ~(10 meV)4~(10−30 mPl)4 = 10−120 mPl4
The cosmological constant is also much smaller than expected from the vacuum expectation value of the Higgs field, which like the inflaton field or dark energy is an omnipresent scalar field:
‹Φ4›~mH4~(100 GeV)4~1052 Λ
As observed by Weinberg in 1987 there is an “anthropic” upper bound on the cosmological constant Λ. He argued “that in universes that do not recollapse, the only such bound on Λ is that it should not be so large as to prevent the formation of gravitationally bound states.” [18].

2.4. The Interactions and Their Strengths

Harnik et al. [19] discuss a universe without weak interactions that undergoes Big Bang nucleosynthesis, matter domination, structure formation, and star formation. They match their “Weakless Universe” to our Universe by simultaneously adjusting Standard Model and cosmological parameters. After multi-parameter adjustment, chemistry and nuclear physics are essentially unchanged. The apparent habitability of the Weakless Universe suggests that the anthropic principle does not determine the scale of electroweak symmetry breaking. They conclude that “the fine-tuning problems associated with the electroweak breaking scale and the cosmological constant appear to be qualitatively different from the perspective of obtaining a habitable universe”.
The strengths or coupling constants of the strong, weak, and electromagnetic interactions are fundamental parameters of the Standard Model of particle physics. They depend on energy and in Grand Unified Theories converge to a common value. Feynman once commented on the famous value of the fine structure constant α = e2/4π = 1/137 of quantum electrodynamics: “There is a most profound and beautiful question associated with the observed coupling constant, e—the amplitude for a real electron to emit or absorb a real photon… It’s one of the greatest damn mysteries of physics: a magic number that comes to us with no understanding by man. You might say the ‘hand of God’ wrote that number, and ‘we don’t know how He pushed his pencil’. We know what kind of a dance to do experimentally to measure this number very accurately, but we don’t know what kind of dance to do on the computer to make this number come out, without putting it in secretly!” [20].

2.5. The Fine-Tuning of Particle Masses. What If No Higgs?

2.5.1. Boson Masses

The carriers of the strong and electromagnetic interaction—the gluon and the photon—are massless. After spontaneous breaking of the electroweak symmetry through the Higgs field, the weak bosons acquire a mass which at low energies suppresses the weak interaction. Without this symmetry breaking (i.e., without a Higgs field), the weak bosons would be massless, and the weak interaction would be about as strong as the electromagnetic one. Star burning would not last billions of years, but rather resemble a nuclear explosion with no time left for the evolution of planetary systems and life.
On a more quantitative level, the mass mW = 80.4 GeV of the W bosons governs the fusion process pp→de+νe in stars. The cross-section of this fusion process which corresponds to inverse beta decay depends on the inverse of the fourth power of the weak boson mass: σ ~ (mW)−4. An increase of the weak boson mass by a factor of two would let the Sun and similar stars burn out within roughly a billion years. Such a rapid star burning would make the evolution of life as we know it almost impossible2.

2.5.2. Fermion Masses

The neutron is heavier than the proton, and is hence unstable: mn − mp = 1.3 MeV ≈ 1‰ mnucleon. This is due to the difference of ≈3 MeV between the masses of the down and up quark (this difference is partially compensated by the stronger electric repulsion of the additional up quark in the proton). In the second and third quark families, however, the up quarks are significantly heavier than the down quarks. So, one might ask: what if also in the first family the up quark would be heavier than the down quark?
Then, the proton would be heavier than the neutron and decay: p→ne+νe. The positron would subsequently annihilate with an electron e+e→γγ. The result would be a neutral universe consisting of photons, neutrons, and neutrinos without a chance for the formation of nuclei and atoms, and hence, life. If mu − md > 1 MeV, then mp − (mn + me) > 2.2 MeV = Ebd and the free energy of the proton decay would be larger than the binding energy Ebd of the deuteron. This would also make the deuteron unstable d→2ne+νe so that the decaying protons could not be trapped in deuterium and form helium like in our world3.
Since the Rydberg energy is R = 0.5α²me and the Bohr radius rB = 1/(αme), the mass of the electron governs the energy levels and distances of the atomic world. An increase of the electron mass to 5 MeV would have the same effect as making the up quark heavier than the down quark. Protons would decay, and we would end up in a neutral world with only photons, neutrons, and neutrinos left over.
In 1937, Paul Dirac in his large numbers hypothesis [21,22,23] related ratios of size scales in the Universe to the ratio of force scales. The dimensionless ratios amount to some forty orders of magnitude. So, the size of the universe is about 1040 times the classical electron radius, which is about the same ratio as the ratio of the electrical to the gravitational forces between a proton and an electron. Dirac hypothesized that the apparent similarity of these ratios might not be a mere coincidence, but instead could result from fundamental cosmological laws.

3. The Anthropic Principle

The observation of the fine-tuning of the Universe is closely related to the anthropic principle. An early expression of this principle was done by Dicke in 1961: “The existence of physicists … [is] sufficient to demand that … relations between the three numbers [GN, H0, Ω] be satisfied”. Lord Martin Rees, cosmologist and Astronomer Royal in his popular book “Just Six Numbers” [24] added the number of dimensions and the relative strength of the electromagnetic to the gravitational interaction to his discussion of the fine tuning of the constants of Nature. The subtitle of the German translation nicely summarizes this book: “Hatte Gott eine Wahl?”—“Did God have a choice?”
In 1986 in their ground-breaking book “The Anthropic Cosmological Principle” [6], Barrow and Tipler explain that this principle holds that the fundamental structure of the Universe is constrained by the existence of intelligent observers. The Universe is as it is because if it were different, observers could not exist. In short: man not only fits to the Universe, the Universe also fits to man. Hawking in his “Brief History of Time” pointed out in 1988: “The remarkable fact is that the values of these numbers seem to have been very finely adjusted to make possible the development of life” [12].
The anthropic principle has been under intense discussions and criticism over the last decades. Steven Weinberg who repeatedly referred to it reportedly warned: “A physicist talking about the anthropic principle runs the same risk as a cleric talking about pornography: No matter how much you say you are against it, some people will think you are a little too interested” [25].
The big epistemological problem behind the anthropic principle is that for the moment we only observe one Universe. Hence, we cannot apply the scientific method to make repeated experiments with the object of our investigation in order to extract regularities and laws. The anthropic principle also runs the danger of ending up in a tautology or a causal circle: we only observe universes that allow an observer. Another critical point is that the anthropic principle makes no predictions but only postdictions.
Several questions should be carefully examined. Are we considering a selection like the number of dimensions or the symmetry breaking scheme of the interactions? How much freedom does an existing theory give a parameter to be tuned or fine-tuned? What exactly is tuned in our Universe: the underlying laws or the parameters, and are the parameters fundamental, emergent, or environ­mental?

4. From Universe to Multiverse

The problem of the uniqueness of our Universe can be avoided going from a single and unique universe to a multiverse consisting of a huge number of different universes. At the extreme energy densities at Planck time (~10−43 s) immediately after the Big Bang, due to quantum gravity the Universe is thought to be dominated by vacuum fluctuations of space-time. Soon (~10−36 s) after, in the cosmological model of inflation, vacuum fluctuations of a scalar (Higgs-like) inflaton field of the size of a tiny fraction of a proton radius could have inflated by many orders of magnitude to a region larger than the event horizon which later expanded to today’s observable Universe.
At these extreme energies, all non-gravitational interactions are still thought to be unified to one primordial force. At decreasing energies, these grand unified symmetries can break down to the symmetries of separate forces in many different ways. In our world, we observe SU(3)C, SU(2)W, and U(1). On top of that, the superstring theory developed in the 1980s by Green, Schwarz, Witten, and others [26] assumes six (or seven) extra spatial dimensions which are curled up at the small distance scales relevant in the early Universe. These theories give rise to a huge (~10500) [27,28] number of possible compactifications to the three dimensions which we observe at the low energies in our Universe today.
Each of the inflationary bubbles may have evolved into a universe with a different realization of the physics potential hidden in grand unified and superstring theories. So, the physics in these universes can be different from the physics in our Universe. Susskind called this vast field of possibilities “The anthropic landscape of string theory” [29].
In his essay “Particle Physics and Inflationary Cosmology” [30], Linde (who in the 1980s developed the inflationary scenario together with Guth [31], Steinhardt, and others) explained: “Instead of a Universe with a single law of physics operating everywhere we are discussing an eternally existing self-reproducing Multiverse which consists of many different parts where all possibilities can be realized”. Applying the anthropic principle to the string landscape, Weinberg in 2007 in an article “Living in the Multiverse” [32] stated that this principle “may explain how the constants of nature that we observe can take values suitable for life without being fine-tuned by a benevolent creator”. A Multiverse is thus not anymore subject of the Copernican principle which asserts that the laws of physics are the same in any part of the universe.
This is what Tegmark [33,34,35] in his classification of parallel universes called a level IV parallel universe. Tegmark in 1997 suggested [36] that “complete mathematical democracy holds: that mathematical existence and physical existence are equivalent, so that all mathematical structures exist physically as well. This is the Level IV multiverse. It can be viewed as a form of radical Platonism, asserting that the mathematical structures in Plato’s realm of ideas … exist ‘out there’ in a physical sense” [33,34]. In the multiverse concept, worlds with different physical laws are assumed to be real, in stark contrast to Leibniz’ purely speculative discussion of “possible worlds” of different degrees of goodness and virtue.
Steinhardt criticized that no experiment can rule out the multiverse hypothesis since it allows for all possible physics scenarios: “… the inflationary paradigm is so flexible that it is immune to experimental and observational tests. First, inflation is driven by a hypothetical scalar field, the inflaton, which has properties that can be adjusted to produce effectively any outcome. Second, inflation does not end with a universe with uniform properties, but almost inevitably leads to a multiverse with an infinite number of bubbles, in which the cosmic and physical properties vary from bubble to bubble. The part of the multiverse that we observe corresponds to a piece of just one such bubble. Scanning over all possible bubbles in the multiverse, everything that can physically happen does happen an infinite number of times. No experiment can rule out a theory that allows for all possible outcomes. Hence, the paradigm of inflation is unfalsifiable” [37].
In his discussion “Universe Or universe? It All Depends On The Multiverse” of whether to capitalize the word “Universe”, Gleiser [38] mentions that “we may obtain information of neighbouring universes, if they have collided with ours in the past” [39], but also insists that we have only our Universe.
Mersini-Houghton and others [40,41,42,43] developed a theory of the initial conditions of the Universe from a quantum multiverse and derived the selection of the initial states from the quantum dynamics of gravity acting on the string landscape. In [44,45], Di Valentino and Mersini-Houghton compare the predictions of a theory of the origin of the universe from a quantum landscape multiverse against the data of the Planck satellite. By considering the quantum entanglement correction of the multiverse, they derive, e.g., a lower limit on the local SUSY breaking scale of 12 PeV at 95% confidence level from recent Planck data. These analyses illustrate that it may be possible to test the hypothesis of a quantum landscape multiverse.

4.1. From Physics to Metaphysics: The Ultimate Dethronement of Man

Speculations on multiple worlds started within pre-Socratic philosophy. Epicurus, who also proposed atomism in a letter to his disciple Herodotus, expressed his belief that “there are infinite worlds both like and unlike this world of ours” and argued as follows: “For the atoms being infinite in number … have not been used up either on one world or on a limited number of worlds, nor on all the worlds which are alike, or on those which are different from these. So that there nowhere exists an obstacle to the infinite number of worlds” [46,47].
As shown by Kragh [48,49], many-world theories were discussed throughout the history of natural philosophy by Leibniz, Hume, Boltzmann, and in the context of cosmology and quantum theory by Eddington, Everett, and others. They were also called pluriverse, megaverse, or parallel worlds. The term “multiverse” [50] was first used in 1895 in a moral context by American philosopher William James [51]. When discussing the anthropic principle Barrow and Tipler [10] in 1986 still do not refer to a multiverse. Neither does Max Tegmark when discussing “worlds ruled by altogether different equations” in 1998 [36]. David Deutsch [52,53,54] in 1995 started to use the term multiverse in its modern context, and around the turn of the millennium it became common to discuss a multiverse [33,55].
The physics in our world could thus be one of many solutions of more general physical laws. Based on his treatise Physics, Aristotle subsequently composed his Metaphysics. In a similar spirit, we might consider the physics of a multiverse as a meta-physics in its original positive sense: a meta-physics encompassing many possible physics scenarios realized in a huge number of universes of a multiverse.
Copernicus assumed that the Earth is not at the center of the Universe, but only one of many planets orbiting around the Sun. Later, Darwin proposed that Man is not the crown and goal of creation but an animal like others and a product of biological evolution. Hubble showed that our Milky Way is only one out of many galaxies in the Universe. Modern science has repeatedly pushed Man off his throne into some remote corner of the Universe. Today, we may get rid of the anthropic problem assuming that our Universe is only one out of a multitude of universes in a multiverse.
After the three fundamental mortifications of modern mankind described by Freud [56], this would be the ultimate dethronement of Man in the history of science. Monod described this aspect of human existence as follows: “The ancient alliance has been broken. Man at last knows he is alone in the unfeeling immensity of the Universe, out of which he has emerged only by chance. His destiny is nowhere spelled out, nor is his duty. The kingdom above or the darkness below; it is for him to choose” [57].
Here, a word of caution may be appropriate. The multiverse is not an established theory but a hypothesis. Asking the question “Does the Multiverse Really Exist?” the astrophysicist George Ellis said [58]: “As skeptical as I am, I think the contemplation of the multiverse is an excellent opportunity to reflect on the nature of science and on the ultimate nature of existence: why we are here... In looking at this concept, we need an open mind, though not too open. It is a delicate path to tread. Parallel universes may or may not exist; the case is unproved. We are going to have to live with that uncertainty. Nothing is wrong with scientifically based philosophical speculation, which is what multiverse proposals are. But we should name it for what it is”.
Hypotheses have been very fruitful in the history of science, and it may take a great amount of time and effort to test or to falsify them. The history of the atomic hypothesis is a good example. Based on his observation of the law of multiple proportions in 1808, John Dalton in his essay “A New System of Chemical Philosophy” formulated the hypothesis that all matter consists of indivisible atoms. The final confirmation of the atomic hypothesis took almost one century, and the theories of Maxwell, Boltzmann, and Einstein had to stand against the criticism of positivists like Mach.
In order to keep science alive and healthy, we should therefore aim to keep an open mind for hypotheses even if we cannot immediately give prescriptions for how to test or to falsify them.

4.2. Kepler’s Harmonices Mundi and the Best of All Worlds

In a similar spirit as when Kepler in his time asked the question: “Why are there just six planets?” we ask today: “Why are there just three fermion families?” Without deeper knowledge, it is impossible to decide whether such a question is a fundamental or an environmental one. In his main works Mysterium Cosmographicum (1596) and Harmonices Mundi (1619), Kepler was looking for God’s plan of the geometry of the Universe and tried to explain the ratios of the planetary orbits from first (and divine) principles. Nesting and encasing the spheres inscribed and circumscribed to the five Platonic solids within one another, he produced six shells the radii of which miraculously corresponded to the sizes of the orbits of the six known planets.
Since Kepler did not know that there are more planets in our solar system, millions of planetary systems in our galaxy and billions of galaxies in our Universe, he considered an accidental fine-tuning to be fundamental. He thus tried to answer an irrelevant question. Additionally, Kepler’s model relied on the orbits being circles, which clearly contradicted his most important discovery that the orbits are ellipses. To save God’s plan, Kepler had to compromise his Platonic model.
So, a sufficient number of alternatives can easily solve an apparent fine-tuning problem. The same may be true for our present anthropic problem: We are fascinated by our fine-tuned Universe which may be completely accidental in view of a sufficiently large number of alternative universes.
Kepler’s dilemma, however, besides the statistical solution also had a fundamental solution: based on his laws Newton was able to create his fundamental theory of gravity. So, in Kepler’s case two solutions of the dilemma existed which were both viable and even not contradictory to each other: the statistical and the fundamental one.
We may be in a similar situation today. In the same spirit as Newton generalized Kepler’s laws, we search for more general and basic laws behind the laws known presently and follow the ideas of grand unification, supersymmetry, superstrings, quantum gravity, etc., which does not imply that the whole of physics can be reduced to a Theory of Everything or a world formula.
However, beyond the search for the fundamental laws, we should also consider the statistical solution of the anthropic problem. The existence within a multiverse of a large number of universes with different dimensionalities, symmetry breaking schemes, strengths of the fundamental forces, particle masses, inflation scenarios, and asymmetries (like matter–antimatter) may allow for exactly the fundamental parameters needed for the formation of stable structures, chemical elements, and finally, life in our world. Fine-tuning would then be a result of a natural cosmic selection of our world out of many worlds as the best habitat for the development of life (see, e.g., Smolin [59]). As Gell-Mann once put it: “If we really live in a multiverse, physics will have been reduced to an environmental science like botany” [60].
So, the indefiniteness and openness of the multiverse idea which Steinhardt and others deplore become very productive: they open the infinitely rich field of possibilities needed for the development of life.

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

References

  1. Leibniz, G.W. Essais de Théodicée sur la Bonté de Dieu, la Liberté de L’homme, et L’origine du mal; Mortier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 1714. [Google Scholar]
  2. Leibniz, G.W. Essays on the Goodness of God, the Freedom of Man and the Origin of Evil. In The Philosophical Works of Leibniz; Tuttle, Morehouse & Taylor: New Haven, CT, USA, 1890. [Google Scholar]
  3. Weinberg, S. Dreams of a Final Theory; Pantheon Books: New York, NY, USA, 1992; p. 242. [Google Scholar]
  4. Einstein, A. Über den gegenwärtigen Stand der Feldtheorie. In Festschrift für Aurel Stodola; Honegger, E., Ed.; Orell Füssli: Zürich, Switzerland, 1929; p. 126. [Google Scholar]
  5. Hoffmann, B. Quotation by Einstein. In The Ultimate Quotable Einstein; Calaprice, A., Ed.; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2010; p. 407. [Google Scholar]
  6. Straus, E.G. Quotation by Einstein. In The Ultimate Quotable Einstein; Calaprice, A., Ed.; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2010; p. 344. [Google Scholar]
  7. Dicke, R.H. Dirac’s Cosmology and Mach’s Principle. Nature 1961, 192, 440–441. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  8. Sagan, C. The Cosmic Connection: An Extraterrestrial Perspective; Doubleday: New York, NJ, USA, 1973; p. 47. [Google Scholar]
  9. Stenger, V. The Anthropic Principle. In The New Encyclopedia of Unbelief; Flynn, T., Ed.; Prometheus Books: Amherst, NY, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
  10. Barrow, J.D.; Tipler, F. The Anthropic Cosmological Principle; Oxford University Press: New York, NJ, USA, 1986. [Google Scholar]
  11. Barrow, J.D. The Constants of Nature; Jonathan Cape Ltd.: London, UK, 2002. [Google Scholar]
  12. Hawking, S. A Brief History of Time; Bantam Books: New York, NJ, USA, 1988. [Google Scholar]
  13. Ehrenfest, P.S. In what way does it become manifest in fundamental laws of physics that space has three dimensions? Proc. R. Acad. Amst. 1917, 20, 200–209. [Google Scholar]
  14. Ehrenfest, P.S. How do the fundamental laws of physics make manifest that space has three dimensions? Annalen der Physik 1920, 61, 440–446. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  15. Tangherlini, F.R. Schwarzschild field in n dimensions and the dimensionality of space problem. Il Nuovo Cim. 1963, 27, 636–651. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  16. Ellis, G.F.R.; Maartens, R.; MacCallum, M.A.H. Relativistic Cosmology; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2012; p. 146. [Google Scholar]
  17. Ade, P.A.R.; Aghanim, N.; Arnaud, M.; Ashdown, M.; Aumont, J.; Baccigalupi, C.; Banday, A.J.; Barreiro, R.B.; Bartlett, J.G.; Bartolo, N.; et al. Planck Collaboration. 2015 Results XIII. Astron. Astrophys. 2016, 594, A13. [Google Scholar]
  18. Weinberg, S. Anthropic Bound on the Cosmological Constant. Phys. Rev. Lett. 1987, 59, 2607–2610. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  19. Harnik, R.; Kribs, G.D.; Perez, G. A universe without weak interactions. Phys. Rev. D 2006, 74, 035006. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  20. Feynman, R.P. QED: The Strange Theory of Light and Matter; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1986; p. 129. [Google Scholar]
  21. Dirac, P.A.M. A New Basis for Cosmology. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. A Math. Phys. Eng. Sci. 1938, 165, 199–208. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  22. Dirac, P.A.M. The Cosmological Constants. Nature 1937, 139, 323. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  23. Dirac, P.A.M. Cosmological Models and the Large Numbers Hypothesis. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. A Math. Phys. Eng. Sci. 1974, 338, 439–446. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  24. Rees, M. Just Six Numbers. The Deep Forces That Shape the Universe; Basic Books: New York, NY, USA, 2000. [Google Scholar]
  25. Giudice, G.F. Naturally Speaking: The Naturalness Criterion and Physics at the LHC. In Perspectives on LHC Physics; World Scientific: Singapore, 2008; p. 172. [Google Scholar]
  26. Green, M.; Schwarz, J.; Witten, E. Superstring Theory: Volume 2, Loop Amplitudes, Anomalies and Phenomenology; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2012. [Google Scholar]
  27. Douglas, M. The statistics of string/M theory vacua. J. High Energy Phys. 2003, 2003, 046. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  28. Ashok, S.; Douglas, M. Counting Flux Vacua. J. High Energy Phys. 2004, 2004, 060. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  29. Susskind, L. The Anthropic Landscape of String Theory. arXiv 2003, arXiv:hep-th/0302219. [Google Scholar]
  30. Linde, A.D. Particle Physics and Inflationary Cosmology; Harwood: Chur, Switzerland, 1990. [Google Scholar]
  31. Guth, A. The Inflationary Universe: The Quest for a New Theory of Cosmic Origins; Basic Books: New York, NY, USA, 1997. [Google Scholar]
  32. Weinberg, S. Living in the Multiverse. In Universe or Multiverse? Carr, B., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2007. [Google Scholar]
  33. Tegmark, M. Parallel Universes. In Science and Ultimate Reality: From Quantum to Cosmos, Honoring John Wheeler’s 90th Birthday; Barrow, J.D., Davies, P.C.W., Harper, C.L., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2003. [Google Scholar]
  34. Tegmark, M. Parallel Universes. Sci. Am. 2003, 288, 41–51. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  35. Tegmark, M. The Multiverse Hierarchy. In Universe or Multiverse; Carr, B., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2007. [Google Scholar]
  36. Tegmark, M. Is “the theory of everything” merely the ultimate ensemble theory? Ann. Phys. 1998, 270, 1–51. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  37. Steinhardt, P. Big Bang blunder bursts the Multiverse bubble. Nature 2014, 510, 9. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  38. Gleiser, M. Universe or universe? It All Depends on the Multiverse. NPR Commentary. 20 February 2013. Available online: www.npr.org/sections/13.7/2013/02/19/172391249/universe-or-universe-it-all-depends-on-the-multiverse (accessed on 16 January 2017).
  39. Gleiser, M. The Universe Next Door. NPR Commentary. 9 January 2013. Available online: www.npr.org/blogs/13.7/2013/01/09/168863713/good-news-bad-news-the-universe-next-door (accessed on 16 January 2017).
  40. Mersini-Houghton, L. Birth of the Universe from the Multiverse. arXiv 2008, arXiv:0809.3623. [Google Scholar]
  41. Mersini-Houghton, L.; Holman, R. ‘Tilting’ the Universe with the Landscape Multiverse: The ‘Dark’ Flow. J. Cosmol. Astropart. Phys. 2009, 2009, 006. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  42. Mersini-Houghton, L. Predictions of the Quantum Landscape Multiverse. Class. Quant. Grav. 2017, 34, 047001. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  43. Kinney, W.H. Limits on entanglement effects in the string landscape from Planck and BICEP/Keck data. J. Cosmol. Astropart. Phys. 2016, 2016, 013. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  44. Di Valentino, E.; Mersini-Houghton, L. Testing predictions of the quantum landscape multiverse 1: The Starobinsky inflationary potential. J. Cosmol. Astropart. Phys. 2017, 2017, 002. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  45. Di Valentino, E.; Mersini-Houghton, L. Testing predictions of the quantum landscape multiverse 2: The exponential inflationary potential. J. Cosmol. Astropart. Phys. 2017, 2017, 020. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  46. Epicurus. Epicurus to Herodotus. In The Stoic and Epicurean Philosophers: The Complete Extant Writings of Epicurus, Epictetus, Lucretius and Marcus Aurelius; Modern Library: New York, NJ, USA, 1957. [Google Scholar]
  47. Crowe, M.J. The Extraterrestrial Life Debate, Antiquity to 1915: A Source Book; Crowe, M.J., Ed.; University of Notre Dame Press: Notre Dame, IN, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
  48. Kragh, H. Contemporary History of Cosmology and the Controversy over the Multiverse. Ann. Sci. 2009, 66, 529–551. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  49. Kragh, H. Higher Speculations: Grand Theories and Failed Revolutions in Physics and Cosmology; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2011; pp. 256–259. [Google Scholar]
  50. Collins English Dictionary. Complete & Unabridged 2012 Digital Edition, Harper Collins Publishers 2012. Available online: www.dictionary.com/browse/multiverse (accessed on 18 July 2017).
  51. James, W. Is Life Worth Living? Int. Jrnl. Ethics 1895, 6, 1–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  52. Deutsch, D. The Multiverse. Interview from 1995 by Noorderlicht. Available online: https://youtu.be/SDZ454K_lBY (accessed on 18 July 2017).
  53. Deutsch, D. The Fabric of Reality; Penguin Books: London, UK, 1997. [Google Scholar]
  54. Deutsch, D. The Structure of the Multiverse. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. A Math. Phys. Eng. Sci. 2002, 458, 2911–2923. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  55. Cirkovic, M.; Bostrom, N. Cosmological Constant and the Final Anthropic Hypothesis. Astrophys. Space Sci. 2000, 274, 675–687. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  56. Freud, S. Imago: Zeitschrift für Anwendung der Psychoanalyse auf die Geisteswissenschaften; Internationaler Psychoanalytischer Verlag: Vienna, Austria, 1917. [Google Scholar]
  57. Monod, J. Chance and Necessity; Alfred Knopf: New York, NY, USA, 1972; p. 180. [Google Scholar]
  58. Ellis, G. Does the Multiverse Really Exist? Sci. Am. 2011, 305, 38–43. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  59. Smolin, L. The Life of the Cosmos; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1999. [Google Scholar]
  60. Duff, M.; Sutton, C. The membrane at the end of the Universe. New Sci. 1988, 118, 67–71. [Google Scholar]
1
On a more general basis one could even abandon the concept of molecular based life.
2
Smaller, slower burning stars with smaller planetary systems could be an alternative.
3
We take into account that the strong interaction conserves isospin and is flavour blind.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Naumann, T. Do We Live in the Best of All Possible Worlds? The Fine-Tuning of the Constants of Nature. Universe 2017, 3, 60. https://doi.org/10.3390/universe3030060

AMA Style

Naumann T. Do We Live in the Best of All Possible Worlds? The Fine-Tuning of the Constants of Nature. Universe. 2017; 3(3):60. https://doi.org/10.3390/universe3030060

Chicago/Turabian Style

Naumann, Thomas. 2017. "Do We Live in the Best of All Possible Worlds? The Fine-Tuning of the Constants of Nature" Universe 3, no. 3: 60. https://doi.org/10.3390/universe3030060

APA Style

Naumann, T. (2017). Do We Live in the Best of All Possible Worlds? The Fine-Tuning of the Constants of Nature. Universe, 3(3), 60. https://doi.org/10.3390/universe3030060

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop