God’s Presence within Henry’s Phenomenology of Life: The Phenomenological Revelation of God in Opposition to Plantinga’s Affirmation of God’s Existence
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Henry’s Original Critique against the Anselmian Proof
2.1. The Ontological Argument as an Expression of Ontological Monism
- (1)
- On the one hand, God’s real and inner essence is independent from the (human) subject in the sense that it is exterior from him;
- (2)
- On the other hand, God’s existence is conceived as a pro-jection (ex-teriorization) of God’s being in a phenomenon that could be achieved by a subject’s conscience.22
2.2. Henry’s Critique of Anselm in the Context of the Phenomenology of Life
- (1)
- First, the human subject grasps reality from the “outside”, remaining always “distant” and “disconnected” from reality itself.
- (2)
- Second, only one kind of phenomenonalization (that is to say, manifestation of reality) is conceived: reality must exteriorize itself (which corresponds to “alienation of being”) to become a phenomenon grasped by the human mind.29
- (3)
- Third, in this philosophical paradigm, the human subject is defined according to the manifestation of another being. As Henry notices, the philosophy of consciousness does not develop a “positive ontology of subjectivity”.30 In other words, the human subject is conceived as being at the service of the ontology of an exterior reality, because in his mind, in his conscience, the manifestation of exterior reality can be realized.
3. How the Debate within Analytic Philosophy Corroborates Henry’s Critique
4. How to Perceive God in the Archi-Affectivity of the Ego?
5. Conclusions
Feuerbach argues that the “proofs for the existence of God have as their aim the ex-teriorisation of the interior and its separation from man.58
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Anselm of Canterbury. 2001. Proslogion. Translated by Thomas Williams. Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company. [Google Scholar]
- Anselme de Cantorbéry. 2008. Quid ad haec respondeat editor ipsius libelli. In L’œuvre d’Anselme de Cantorbéry, vol. 1: Monologion. Proslogion. Édition et traduction de Michel Corbin. Paris: Les Éditions du Cerf, pp. 298–318. [Google Scholar]
- Furuso, Tadayoshi. 2015. La répétition de la philosophie du christianisme. In Revue Internationale Michel Henry: La phénoménologie Française au Japon. n. 6. Louvain-la-Neuve: Presses Universitaires de Louvain, pp. 85–101. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, Michel. 2014. L’essence de la Manifestation. Paris: Épiméthée/PUF. First published 1963. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, Michel. 2003. Le cogito et l’idée de phénoménologie. In Phénoménologie—Tome II: De la subjectivité. Paris: Épiméthée/PUF, pp. 57–72, Article originally published in Cartesiana 3, Osaka, 1984, pp. 1–15. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, Michel. 2004. Acheminement vers la question de Dieu: Preuve de l’être ou l’épreuve de la vie. In Phénoménologie de la vie—Tome IV: Sur l’éthique et la Religion. Paris: Épiméthée/PUF, pp. 67–80, Article originally published in Archivio di Filosofia, 1–3, 1990, pp. 521–30. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, Michel. 2003. Phénoménologie de la vie. In Phénoménologie de la vie—Tome I: De la phénoménologie. Paris: Épiméthée/PUF, pp. 59–76, Article originally published in Prétentaine (« le vivant »), n. 14–15, décembre 2001, pp. 11–25. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, Michel. 1973. The Essence of Manifestation. Translated by Girard Etzkorn. Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, Michel. 1975. Philosophy and Phenomenology of the Body. Translated by Girard Etzkorn. Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, Michel. 1976. Marx I: Une philosophie de la réalité. Paris: Gallimard. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, Michel. 1985. Généalogie de la psychanalyse. Paris: Épiméthée/PUF. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, Michel. 1996. C’est moi la vérité. Pour une Philosophie du Christianisme. Paris: Les Éditions du Seuil. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, Michel. 2000. Incarnation. Une Philosophie de la Chair. Paris: Éditions du Seuil. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, Michel. 2005. Entretiens. Arles: Sulliver. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, Michel. 2010. Pour une phénoménologie de la vie. Entretien avec Olivier Salazar-Ferrer. Clichy: Éditions de Corlevour. [Google Scholar]
- Lavigne, Jean-François. 2011. Souffrance et ipséité selon Michel Henry. Le problème de l’identité transcendantale de l’ego. In Cahiers Philosophiques. No. 126 2011/3. Paris: Réseau Canopé, pp. 66–81. [Google Scholar]
- O’Sullivan, Michael. 2006. Michel Henry: Incarnation, Barbarism and Belief. An Introduction to the Work of Michel Henry. New York and Oxford: Peter Lang. [Google Scholar]
- Plantinga, Alvin. 1990. God and Other Minds. A Study of the Rational Justification of Belief in God. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press. First published 1967. [Google Scholar]
- Plantinga, Alvin. 1974. The Nature of Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Plantinga, Alvin. 1977. God, Freedom, and Evil. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans Publishing Co. [Google Scholar]
- Plantinga, Alvin. 2000. Warranted Christian Belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Plantinga, Alvin, and Michael Tooley. 2008. Knowledge of God. Malden and Oxford: Blackwell Publishing. [Google Scholar]
1 | Anselm of Canterbury (1033/4-1109) proposed a “single argument” (unum argumentum), that has been much commented upon in Modern and Contemporary Philosophy, according to which reason affirms the necessary existence of God. The argument assumes the idea of God as the “being greater than which no other being can be conceived. (Id quod maius cogitarit nequit)” According to this notion, it is contradictory to deny God’s existence, because we can also conceive a greater being than a non-existent God (cf. Anselm of Canterbury 2001). |
2 | Cf. (Plantinga [1967] 1990, p. 38). |
3 | |
4 | |
5 | |
6 | |
7 | |
8 | |
9 | This is the reason why we can state the argument by the following: “if it is logically possible that God exists, then it is logically necessary that God exists” (Plantinga and Tooley 2008, p. 84). |
10 | (Plantinga 1977, p. 111). Plantinga’s reformulation of the Anselmian proof is located in two key-works: first, in God, Freedom, and Evil (Plantinga 1977, pp. 108–15); second, in The Nature of Necessity wherein the argument is presented in a more sophisticated way, following the techniques of modal logic (see Plantinga 1974, pp. 213–17). I do not intend here to explain the argument in detail. I will rather focus my analysis in the main concepts with which Plantinga’s works, in order to show its opposition to Henry’s phenomenology. |
11 | |
12 | Cf. (Plantinga 2000, p. 259). |
13 | |
14 | Cf. (Plantinga 1977, p. 112). |
15 | “Loin de frayer l’accès à Dieu, la preuve d’Anselme l’interdit.” (Henry [1990] 2004, p. 73). |
16 | Cf. (Henry 2010, p. 45). This lecture in Rome was the basis of the article “Acheminement vers la question de Dieu: preuve de l’être ou l’épreuve de la vie” (Cf. Henry [1990] 2004, pp. 67–80; article originally published in Archivio di Filosofia, diretto da Marco M. Olivetti, anno LVIII, 1990, No. 1-3, pp. 521–32). |
17 | Cf. (Henry [1963] 2014, L’essence de la manifestation, §8: p. 62, §10: p. 82). This is developed in Henry’s analysis of “phenomenological distance” and the transcendental “alienation” to every phenomenon. |
18 | |
19 | |
20 | This “ontological difference” or “phenomenological distance” is, in Kant’s philosophy, the condition of possibility of any kind of experience (cf. Henry 1973, §7: p. 38, §11: pp. 90–91). |
21 | |
22 | In the present paper, the masculine pronoun is used to mention God. It is important to notice that this choice is due to the fact that the authors we are dealing with, such as Anselm, Plantinga and Henry, operate within Christian tradition. However, the paper will use some times the neutral pronoun in order to show that both Plantinga’s argumentation as Henry’s view can be applied to a God different from the Trinity of Christian theology. |
23 | |
24 | “Consciousness therefore is not some other form of existence than that which arises in the internal splitting apart of Being; rather it is this very existence, this sole and unique form of all possible manifestation.” (Henry 1973, §11: p. 77). |
25 | Cf. (Henry [1990] 2004, pp. 72–73). |
26 | Cf. (Henry 2010, pp. 44–45). |
27 | Cf. (Henry [1990] 2004, pp. 67–68, 73). The same critique that we find in L’essence de la manifestation is also stated in a more clear way in the first volume of Henry’s Trilogy, with an explicit mention of Anselm’s name and Anselm’s Proslogion. In C’est moi la vérité, Michel Henry opposes the “infinitely great Being” of Anselm as against the “Christian God” (cf. Henry 1996, p. 72), judging that the Medieval Doctor was the first to open the way to a process of “denaturation” of God within occidental philosophy. According to Michel Henry, Anselm’s concept of God conceives only the phenomenality of representation, and applies it to God. This approach does not consider the access to God’s manifestation through the affectivity of the self (cf. Henry 1996, pp. 194–95). |
28 | |
29 | Cf. (Henry [2001] 2003, pp. 62–63). |
30 | Following Maine de Biran, Michel Henry tries to substitute a “transcendental phenomenology of classical and empirical psychology” by a real “ontology of subjectivity” (cf. Henry 1975, p. 16). |
31 | |
32 | Cf. (O’Sullivan 2006, pp. 30–31). |
33 | The forgetfulness of affectivity consists precisely in the contradiction into which Descartes falls by excluding the auto-affection of the ego. In fact, on the one hand, in the Second Meditation, Descartes discovers the reality of the soul, the auto-affection, as the primarily phenomenon to which we have access. But, on the other hand, at the end of this Meditation, Descartes concludes that there is no appearance of affectivity. Furthermore, the Third Meditation (within which God’s existence is affirmed) accentuates the oblivion of the affectivity realm (cf. Henry 1985, pp. 58–59). |
34 | Michel Henry appreciates the Descartes of the Seconde Méditation. That is to say, the Descartes who discovered the first cetain reality of the cogito, who his a affective subject. However, the Descartes of the “the clear and dinctis ideas” is, according to Henry, in contradiction with is discourvering. This one is the Descartes appreciated by Husserl (cf. Henry [1984] 2003, pp. 57–72). It seems to me, that Plantinga is also more close to the second Descartes. |
35 | Cf. (Plantinga [1967] 1990, p. 47). |
36 | |
37 | |
38 | |
39 | |
40 | Cf. (O’Sullivan 2006, p. 30). |
41 | |
42 | Cf. (Plantinga 1977, pp. 268–71). |
43 | Cf. (Henry 2010, p. 45). |
44 | |
45 | I am translating the French adjective “pathéthique” Henry used, derived from the Greek word pathos, by “pathos-inducing”. |
46 | Cf. (Henry 2000, §11: pp. 86–93). |
47 | |
48 | |
49 | “En sa certitude invincible, dans le pathos de sa chair souffrance ou de sa joie, il ne lui doit rien.” (Henry 2000, §15: p. 132). |
50 | “Ipséité désigne le fait d’être soi-même, le fait d’être un Soi (…) C’est un Soi singulier et réel (…) généré par la Vie comme ce en quoi elle s’éprouve et se révèle à elle-même” (Henry 1996, p. 29). |
51 | |
52 | |
53 | |
54 | Cf. (O’Sullivan 2006, pp. 176–77). |
55 | It is interesting to notice that Henry’s argument avoids, in a certain sense, Kant’s critique, because it does not put God’s existence in the accusative term. In other words, according to his opponents, the ontological argument predicates God’s existence. And that is valid only in the copulative meaning of being, but it is never legitimate in the existential meaning of being. However, Henry underlines that in his own argument is the human subject who is in the accusative term, and so God is not predicated (cf. Lavigne 2011, p. 75). |
56 | Cf. (Furuso 2015, p. 86). |
57 | Cf. (Henry 2005, pp. 152–54). |
58 | (Henry 1976, p. 102). We used the translation presented by Michael O’Sullivan (cf. O’Sullivan 2006, p. 121). |
© 2018 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Gonçalves Lind, A. God’s Presence within Henry’s Phenomenology of Life: The Phenomenological Revelation of God in Opposition to Plantinga’s Affirmation of God’s Existence. Religions 2018, 9, 187. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel9060187
Gonçalves Lind A. God’s Presence within Henry’s Phenomenology of Life: The Phenomenological Revelation of God in Opposition to Plantinga’s Affirmation of God’s Existence. Religions. 2018; 9(6):187. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel9060187
Chicago/Turabian StyleGonçalves Lind, Andreas. 2018. "God’s Presence within Henry’s Phenomenology of Life: The Phenomenological Revelation of God in Opposition to Plantinga’s Affirmation of God’s Existence" Religions 9, no. 6: 187. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel9060187
APA StyleGonçalves Lind, A. (2018). God’s Presence within Henry’s Phenomenology of Life: The Phenomenological Revelation of God in Opposition to Plantinga’s Affirmation of God’s Existence. Religions, 9(6), 187. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel9060187