The ‘Local’ Nature of Religious Hinges and the Problem of ‘Honest Doubt’
Abstract
[Wittgenstein] was impatient with ‘proofs’ of the existence of God, and with attempts to give religion a rational foundation.
1. Pritchard’s Parity Argument
[…] quasi-fideism argues that a subject’s basic religious commitments are hinge commitments and hence, like all hinge commitments, are essentially arational.
The parity argument offered by quasi-fideism […] appeals to the fundamentally arational nature of everyday belief in order to defend the fundamentally arational nature of religious belief. Yes, religious belief has at its heart arational hinge commitments, but this cannot be an objection to the rationality of religious belief if it is true that belief in general has at its heart arational hinge commitments.
We are thus led to a distinctive account of the epistemology of religious commitment, which I call quasi-fideism. Like fideism, it holds that the epistemology of religious commitments must allow for the fact that fundamental religious convictions are essentially arational in kind. But unlike fideism, it does not epistemically ‘ghettoise’ religious belief, but rather treats it as analogous to believing more generally.
[…] clearly, in the non-religious case, if it turned out that we cannot hold on to our hinges, this would open the door to forms of radical skepticism which would drag with them all our epistemic methods by means of which we form epistemically rational beliefs. By contrast, in the religious case, we would certainly receive an existential blow, but nothing detrimental to the proper exercise of our rational faculties. That is, one might lose hope or faith in the meaningfulness of life, or in the possibility of being reunited with one’s loved ones in an afterlife. Yet, one would not lose the ability to form evidentially justified belief and, with it, a grip on epistemic rationality altogether. […] Thus, there is no real ‘parity argument’ on offer between religious and non-religious belief capable of salvaging the epistemic rationality of the former, which we may evince from Pritchard’s interpretation of Wittgenstein’s OC.
2. What Can Be Called a Religious Hinge?
By this, I have in mind those religious commitments that are fundamental to a religious life, as opposed to merely incidental religious beliefs that come with a religious life. For example, that God exists, or that miracles can occur would be natural instances of the former, whereas beliefs about, say, the more arcane elements of religious teaching would be natural instances of the latter.
But when is something objectively certain? When a mistake is not possible. But what kind of possibility is that? Mustn’t mistake be logically excluded?(OC 194)
The point is that one’s religious convictions play an indispensable part in what it is to be a religious believer at all, such that one cannot lose very many of them (if any) without losing one’s faith altogether. One’s incidental religious beliefs are not like this. One can alter quite a lot of these—and, indeed, over the course of one’s life one probably will—while still retaining one’s faith. […] in order to develop a suitable epistemology of religious belief we need to be sensitive to this distinction.
It is usually assumed that if there are religious hinge commitments, then one of them will be a commitment to the proposition ‘God exists’4. I don’t think this is a plausible candidate to be a hinge commitment, however, as it is far too abstract and theoretical in nature. Accordingly, I doubt that the kind of visceral certainty that Wittgenstein is describing, and which on a quasi-fideistic view would be manifest as regards fundamental religious commitments, would attach itself to this claim. A more promising example would be something that captures the personal relationship one bears to God, such as that God loves me.
3. Religious Hinges Are Local
It might be imagined that some propositions, of the form of empirical propositions, were hardened and functioned as channels for such empirical propositions as were not hardened but fluid; and that this relation altered with time, in that fluid propositions hardened, and hard ones became fluid.(OC 96)
[…] if (epistemic) rationality is not absolute but dependent on a system of a-rational hinges, and if different, potentially incompatible, systems of a-rational hinges could exist, then ordinary beliefs based on them would also be rational, despite their incompatibility.
Provided that there is a wide-ranging overlap in the hinge commitments held by both parties, then resolving deep disagreements, while it may face practical hurdles, is not in principle impossible. Call any form of epistemic relativism that entails epistemic incommensurability strong epistemic relativism, and any form of epistemic relativism that doesn’t entail epistemic incommensurability weak epistemic relativism. The point of the foregoing is that hinge epistemology in itself only seems to entail weak epistemic relativism, as while it might entail the possibility of divergent hinge commitments, this is compatible with such a divergence being peripheral rather than substantial.
4. Doubting a Hinge?
While we might loosely characterize epistemic vertigo as doubt, it differs in some important respects from ordinary doubt. The honest doubt that concerns us in the religious case […] is not ordinary doubt but rather epistemic vertigo as it arises in a religious context. […] honest doubt is meant to be compatible with religious conviction. Indeed, the guiding idea is that honest doubt can be a natural manifestation of a reflective religious life. If so, then honest doubt and religious conviction must at least be compatible. Honest doubt is thus distinct from the kind of doubt that actually undercuts one’s religious conviction (call this ordinary doubt). The honest doubter isn’t in the process of losing their faith, and certainly hasn’t lost it, but is rather simply entertaining honest doubts about it (albeit […] of a fundamental kind). […] although [honest doubt] is not a doubt that undercuts one’s religious conviction, it is nonetheless a genuine form of doubt, and not merely (3) some form of intellectual artifice.’
[…] our epistemic situation, even after we have resolved the problem of radical scepticism, is not the same as the folk who have never engaged with that problem in the first place. I think that this explains why even when we have successfully dealt with the radical sceptical difficulty we nonetheless feel a sense of unease with our epistemic position. I call this anxiety epistemic vertigo. The use of a phobic term is deliberate. The idea is that while one may be aware that the sceptical problem is resolved, and thus no longer poses an epistemic threat […] one can nonetheless feel a kind of epistemic ‘giddiness’ at surveying one’s epistemic situation from the detached perspective whereby the hinges are in view. […] Just as one can be aware, while up high, that one is secure, and yet be anxious nonetheless, the same goes for epistemic vertigo when we become aware of the hidden role that hinge commitments play in our rational practices.
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | For a more elaborate description of ‘hinges’, see Moyal-Sharrock and Pritchard (2025). |
2 | For a description of my taxonomy of hinges based on On Certainty, see Moyal-Sharrock (2005) or Moyal-Sharrock and Pritchard (2025). |
3 | See, for example, Svensson (1981, 84ff) and Stroll (2002, 449ff) who refer exclusively to ‘objective certainty’; Nigel Pleasants uses both expressions (Pleasants 2025); I initially referred to both ‘objective certainty’ and ‘hinge certainty’ (e.g., Moyal-Sharrock 2005), but have since used the latter exclusively. |
4 | Pritchard himself assumes this in the first passage quoted in this section (Pritchard 2018, pp. 1–2). |
5 | See, for example, the definitions offered by the Oxford English Dictionary (OED): religion is ‘belief in or acknowledgement of some superhuman power or powers (esp. a god or gods) which is typically manifested in obedience, reverence, and worship’. |
6 | For a more elaborate description of this distinction—and its source in On Certainty, see Moyal-Sharrock (2005) or Part I of Moyal-Sharrock and Pritchard (2025). |
7 | Indeed, even some atheists consider themselves Jewish out of a sense of socio-cultural and historical belonging to the Jewish people. This would imply a very liberal extension of the concept of religion which would not be admissible on the definition of religion (OED) we have assumed here. |
8 | As noted above, though not a hinge for liberal Jews, it would be one for conservative or orthodox Jews. |
9 | For more on the acquisition and erosion of local hinges, see Moyal-Sharrock (2005). |
10 | Though as O’Hara notes (in conversation), it is a matter of scholarly controversy whether some/all the peoples that became Israel migrated or were ‘natives’ of the land. |
11 | O’Hara uses documentation to argue that ‘for a Second Temple Jew, the eating of pork, and more so the use of pork in a cult setting was unthinkably impious. Its wrongness was … a basic moral certainty for them’ (O’Hara 2018, p. 122). For a Jew to sacrifice a pig on the altar in the Jerusalem Temple would be ‘so impious that its wrongness would be indubitable. So the Jew who did such a thing would have to be thought of as an infidel or a heretic. For a Second Temple Jew, to deliberately sprinkle pigs-blood on the altar of the Jerusalem Temple, would have been in the same category as murder’ (O’Hara 2018, pp. 122–23; 123n5). |
12 | For a more extended argument on the subject of relativism, see Moyal-Sharrock (forthcoming). |
13 | As I am reminded by Neil O’Hara, though Job’s faith in God’s existence is usually thought to remain unshaken, this is sometimes contested (see, for example, N. K.Verbin ‘Uncertainty and religious belief’, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 51: 1 (2002, pp. 1–37). Granted, but I feel the main point about Job is that he retains his faith in spite of all the vicissitudes God unleashes on him. |
14 | I am extremely grateful to Neil O’Hara for his comments and for our discussion of this paper. |
References
- Bagheri Noaparast, Zoheir. 2025. God Unhinged? A Critique of Quasi-Fideism. Religions 16: 186. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Coliva, Annalisa. 2025. Against Quasi-Fideism. Religions 16: 365. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Malcolm, Norman. 2018. A Memoir. In Portraits of Wittgenstein: Abridged Edition. Edited by F. A. Flowers, III and Ian Ground. London: Bloomsbury Academic, pp. 619–72. [Google Scholar]
- Moyal-Sharrock, Danièle. 2005. Understanding Wittgenstein’s on Certainty. London: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Moyal-Sharrock, Danièle. Forthcoming. Religious Hinges and Epistemic Relativism. In The Nature of Religious Belief in Wittgenstein’s Philosophy. Edited by Ulrich Arnswald and Joaquín Jareño-Alarcón.
- Moyal-Sharrock, Danièle, and Duncan Pritchard. 2025. Wittgenstein on Knowledge and Certainty. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- O’Hara, Neil. 2018. Moral Certainty and the Foundations of Morality. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- O’Hara, Neil. 2025. Basic Religious Certainty and the New Testament. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 97: 1–16. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pleasants, Nigel. 2025. Hinge-certainty and the asymmetricality of “deep moral disagreement”. Synthese 205: 210. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pritchard, Duncan. 2015. Wittgenstein on Faith and Reason: The Influence of Newman. In God, Truth and Other Enigmas. Edited by Miroslaw Szatkowski. Berlin: De Gruyter, pp. 145–59. [Google Scholar]
- Pritchard, Duncan. 2018. Quasi-Fideism and Religious Conviction. European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 10: 51–66. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pritchard, Duncan. 2019. Wittgensteinian Epistemology, Epistemic Vertigo, and Pyrrhonian Scepticism. In Epistemology After Sextus Empiricus. Edited by Justin Vlasits and Katja Maria Vogt. Oxford: Oxford UP, pp. 172–92. [Google Scholar]
- Pritchard, Duncan. 2022. Quasi-Fideism and Epistemic Relativism. Inquiry, 1–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pritchard, Duncan. Forthcoming. Quasi-fideism and Virtuous Anti-evidentialism: Wittgenstein and Newman on Knowledge and Certainty. In Newman and Contemporary Philosophy. Edited by Joseph Milburn and Frederick Aquino. London: Routledge.
- Stroll, Avrum. 2002. Understanding on Certainty: Entry 194. In Wittgenstein and the Future of Philosophy. Edited by Rudolf Haller and Klaus Puhl. Vienna: oebvhpt, pp. 446–56. [Google Scholar]
- Svensson, Gunnar. 1981. On Doubting the Reality of Reality: Moore and Wittgenstein on Sceptical Doubts. Stockholm: Almqvist & Wiksell. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1997. On Certainty, amended 1st ed. Edited by G. E. M. Anscombe and Georg Henrik von Wright. Translated by Denis Paul, and G. E. M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Moyal-Sharrock, D. The ‘Local’ Nature of Religious Hinges and the Problem of ‘Honest Doubt’. Religions 2025, 16, 1185. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16091185
Moyal-Sharrock D. The ‘Local’ Nature of Religious Hinges and the Problem of ‘Honest Doubt’. Religions. 2025; 16(9):1185. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16091185
Chicago/Turabian StyleMoyal-Sharrock, Daniele. 2025. "The ‘Local’ Nature of Religious Hinges and the Problem of ‘Honest Doubt’" Religions 16, no. 9: 1185. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16091185
APA StyleMoyal-Sharrock, D. (2025). The ‘Local’ Nature of Religious Hinges and the Problem of ‘Honest Doubt’. Religions, 16(9), 1185. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16091185